Routledge Handbook of
Public Policy
This Handbook provides a comprehensive global survey of the policy process. Written by an
outstanding line-up of distinguished scholars and practitioners, the Handbook covers all aspects of
the policy process including:
theory from rational choice to the new institutionalism
frameworks network theory, the advocacy coalition framework, punctuated equilibrium
models and institutional analysis and development theory
key stages in the process agenda-setting, formulation, decision-making, implementation
and evaluation
the roles of key actors and institutions
policy learning and policy dynamics from path dependency to process sequencing
This is an invaluable resource for all scholars, graduate students and practitioners in public policy
and policy analysis.
Eduardo Araral Jr. is Assistant Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy,
National University of Singapore.
Scott Fritzen is Associate Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy, National
University of Singapore.
Michael Howlett is Burnaby Mountain Chair in the Department of Political Science at Simon
Fraser University, Vancouver, Canada.
M Ramesh is Chair Professor of Govenance and Public Policy at the Hong Kong Institute of
Education and Visiting Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy, National
University of Singapore.
Xun Wu is Associate Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy, National University
of Singapore.
Routledge Handbook of
Public Policy
Edited by
Eduardo Araral Jr.
Scott Fritzen
Michael Howlett
M Ramesh
Xun Wu
First published 2013
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2013 selection and editorial matter, E. Araral Jr., S. Fritzen, M. Howlett, M. Ramesh, X.
Wu; individual chapters, the contributors
The right of E. Araral Jr., S. Fritzen, M. Howlett, M. Ramesh, X. Wu to be identied as
editors of this work has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and
Patent Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any
form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented,
including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system,
without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and
are used only for identication and explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Routledge Handbook of Public Policy / edited by E. Araral ... [et al.].
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
1. Policy sciences. I. Araral, Eduardo II. Title: Handbook of Public Policy.
H97.R68 2013
320.6dc23
2012008846
ISBN: 978-0-415-78245-6 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-0-203-09757-1 (ebk)
Typeset in Bembo
by Taylor & Francis Books
Contents
List of illustrations ix
List of contributors xi
PART I
Introduction to the study of the public policy process: history
and method 1
1 Public policy debate and the rise of policy analysis
3
Michael Mintrom and Claire Williams
2 The policy-making process
17
Michael Howlett and Sarah Giest
3 Comparative approaches to the study of public policy-making
29
Sophie Schmitt
4 International dimensions and dynamics of policy-making
44
Anthony Perl
PART II
Conceptualizing public policy-making 57
5 State theory and the rise of the regulatory state
59
Darryl S.L. Jarvis
6 The public choice perspective
76
Andy Whitford
7 Institutional analysis and political economy
87
Michael D. McGinnis and Paul Dragos Aligica
8 Postpositivism and the policy process
98
Raul Perez Lejano
v
PART III
Modelling the policy process: frameworks for analysis 113
9 The institutional analysis and development framework
115
Ruth Schuyler House and Eduardo Araral Jr.
10 The advocacy coalition framework: coalitions, learning and policy change
125
Christopher M. Weible and Daniel Nohrstedt
11 The punctuated equilibrium theory of agenda-setting and policy change
138
Graeme Boushey
12 Policy network models
153
Chen-Yu Wu and David Knoke
PART IV
Understanding the agenda-setting process 165
13 Policy agenda-setting studies: attention, politics and the public
167
Christoer Green-Pedersen and Peter B. Mortensen
14 Focusing events and policy windows
175
Thomas A. Birkland and Sarah E. DeYoung
15 Agenda-setting and political discourse: major analytical frameworks and
their application
189
David A. Rochefort and Kevin P. Donnelly
16 Mass media and policy-making
204
Stuart Soroka, Stephen Farnsworth, Andrea Lawlor and Lori Young
PART V
Understanding the formulation process 215
17 Policy design and transfer
217
Anne Schneider
18 Epistemic communities
229
Claire A. Dunlop
19 Policy appraisal
244
John Turnpenny, Camilla Adelle and Andrew Jordan
Contents
vi
20 Policy analytical styles 255
Igor S. Mayer, C. Els van Daalen and Pieter W.G. Bots
PART VI
Understanding the decision-making process 271
21 Bounded rationality and public policy decision-making
273
Bryan D. Jones and H.F. Thomas III
22 Incrementalism
287
Michael Hayes
23 Models for research into decision-making processes: on phases, streams,
rounds and tracks of decision-making
299
Geert R. Teisman and Arwin van Buuren
24 The garbage can model and the study of the policy-making process
320
Gary Mucciaroni
PART VII
Understanding the implementation process 329
25 Bureaucracy and the policy process
331
Ora-orn Poocharoen
26 Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution in the policy process
347
Boyd Fuller
27 Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
361
Robert Agrano, Michael McGuire and Chris Silvia
28 Development management and policy implementation: relevance beyond
the global South
374
Derick W. Brinkerho and Jennifer M. Brinkerho
PART VIII
Understanding the evaluation process 385
29 Six models of evaluation
387
Evert Vedung
30 Policy feedback and learning
401
Patrik Marier
Contents
vii
31 Randomized control trials: what are they, why are they promoted as the
gold standard for casual identication and what can they (not) tell us?
415
David Fuente and Dale Whittington
32 Policy evaluation and public participation
434
Carolyn M. Hendriks
PART IX
Policy dynamics: patterns of stability and change 449
33 Policy dynamics and change: the never-ending puzzle
451
Giliberto Capano
34 Policy trajectories and legacies: path dependency revisited
462
Adrian Kay
35 Process sequencing
473
Carsten Daugbjerg
36 Learning from success and failure?
484
Allan McConnell
Author index
495
Subject index 510
Contents
viii
Illustrations
Figures
9.1 A framework for institutional analysis 118
10.1 Flow diagram of the advocacy coalition framework 128
11.1 Incremental and punctuated policy change distributions 148
14.1 Comparative attention to terrorism 180
14.2 Dominant problem frames in school violence, by venue 182
16.1 Coverage of natural disasters/weather and pollution/climate change by year 210
18.1 Bibliographic analysis of 638 articles, book chapters and books citing Haass
1992 introductory article to the IO special edition 231
18.2 Bibliographic analysis of 638 articles, book chapters and books citing Haass
1992 introductory article to the IO special edition (subject areas receiving 11
citations or more) 232
20.1 Policy analysis tasks 258
20.2 Policy analysis styles 259
20.3 The underlying values and criteria of policy analysis 262
20.4 Overview of the complete hexagon model of policy analysis 266
23.1 A depiction of four models for the analysis of decision-making processes 302
23.2 The concept of decision-making used in the phase model 304
23.3 The concept of decision-making used in the stream model 305
23.4 The concept of decision-making used in the rounds model 306
23.5 The concept of decision-making used in the tracks model 307
29.1 Goal-attainment model 389
29.2 Side-eects model with specied pigeonholes for side-eects 391
29.3 Potential stakeholders in local social welfare interventions 395
Tables
2.1 A taxonomy of substantive policy instruments 22
2.2 A resource-based taxonomy of procedural policy instruments 23
3.1 Subdisciplines of comparative public policy research 38
4.1 Supranational governance dynamics 52
5.1 General approaches to political phenomena and illustrative theoretical examples 60
5.2 A comparative typology of the interventionist and regulatory state 68
14.1 The substance of the agenda when events are or are not mentioned in testimony 181
14.2 Key issues addressed in aviation security legislation 183
ix
16.1 Coverage of natural disasters/weather and pollution/climate change 211
20.1 Positive and negative images of the policy analyst 265
22.1 Four quadrants of policy change 289
22.2 A typology of decision environments 291
23.1 Comparative perspectives on the phase model, the stream model and the
rounds model 308
23.2 Events in decision-making on the Betuwe line and a fourfold research result 314
28.1 Competing perspectives on development management 378
36.1 The three realms of policy success 488
Box
20.1 Translation of values into quality criteria 264
List of illustrations
x
Contributors
Camilla Adelle is a Senior Research Associate in the Science, Society and Sustainability Research
Group, School of Environmental Sciences, University of East Anglia, Norwich, UK.
Robert Agrano is an Emeritus Professor in the School of Public and Environmental Aairs,
Indiana University, Bloomington, USA and Catedrático in the Government and Public
Administration Program, Instituto Universitario Ortega y Gasset, Madrid, Spain. He joined
Indiana University in 1980 from Northern Illinois University and started at Ortega y Gasset in
1990. He continues to be professionally active, specializing in public administration, inter-
governmental relations and management, and public network studies.
Paul Dragos Aligica is a Senior Research Fellow at the Mercatus Center, a Senior Fellow on
the F.A. Hayek Program for Advanced Study in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, a Faculty
Fellow at the James Buchanan Center for Political Economy at George Mason University,
USA, and an Adjunct Fellow at the Hudson Institute, Washington DC, USA. He studies
institutional analysis and institutional theory.
Eduardo Araral Jr. is an Assistant Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public
Policy, National University of Singapore. He is interested in the study of institutions for
collective action from local to international levels and covering a variety of areas from the
commons, international security, climate adaptation, bureaucracy and aid and water resources
management.
Thomas A. Birkland is William T. Kretzer Distinguished Professor at the School of
International and Public Aairs, North Carolina State University, USA where he teaches
courses on the public policy process, environmental politics and policy, and disaster policy
and management. His research has focused on how and to what extent major focusing
events inuence policy agendas. His current research seeks to connect focusing events and
policy failure to policy change and learning. He is the author of An Introduction to the Policy
Process (2nd edn, M.E. Sharpe), and After Disaster and Lessons of Disaster (both Georgetown
University Press), and is co-editor with Todd Schaefer of The Encyclopedia of Mass Media
(CQ Press).
Pieter Bots is an Associate Professor in the Faculty of Technology, Policy and Management
(TPM), Delft University of Technology, Netherlands. His expertise lies mainly in conceptual
models and computer-based tools to support problem formulation and multi-actor systems
analysis, preferably in combination with serious gaming/simulation.
xi
Graeme Boushey is an Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science at the Uni-
versity of California, Irvine, USA, where he teaches courses in American politics, Californian
and state politics, public policy, and research methodology. His research focuses on public
policy processes and political decision-making in American federalism. His teaching and research
are organized around practical and theoretical questions of state and federal policy-making.
Derick W. Brinkerho is a Distinguished Fellow in International Public Management, at the
Research Triangle Institute and has more than 30 years of experience with public management
issues in developing and transitioning countries, focusing on policy analysis, programme imple-
mentation and evaluation, participation, institutional development, democratic governance, and
change management. He is co-editor of the journal Public Administration and Development, and
serves on the editorial boards of Public Administration Review and International Review of Adminis-
trative Sciences. He also holds an associate faculty appointment at the Trachtenberg School of
Public Policy and Public Administration, George Washington University, USA.
Jennifer M. Brinkerho is Professor of Public Administration and International Aairs and
Co-Director, GW Diaspora Program at the Elliott School of International Aairs at George
Washington University, USA. She teaches courses on public service, international development
policy and administration, development management and organizational behaviour. She is par-
ticularly keen on encouraging people to pursue service careers thoughtfully, grounding their
commitment to change in self-awareness and working in community. She is the author
of Digital Diasporas: Identity and Transnational Engagement (Cambridge University Press, 2009)
and Partnership for International Development: Rhetoric or Results? (Lynne Rienner, 2002); the
editor of Diasporas and Development: Exploring the Potential (Lynne Rienner, 2008); and co-editor
of NGOs and the Millennium Development Goals: Citizen Action to Reduce Poverty (Palgrave
Macmillan, 2007).
Giliberto Capano is Professor of Political Science and Public Policy at the University of
Bologna, Italy. He specializes in comparative higher education, public administration and the-
ories of policy-making. He has recently edited (with Elisabetta Gualmini) La Pubblica amminis-
trazione in Italy (Il Mulino, 2011) and European and North American Policy Change (Routledge,
2009) with Michael Howlett.
Carsten Daugbjerg is a Professor at the Institute of Food and Resource Economics, University
of Copenhagen, Denmark. His research area is comparative public policy with a particular
interest in historical institutitionalism, policy networks, policy instruments and ideas in public
policy. His empirical research has focused on agricultural policy reform, trade negotiations in
the World Trade Organization, global food regulation, government interest group relations and
environmental policy.
Sarah E. DeYoung is a doctoral student at North Carolina State University, USA, in the
Psychology in the Public Interest programme. Her research interests are disaster policy and
community disaster preparedness.
Kevin P. Donnelly is Assistant Professor of Political Science and Public Administration at
Bridgewater State University, USA. His previous work includes Foreign Remedies: What the
Experience of Other Nations Can Tell Us about Next Steps in Reforming U.S. Health Care (2012),
co-authored with David A. Rochefort.
List of contributors
xii
Claire A. Dunlop teaches politics and administration at the University of Exeter, UK. Pre-
viously she worked for the Scottish Consumer Council and the Scottish Executive. She has worked
and published widely on issues related to knowledge use in governments and policy appraisal.
Her recent work has appeared in Political Studies, Public Management Review and Regulation and
Governance.
Stephen J. Farnsworth is Professor of Political Science and International Aairs at the George
Washington University, USA, where he directs the universitys Center for Leadership and
Media Studies. He is the author or co-author of four books on media and politics and a former
Fulbright Scholar at McGill University, Canada.
David Fuente is a PhD student in the Department of City and Regional Planning at the
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA.
Boyd Fuller is an Assistant Professor in the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy at the
National University of Singapore. His research focuses on the resolution of dicult water,
environmental and land conicts when stakeholders have apparently irreconcilable dierences in
values, identities or culture. He is currently researching the use of traditional and innovative
dispute resolution techniques for public disputes in post-conict areas of Southeast Asia. His
previous research examined the mediation of intractable environmental conicts in the United
States. He has eight years experience designing and implementing water supply projects in
developing countries.
Sarah Giest is a PhD student in the Department of Political Science at Simon Fraser University
in Burnaby, BC, Canada. She works on innovation systems and networks with special reference to
comparative biotechnology clusters.
Christoer Green-Pedersen is Professor of Political Science at Aarhus University, Denmark.
His research focuses on agenda-setting dynamics and party competition.
Michael Hayes is Professor of Political Science at Colgate University, USA, specializing in
interest group theory, incrementalism and policymaking, eects of public opinion on the
legislative process. He has taught at Lawrence University and Rutgers University and pub-
lished Incrementalism and Public Policy; Lobbyists and Legislators; various book chapters and
articles (Journal of Politics, Polity) on the inuence of interest groups and public opinion on
policy-making.
Carolyn M. Hendrikss work examines the democratic practices of contemporary governance,
particularly with respect to public deliberation, inclusion and political representation. She
has taught and published widely on the application and politics of inclusive and deliberative
forms of citizen engagement. With a background in both political science and environmental
engineering, Carolyn has a particular interest in the governance of the environment, as well as
science and technology issues. She has recently published a book on the practice of delib-
erative democracy entitled The Politics of Public Deliberation: Citizen Engagement and Interest
Advocacy (Palgrave Macmillan, 2011).
Ruth Schuyler House is a PhD student in the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy at the
National University of Singapore. Her research concentrates on the elds of water and
List of contributors
xiii
sanitation policy. She is also interested in the changing face of governance and emerging
opportunities for the private sector to assume responsibility for and lend valuable knowledge
and resources to addressing poverty alleviation.
Michael Howlett is Burnaby Mountain Professor in the Department of Political Science at
Simon Fraser University in Vancouver, Canada. He has published widely, most recently
Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments (Routledge, 2011) and is co-editing with David
Laycock Regulating Next Generation Agri-Food Biotechnologies, Lessons from European, North Amer-
ican and Asian Experiences (Routledge, 2012)
Darryl S.L. Jarvis is Vice-Dean of Academic Aairs and Associate Professor at the Lee Kuan
Yew School of Public Policy, National University of Singapore and specializes in risk analysis
and the study of political and economic risk in Asia, including investment, regulatory and
institutional risk analysis. He has been a consultant to various government bodies and business
organizations, and for two years was a member of the investigating team and then chief
researcher on the Building Institutional Capacity in Asia (BICA) project commissioned by the
Japanese Ministry of Finance.
Bryan D. Joness research interests centre on the study of public policy processes, American
governing institutions, and the connection between human decision-making and organizational
behaviour. Before joining the Department of Government at the University of Texas, Austin,
USA, in 2008, Professor Jones was the Donald R. Matthews Distinguished Professor of Amer-
ican Politics at the University of Washington. Previously, he was Distinguished Professor and head
of department at Texas A&M University, and also taught at Wayne State University. His books
include Politics and the Architecture of Choice (2001) and Reconceiving Decision-Making in Democratic
Politics (1994), both winners of the APSA Political Psychology Section Robert Lane Award; The
Politics of Attention (co-authored with Frank Baumgartner, 2005); Agendas and Instability in
American Politics (co-authored with Frank Baumgartner, 1993), winner of the 2001 Aaron
Wildavsky Award for Enduring Contribution to the Study of Public Policy of the American
Political Science Associations Public Policy Section and The Politics of Bad Ideas (co-authored
with Walt Williams).
Andrew Jordan is Professor of Environmental Politics at the University of East Anglia, Nor-
wich, UK. He is interested in the governance of environmental problems in many dierent
contexts, but especially that of the European Union.
Adrian Kay is an Associate Professor in the Crawford School at the Australian National Uni-
versity and Director of its Policy and Governance Program. His current research interests are in
the relationships between international and domestic policy processes, with a particular empiri-
cal focus on health and agriculture.
David Knoke is a Professor in the Department of Sociology at University of Minnesota, USA,
where he teaches a graduate network analysis seminar that attracts students from diverse dis-
ciplines. He co-authored Network Analysis (1982) and has published 15 books and more than
100 articles and book chapters, primarily on organizations, networks, politics and social statistics.
He was principal co-investigator on several National Science Foundation-funded projects on
voluntary associations, lobbying organizations in national policy domains, and organizational
surveys of diverse establishments.
List of contributors
xiv
Andrea Lawlor is a PhD student the Department of Political Science McGill University, Canada
specializing in media and public policy. Other research interests include political parties, party
nancing and Quebec politics. Her research can be found in Canadian Public Administration.
Raul Perez Lejano is an Associate Professor of Planning, Policy and Design in the School of
Social Ecology at the University of California, Irvine, USA. His research is currently in envir-
onmental planning, new decision models for explaining non-state/non-market institutions,
relational models of collective action, planning theory, institutional models of care and justice
research.
Patrik Marier holds a Tier-II Canada Research Chair (CRC) in Comparative Public Policy. His
research focuses broadly on the impact of changing demographic structures on reforms to the
welfare state in comparative contexts. His earlier work examined the politics of pension reform in
a number of countries including Sweden, Canada, Mexico and the United States. His current
research looks more broadly at the impact of ageing populations on a number of public policy
elds including education, health care and labour policy across comparative cases.
Igor S. Mayer is a Senior Associate Professor in the Faculty of Technology, Policy and Man-
agement (TPM) at Delft University of Technology, Netherlands. He is also the director of the
TU-Delft Centre for Serious Gaming.
Allan McConnell is Professor in the Department of Government and International Relations,
University of Sydney, Australia. He has published extensively on policy and political issues
surrounding crises, disasters, failures and ascoes, as well as the more upbeat topic of policy success.
Michael D. McGinnis is Professor and Director of Graduate Studies in the Department of
Political Science at Indiana University, Bloomington, USA. He studies the unique contributions
that faith-based organizations make to the design and implementation of public policy related to
humanitarian relief, development assistance, peace-building and reconciliation in troubled
regions of the world, as well as standard public services in education, health care and welfare
assistance in societies less directly challenged by the ravages of war.
Michael McGuire is Professor in the School of Public and Environmental Aairs, Indiana
University, Bloomington, USA. He works on intergovernmental and interorganizational colla-
boration and networks and has published widely on public management topics. His recent
publications on the subject have appeared in Public Administration Review and Public Administra-
tion among others.
Michael Mintrom is Professor of Public Sector Management at Monash University and the
Australia and New Zealand School of Government. He is the author of Contemporary Policy
Analysis (Oxford University Press, 2012), People Skills for Policy Analysts (Georgetown University
Press, 2003), and Policy Entrepreneurs and School Choice (Georgetown University Press, 2000).
Peter B. Mortensen is Associate Professor of Political Science at Aarhus University. His
research focuses on agenda-setting and public policy.
Gary Mucciaroni is a member of the Political Science Department at Temple University,
USA and was Department Chair between 2005 and 2010. The focus of his research and
List of contributors
xv
publication is the politics of public policy-making in the United States examining the forces
and actors that impinge upon the policy choices of government. He has published The Political
Failure of Employment Policy, 19451982, Reversals of Fortune: Private Interests and Public Policy,
Deliberative Choices: Debating Public Policy in Congress and Same Sex, Dierent Politics: Issues and
Institutions in the Struggle for Gay and Lesbian Rights.
Daniel Nohrstedt is an Associate Professor of Political Science at the Department of Gov-
ernment, Uppsala University, Sweden. His research is primarily focused on crisis and learning,
intelligence issues, counter-terrorism policy and the public policy process.
Anthony Perl is Professor and Director of the Urban Studies Program and a member of the
Department of Political Science at Simon Fraser University in Vancouver, Canada. His current
research crosses disciplinary and national boundaries to explore the policy decisions that aect
transportation, cities and the environment. His latest book, co-authored with Richard Gilbert,
is Transport Revolutions: Moving People and Freight Without Oil published by New Society Pub-
lishers in 2010.
Ora-orn Poocharoen is an Assistant Professor at the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy
at the National University of Singapore. Her research interests include public management
reform, public administration theory, organization theory, comparative public administration
and public policy analysis.
David A. Rochefort is Arts and Sciences Distinguished Professor of Political Science at
Northeastern University, USA. His previous works include Foreign Remedies: What the Experience
of Other Nations Can Tell Us about Next Steps in Reforming U.S. Health Care (2012), written with
Kevin P. Donnelly, and co-editor with Roger W. Cobb of The Politics of Problem Denition (1994),
among other titles.
Sophie Schmitt is an Assistant Professor in the Department of Comparative Public Policy
and Administration, University of Konstanz, Germany, and specializes in comparative public
policy with a particular focus on environmental and social policy and regulation. She has
recently published articles in the Journal of European Public Policy and European Integration Online
Papers.
Anne Schneider is a Professor in the School of Justice at the University of Arizona, USA and
specializes in public policy and the role of policy in democracy. She and long-time co-author
Helen Ingram are the authors of Policy Design for Democracy (Kansas University Press), and
Deserving and Entitled (SUNY Press), and The social construction of target populations, American
Political Science Review, June 1993.
Chris Silvia looks at interorganizational approaches to service delivery through the lens of
emergency management. His research aims to help public managers, who are more accustomed
to leading in hierarchical organizations, successfully contribute to leading networks. His recent
research has appeared in Journal of Public Aairs Education, State and Local Government Review and
Public Administration Review.
Stuart Soroka is an Associate Professor in the Department of Political Sciences, McGill University,
Montreal, Canada.
List of contributors
xvi
Geert R. Teisman is currently Professor of Public Administration and Complex Decision
Making and Process Management at the Erasmus University Rotterdam, Netherlands, and was
previously Professor of Spatial Planning at the University of Nijmegen. He is member of the
board of Habiforum, a joint venture between science, private sector and public authorities which
explores possibilities of multiple land use. He is Scientic Director of Living with Water, a
foundation which governs a variety of projects in which water system improvement is one of its
important aims. He is member of the executive board of Netlipse, a European knowledge
exchange network in the eld of infrastructure project management. He regularly advises gov-
ernments and private organizations on complex decision-making, strategic planning, public-
private partnerships, process management, intergovernmental co-operation in metropolitan areas
and policy evaluation.
H.F. Thomas III is a PhD student at Pennsylvania State University, USA, working on information,
science and technology policy issues.
John Turnpenny is a Senior Research Associate at the University of East Anglia, Norwich, UK.
His research focuses on the relationship between science, evidence and public policy-making.
Arwin van Buuren is an Associate Professor at the Department of Public Administration at
the Erasmus University Rotterdam, Netherlands. His research focuses on the domain of
water and climate governance. He is especially interested in the way in which complex
governance processes are organized and how the relationship between knowledge and govern-
ance can be optimized. He combines fundamental with applied research. His recent articles
have been published in International Journal of Project Management, International Journal of Public
Management, Public Management Review, Climatic Change and Environmental Impact Assessment
Review.
Els van Daalen is an Associate Professor at the Faculty of Technology, Policy and Manage-
ment (TPM), Delft University of Technology, Netherlands. Her research interests include
system dynamics modelling and the use of models in policy-making.
Evert Vedung is an Emeritus Professor of Political Science and a specialist in housing policy at
Uppsala University, Sweden. He has held posts at Mälardalen University College and the
University of Uppsala. He has been a board member of the Swedish Evaluation Society since its
foundation.
Christopher M. Weible is an Assistant Professor in the School of Public Aairs at the Uni-
versity of Colorado Denver, USA. He teaches courses in environmental policy and politics,
public policy, policy processes, policy analysis, and research methods and design. His area of
research is in policy change, learning, political behaviour, coalitions and networks, institutions and
collective action, collaborative governance, and the role of scientic and technical information
in the policy process.
Andy Whitford is a Professor of Public Administration and Policy in the School of Public and
International Aairs at the University of Georgia, USA. He concentrates on research and
teaching in organizational studies and public policy, with specic interest in organization theory,
models of decision-making and adaptation, and the political control of the bureaucracy. His
interests in public policy include environmental, regulation and public health policy. He has
List of contributors
xvii
particularly strong interest in the use of simulation and experimental methods for understanding
organizational behaviour and individual choice.
Dale Whittington is a Professor of Environmental Sciences and Engineering, City and
Regional Planning, and Public Policy, at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill,
USA. Since 1986 he has worked for the World Bank and other international agencies on the
development and application of techniques for estimating the economic value of environmental
resources in developing countries, with a particular focus on water and sanitation and vaccine
policy issues.
Claire Williams is a policy advisor at Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand. She
has previously published in Policy and Society.
Chen-Yu Wu is a graduate student in the Department of Sociology at the University of
Minnesota, USA, and was a Teaching Assistant for the courses Introduction to Sociology and
Basic Social Statistics.
Lori Young is a PhD student in the Annenberg School of Communication at the University of
Pennsylvania, USA. Her published work includes studies of foreign news reporting in Canada
and the United States and has appeared in journals such as The International Journal of Press/Pol-
itics.
List of contributors
xviii
Part I
Introduction to the study of
the public policy process
History and method
1
Public policy debate and the rise
of policy analysis
Michael Mintrom and Claire Williams
Since the mid-1960s, an increasingly large number of people, trained in the humanities and
social sciences, have come to devote their professional lives to producing policy advice. This is a
global phenomenon, although until recently the intensication of activities associated with
policy advising has been most pronounced in the United States. As government demand for
well-trained policy analysts and advisors has risen, universities have sought to provide relevant
graduate-level training.
The rise of policy analysis is usefully construed as a movement. Use of this term implies a
deliberate eort on the part of many people to reconceive the role of government in society
and renegotiate aspects of the relationships that exist between individuals, collectivities and
governments. However, the claim that there is a policy analysis movement should not be taken
to imply either consistency of purpose or a deliberate striving for coordination among producers
of policy analysis. While not directly comparable in a political sense with other social movements,
the policy analysis movement has been highly inuential. It has served to transform the advice-
giving systems of governments, altered the nature of policy debate, and, as a consequence,
challenged informal yet long-established advising practices through which power and inuence
ow. The profundity of this transformation has often eluded the attention of social and political
commentators. That is because the relevant changes have caused few immediate or obvious rup-
tures in the processes and administrative structures typically associated with government or,
more broadly speaking, public governance.
Early representations of policy analysis tended to cast it as a subset of policy advising. As such,
policy analysis was seen primarily as an activity conducted inside government agencies with the
purpose of informing the choices of a few key people, principally elected decision-makers
(Lindblom 1968; Wildavsky 1979). Today, the potential purposes of policy analysis are under-
stood to be much broader. Many more audiences are seen as holding interests in policy and as
being open to indeed demanding of appropriately presented analytical work (Radin 2000).
Beyond people in government, people in business, members of non-prot organizations, and
informed citizens all constitute audiences for policy analysis. While policy analysts were once
thought to be mainly located within government agencies, today policy analysts also can be found
in most organizations that have direct dealings with governments, and in many organizations
where government actions signicantly inuence the operating environment. In addition, many
3
university-based researchers, who tend to treat their peers and their students as their primary
audience, conduct studies that ask questions about government policies and that answer them
using forms of policy analysis. Given this, an appropriately encompassing denition of con-
temporary policy analysis needs to recognize the range of topics and issue areas policy analysts
work on, the range of analytical and research strategies they employ, and the range of audiences
they seek to address. In recognizing the contemporary breadth of applications and styles of
policy analysis, it becomes clear that eective policy analysis calls for not only the application of
sound technical skills (Mintrom 2012), but also deep substantive knowledge, political percep-
tiveness and well-developed interpersonal skills (Mintrom 2003). Although producing high-
quality, reliable advice remains a core expectation for many policy analysts, advising now
appears as a subset of the broader policy analysis category. The transition from policy analysis as
a subset of advising to advising as a subset of analysis represents a signicant shift in orientation
and priorities from earlier times.
In what follows, we rst review the sources of increasing demand for policy analysis. We then
review the growth and adaptation in the supply of policy analysis that has occurred in response
to this demand. We conclude by discussing the current state of public policy debate and the
likely future trajectory of both the practice of policy advising and the training of policy analysts.
Throughout, we take the United States as our main point of reference. However, we have also
sought to demonstrate the comparative relevance of our argument. We have done this by discussing
the international embrace of New Public Management orthodoxy (from the late 1970s to the
mid-1990s) and government responses to the global nancial crisis (from 2007 into 2012).
Before proceeding, it is useful to dene terms. For the purposes of this discussion, public policies
are considered to be any actions taken by governments that represent previously agreed responses
to specied circumstances. Governments design public policies with the broad purpose of
expanding the public good (Howlett 2011; Mintrom 2012). Policy studies refers to research on
policy topics and analytical work conducted primarily by university-based researchers with the
goal of critically assessing past, present and proposed policy settings. Policy studies can be under-
taken by researchers in many disciplinary or cross-disciplinary settings. They can draw upon a
range of analytical and interpretative methodologies. Policy studies may be historical and com-
parative in their scope. The term policy sciences refers to the subset of analytical techniques
devised in the social sciences that have been applied to understanding the design, implementa-
tion and evaluation of public policies. Policy analysis is here discussed as work intended to
advance knowledge of the causes of public problems, alternative approaches to addressing them,
the likely impacts of those alternatives, and trade-os that might emerge when considering appro-
priate governmental responses to those public problems. Policy advising is dened here as the
practice of providing information to decision-makers in government, with the intention of
improving the base of knowledge upon which decisions are made. While policy advising need
not be based upon rigorous policy analysis, over recent decades such policy analysis has come to
play a more central part in the development of advice for decision-makers.
The evolving demand for policy analysis
Demand for policy analysis has been driven mostly by the emergence of problems and by
political conditions that have made those problems salient. Early in the development of policy
analysis techniques, the people who identied the problems that needed to be addressed tended
to be government ocials. They turned to academics for help. Frequently, those academics
deemed to be most useful, given the problems at hand, were economists with strong technical
skills, who had the ability to estimate the magnitude of problems, undertake statistical analyses,
Mintrom and Williams
4
and determine the costs of various government actions. During the twentieth century, as transpor-
tation, electrication and telecommunications opened up new opportunities for market exchange,
problems associated with decentralized decision-making became more apparent (McCraw 1984).
Meanwhile, as awareness grew of the causes of many natural and social phenomena, calls emerged
for governments to establish mechanisms that might eectively manage various natural and
social processes. Many matters once treated as social conditions, or facts of life to be suered,
were transformed into policy problems (Cobb and Elder 1983). Together, the increasing scope
of the marketplace, the increasing complexity of social interactions, and expanding knowledge
of social conditions created pressures from a variety of quarters for governments to take the lead
in structuring and regulating individual and collective action. Tools of policy analysis, such as
the analysis of market failures and the identication of feasible government responses, were devel-
oped to guide this expanding scope of government. Yet as the reach of policy analysis grew,
questions were raised about the biases inherent in some of the analytical tools being applied. In
response, new eorts were made to account for the eects of policy changes, and new voices
began to contribute in signicant ways to policy development. To explore the factors prompt-
ing demand for policy analysis, it is useful to work with a model of the policy-making process.
A number of conceptions of policy-making have been developed in recent decades. Here, we
apply the stages model, where ve stages are typically posited: problem denition, agenda setting,
policy adoption, implementation, and evaluation (Eyestone 1978).
Initial demands for policy analysis were prompted by growing awareness of problems that
governments could potentially address. Questions inevitably arose concerning the appropriateness
of alternative policy solutions. Thus, in the United States in the 1930s, as the federal government
took on major new roles in the areas of regulation, redistribution and the nancing of infra-
structural development, the need arose for high quality policy analysis. With respect to regulatory
policy, concerns about the threat to the railroads of the emerging trucking industry prompted
the expansion of the Interstate Commerce Commission (Eisner 1993). This body employed lawyers
and economists who helped to devise an expanding set of regulations that eventually covered
many industries. Although the American welfare state has always been limited compared with
welfare states elsewhere, especially those within Europe, its development still required concerted
policy analysis and development work on the part of a cadre of bureaucrats (Derthick 1979).
Initially, much of the talent needed to ll these positions was drawn from states like Wisconsin,
where welfare policies had been pioneered by Robert LaFollette. As the role of the United States
government in redistribution expanded, policy analysts swelled the ranks of career bureaucrats in
the Treasury, the Oce of Management and Budget, and the Department of Health and Human
Services. Meanwhile, benet-cost analysis, a cornerstone of modern policy analysis and a core
component of public economics, was developed to help in the planning of dam construction in
the Tennessee Valley in the 1930s. Politicians at the time worried that some dams were being
built mainly to perpetuate the ow of cash to construction companies rather than to meet growing
demand for electricity and ood control (Eckstein 1958). The broad applicability of the tech-
nique soon became clear and its use has continually expanded. At the same time, eorts to improve
the sophistication of the technique, and to develop variations on it that are best suited to dierent
sets of circumstances have also continued to occur (Boardman et al. 2006; Carlson 2011).
Several features of policy development, the politics of agenda setting, and the policymaking
process have served over time to increase demand for policy analysts. The dynamics at work
have been similar to those through which an arms race generates ongoing and often expanding
demand for military procurements. In Washington, DC, the growing population of policy analysts
employed in the federal government bureaucracy led to demand elsewhere around town for
policy analysts who could verify or contest the analysis and advice emanating from government
Public policy debate
5
agencies. A classic example is given by the creation of the Congressional Budget Oce (CBO).
This oce was established as an independent resource for Congress that would generate analysis
and advice as a check on the veracity of the analyses prepared and disseminated by the execu-
tive-controlled Oce of Management and Budget (Wildavsky 1992). The General Accounting
Oce renamed in 2004 the Government Accountability Oce was also developed to
provide independent advice for Congress. The purview of this Oce has always been broader
than that of the Congressional Budget Oce.
As the analytical capabilities available to elected politicians grew, groups of people outside
government but with signicant interests in the direction of government policy began devoting
resources to the production of high-quality, independent advice. Think tanks, like the Brook-
ings Institution and the American Enterprise Institute, established in the 1920s and 1940s
respectively, and both still going strong, represent archetypes of many independent policy shops
now located in Washington, DC (Smith 1991).
Today, due to the knowledge base of think tanks and their entrepreneurial capacity, their
sta and aliates are often regarded as members of a select few who dominate policy. Networks
between non-governmental policy experts and politicians in the United States are strengthened
through appointments into government departments often described as a revolving door”–
in which policy experts frequently move into and out of key positions in the government over
successive presidential elections. Therefore, United States think tanks are often viewed as
trustworthy sources of advice to the administration because of their deep connections, the star
status of some of their people, and their sophisticated inuence eorts.
It is useful to note that the roles, character, and eectiveness of think tanks are shaped by
country-specic institutional and political factors. In the United States, most think tanks tend to
serve both as watch dogs and as idea brokers; how much they exhibit either characteristic
depends largely on their alignment or lack of alignment with the political colours of the current
Administration. In contrast, most think tanks operating in Asian countries tend to view their
role as regime-enhancing (Stone 2000; Stone and Denham 2004; Abelson 2004).
Parliamentary systems, found most conspicuously in Commonwealth countries, tend to
exhibit greater centralization of legislative power and accountability than systems like that of the
United States where the separation of powers is a fundamental characteristic of governance.
Centralization of power gives those in leadership positions greater control over policy. The
electoral system can serve to either enhance or diminish the power that those in government
exercise over policy development. This has been clearly exhibited in the case of New Zealand,
where a switch in 1996 from rst-past-the-post to mixed member proportional representation
in parliament changed the political landscape. Due to the increased diversity and number of
actors in the policy-making process, policy deliberation now tends to be longer and more con-
sultative, requiring greater input from a wider range of political actors and interest groups (Boston
et al. 2003). This change in the electoral system has resulted in greater demand for policy ana-
lysis. The potential for inuence among political parties, members of parliament and interest
groups outside the government has led them to build analytical strengths that had previously
been almost the exclusive preserve of government departments.
The American constitution has an enshrined checks and balances system including a federal
and presidential system which is highly decentralized and fragmented. Establishment of the
Congressional Policy Advisory Board in 1998 has provided a further channel for experts to
share their advice with members of Congress as three-quarters of the policy experts on the
board are from think tanks. Combined with weak parties and considerable employee turnover,
the United States government is open to a host of government and non-government experts
engaging in policy-making (McGann and Johnson 2006).
Mintrom and Williams
6
Although policy analysis is often understood as work that occurs before a new policy or
programme is adopted, demand for policy analysis has also been driven by interest in the
eectiveness of government programmes. The question of what happens once a policy idea has
been adopted and passed into law could be construed as too operational to deserve the attention
of policy analysts. Yet, during the past few decades, elements of implementation have become
recognized as vital for study by policy analysts (Bardach 1977; Lipsky 1984; Pressman and
Wildavsky 1973). In part, this has been led by results of programme evaluations, which have
often found policies not producing their intended outcomes, or worse, creating whole sets of
unintended and negative consequences. One important strain of the work devoted to assessing
implementation has contributed to what is now known as the government failure literature
(Niskanen 1971; Weimer and Vining 2005; Wolf 1979). The possibility that public policies
designed to address market failures might themselves create problems led to a greater respect for
market processes and a degree of scepticism on the part of policy analysts towards the remedial
abilities of government (Rhoads 1985). In turn, this required policy analysts to develop more
nuanced understandings of the workings of particular markets. The government failure litera-
ture has led to greater interest in government eorts to simulate market processes, or to reform
government and contract out aspects of government supply that could be taken up by private
rms operating in the competitive marketplace (Osborne and Gaebler 1993). Where eorts to
reform government have been thorough-going, an interesting dynamic has developed. As the
core public sector has shrunk in size, the number of policy analysts employed in the sector has
increased, both in relative and in absolute terms. This dynamic is indicative of governments devel-
oping their capacities in the management of contracts rather than in the management of services
(Savas 1987). In these new environments, people exhibiting skills in mechanism design and
benet-cost analysis have been in demand. Therefore, employment opportunities for policy ana-
lysts have tended to expand, even as the scope of government has been curtailed. Fiscal con-
servatism, which was a hallmark of governments in many jurisdictions that embraced the New
Public Management practices added to this trend (Yergin and Stanislaw 1998; Williamson 1993).
When budgets are squeezed, it becomes critical for all possible eciency gains to be realized.
More than any other trained professionals, policy analysts working in government are well-
placed to undertake the kind of analytical work needed to identify cost-saving measures and to
persuade elected decision-makers to adopt them.
The exact inuence policy advisors have been able to exert over political decision-makers is
dicult to measure because of the range of factors that inuence policy outcomes. Moreover,
the changing nature of political and institutional environments throughout periods in history
have meant that not only has the denition of policy analyst changed over time but the extent
of their inuence has also uctuated. Windows of opportunity for policy inuence appear
more frequently in some circumstances than in others (Kingdon 1995). For example, the move
towards addressing large national debts led to wide-scale reform of government policy settings
in many jurisdictions during the 1980s and 1990s.
By the 1980s the world had become intensely global: economically, socially and politically.
Global problems often resulted in similar policy outcomes. In New Zealand at that time, poli-
tical leaders became aware that the countrys economic position was deteriorating. Faced with
economic stagnation, social disruption and ideological shifts away from dependence upon gov-
ernment for the allocation of many resources in society, the New Zealand government became
open to the inuence of institutions and agencies with perceived expertise in the dominant
problems of the day (Oliver 1989).
The strength of central agencies, endowed with economic expertise, such as the New Zealand
Treasury and organizations such as the New Zealand Business Round Table (NZBRT), were
Public policy debate
7
intensied by individual networks intertwining ministers with key bureaucrats and non-elected
political actors. Not unlike other countries such as Norway, Sweden, Britain and France, in the
1980s, a single economics ministry in New Zealand meant that there were few opportunities
for countervailing power. The system in New Zealand at that time was thus described by one
commentator as an elective dictatorship (Boston 1989).
In New Zealand the Treasury was the Governments most important advisory body. By
recruiting a senior manager from the Treasury, Roger Kerr, to lead the NZBRT in 1986,
business leaders recognized the value of networks and the strength of the Treasury department
(Mintrom 2006). The NZBRT ensured that the views of business leaders were fully articulated
in policy discussions. The Minister of Finance was reported at the time to have a relationship
with the Round Table that was so close you couldnt slide a Treasury paper between them
(Murray and Pacheco 2001).
The conditions that allowed a few advisors broad inuence over political decision-makers can
partly explain why the economic restructuring undertaken in New Zealand in the 1980s and
1990s was so extensive. As with Reaganism in the United States, and at least the early days of
Thatcherism in Britain, Rogernomics in New Zealand followed a pattern of international
policy transfer which included commercialization, liberalization and deregulation. These ideas
were not new. They began in North America and Europe a decade earlier and represented a
global spread of neo-liberal politics (Dolowitz and Marsh 2000; Heernan 1999).
Over the past few decades, technological advances have improved communication and made
it easier for policy advisers and decision-makers to assess dierent policy decisions, thus increasing
the occurrences of policy transfer. While it is relatively simple to spot broad trends in policy
development, individual countries always exhibit specic, even idiosyncratic, policy design ele-
ments. Liberalization in New Zealand, the United States and Britain during the 1980s and 1990s
included rescission of the existing regulatory regime and a reduction in protectionist legislation
aimed at instituting competitiveness through a free market. In New Zealand, it was carried out
extensively at an unprecedented speed and has largely been unparalleled (Goldnch 1998). In
the United States the focus on monetary policy as a prime instrument to shape the economy
represented a comprehensive change in policies which were up to that time not politically
viable. In contrast, liberalization and deregulation in Britain were not as quick, nor were they a
radical departure from ideas already in train, and were thus seen as more path dependant and
incremental (Niskanen 1988; Heernan 1999).
The global nancial crisis emerged rapidly in mid-2007. This saw governments around the
world intervene in the operation of nancial markets in a manner that would have been
shunned during the 1980s and 1990s. The degree to which public policy settings undergird the
eective workings of markets has become salient again. As a consequence, the current period
has entrenched the pervasive role of government in capitalist societies. At its best, this new era
of policy-making has seen eorts being made to carefully balance responses to market failures
against risks of government failure. At its worst, the new era has oered instances of those who
contributed to the crisis being cushioned, with those most harmed by the crisis receiving no
governmental relief. In short, the current period has opened space for extensive debate about
public policy and the role of government in society. The developmental role of governments in
promoting economic advancement observed most starkly in the Asian tiger economies over
recent decades has been eyed by some observers as a sound prescription, even for the most
advanced economies in the world. Sceptics have been much more concerned about extensive
government interventions into economic activities. Frequent voice has been given to the worry
of government failure exhibited most obviously by special interest capture of government
subsidies.
Mintrom and Williams
8
Discussions during the 1960s and 1970s of the role of policy analysts in society often por-
trayed them as whiz kids or econocrats on a quest to imbue public decision-making with
high degrees of rigour and rationality (Self 1977; Stevens 1993). Certainly, proponents of benet-
cost analysis considered themselves to have a technique for assessing the relative merits of
alternative policy proposals that, on theoretical grounds, trumped any others on oer. Likewise,
proponents of programme evaluation employing quasi-experimental research designs considered
their approach to be superior to other approaches that might be used to determine programme
eectiveness (Cook and Campbell 1979). That the application of both benet-cost analysis and
quantitative evaluation techniques has continued unabated for several decades speaks to their
perceived value for generating usable knowledge. However, the limitations of such techniques
have not been lost on critics. In the case of benet-cost analysis, features of the technique that
make it so appealing such as the reduction of all impacts to a common metric and the cal-
culation of net social benets have also attracted criticism. In response, alternative methods for
assessing the impacts of new policies, such as environmental impact assessments, social impact
assessments and health impact assessments have gained currency (Barrow 2000; Lock 2000; Wood
1995). Similarly, widespread eorts have been made to promote the integration of gender and
race analysis into policy development (Mintrom 2012; Myers 2002; True and Mintrom 2001).
In the case of evaluation studies, fundamental and drawn-out debates have occurred covering
the validity of various research methods and the appropriate scope and purpose of evaluation
eorts. Signicantly for the present discussion, these debates have actually served to expand demand
for policy analysis. Indeed, government agencies designed especially to audit the impacts of
policies on the family, children, women and racial minorities have now been established in
many jurisdictions. Further, evaluation of organizational processes, which often scrutinize the
nature of the interactions between organizations and their clients are now accorded equivalent
status among evaluators as more traditional eorts to measure programme outcomes (Patton
1997; Weiss 1998). Yet these process evaluations are motivated by very dierent questions and
draw upon very dierent methodologies than traditional evaluation studies that assessed programme
impacts narrowly.
This review of the evolving demand for policy analysis has identied several trends that have
served both to embed policy analysts at the core of government operations and to expand
demand for policy analysts both inside and outside government. These trends have much to do
with the growing complexity of economic and social relations and knowledge generation. Yet
there is also a sense in which policy analysis itself generates demand for more policy analysis.
While these trends have been most observable in national capitals, where a large amount of
policy development occurs, they have played out in related ways in other venues as well. For
instance, in federal systems, expanding cadres of well-trained policy analysts have become engaged
in sophisticated, evidence-based policy debates in state and provincial capitals.
Cities, too, are increasingly making extensive use of policy analysts in their strategy and planning
departments. At the global level, key coordinating organizations, such as the World Bank, the
International Monetary Fund, the World Trade Organization, and the Organization for Eco-
nomic Cooperation and Development have made extensive use of the skills of policy analysts to
monitor various transnational developments and national-level activities of particular relevance
and interest.
Today, the demand for policy analysis is considerable, and it comes both from inside and
outside governments. This demand is likely to keep growing as calls emerge for governments to
tackle emerging, unfamiliar problems. On the one hand, we should expect to see ongoing
eorts to harness technical procedures drawn from the social sciences and natural sciences for
the purposes of improving the quality of policy analysis. On the other hand, more people are
Public policy debate
9
likely to apply these techniques, reinvent them, or develop whole new approaches to counteract
them, all with the purpose of gaining greater voice in policy-making at all levels of government
from the local to the global.
The evolving supply of policy analysis
To meet the growing demand for policy analysis, since the mid-1960s supply has greatly
expanded. But this expansion has been accompanied, at least around the edges of the enterprise,
by a transformation in the very nature of the products on oer. Consequently it is now com-
monplace to nd policy analysts who question the questions of the past, who are politically
motivated, or who seek to satisfy intellectual curiosity rather than to oer solutions to immediate
problems. Thus, the apparently straightforward question of what constitutes policy analysis cannot
be addressed in a straightforward manner. Answers given will be highly contingent on context.
For example, an answer oered in the mid-1970s would be narrower in scope than an answer
oered now. Likewise, the question of who produces policy analysis is also contingent. Econ-
omists have always been well represented in the ranks of policy analysts. People from other
disciplines have also contributed to policy analysis, although there has often been a sense that
other disciplines have less to contribute to policy design and the weighing of alternatives.
Today, practitioners and scholars heralding from an array of disciplines are engaged in this kind
of work, and the relevance of disciplines other than economics is well understood. In this review
of the evolving supply of policy analysis, we consider both the development of a mainstream
and the growing diversity of work that now constitutes policy analysis.
There has always been a mainstream style of conducting policy analysis. That style is more
prevalent today than it has ever been. The style is portrayed by practitioners and critics alike as
the application of a basic, yet continually expanding, set of technical practices (Stokey and
Zeckhauser 1978). Most of those practices derive from microeconomic analysis. They include
the analysis of individual choice and trade-os, the analysis of markets and market failure, and the
application of benet-cost analysis. Contemporary policy analysis textbooks tend to build on this
notion of policy analysis as a technical exercise (Bardach 2000; Mintrom 2012; Munger 2000;
Weimer and Vining 2005). For example, in his practical guide to policy analysis, Eugene Bar-
dach (2000) contends that a basic, eightfold approach can be applied to analysing most policy
problems. The approach requires us to dene the problem, assemble some evidence, construct the
alternatives, select the criteria, project the outcomes, confront the trade-os, decide, and tell our
story. As with Stokey and Zeckhausers approach, Bardachs approach clearly derives from
microeconomic analysis, and benet-cost analysis in particular. None of this should surprise us
since, to the extent that a discipline called policy analysis exists at all, it is a discipline that grew
directly out of microeconomic analysis. That disciplinary linkage remains strong. Economists
comprise the majority of members of the United States-based Association for Public Policy Analysis
and Management (APPAM), the largest such association in the world. Likewise, contributions
to the Associations Journal of Policy Analysis and Management are authored predominantly,
although certainly not exclusively, by economists.
Viewed positively, we might note that the basic approach to policy analysis derived from
microeconomics is extremely serviceable. As scholars have continued to apply and expand this
style of analysis, a rich body of technical practices has been created. Extensive eorts have been
made to ensure that university students interested in careers in policy analysis gain appropriate
exposure to these approaches and receive opportunities to apply them. Most Masters pro-
grammes in public policy analysis or public administration require students to take a core set of
courses that expose them to microeconomic analysis, public economics, benet-cost analysis,
Mintrom and Williams
10
descriptive and inferential statistics, and evaluation methods. Sometimes the core is augmented
by courses on topics such as strategic decision-making, the nature of the policy process, and
organizational behaviour. Students are usually also given opportunities to augment their core
course selections with a range of elective courses from several disciplines. Without doubt, gradu-
ates of these programmes emerge well-equipped to immediately begin contributing in useful
ways to the development of public policy. Over recent decades, many universities in the United
States have introduced Masters programmes designed to train policy analysts along the lines
suggested here. More recently, similar programmes have been established in many other coun-
tries around the globe. Those establishing them know that there is strong demand for the kind
of training they seek to provide. These professional courses create opportunities for people who
have already been trained in other disciplines to acquire valuable skills for supporting the devel-
opment of policy analyses. Graduates end up being placed in many organizations in the public,
private and non-prot sectors.
Viewed more negatively, the mainstream approach to teaching and practising policy analysis
can be critiqued for its narrowness and the privileging of techniques derived from economic
theory over analytical approaches that draw upon political and social theory. Suppose we again
describe the policy-making process as a series of stages: problem denition; agenda setting; policy
adoption; implementation; and evaluation. The mainstream approach to policy analysis has little
to contribute to our understanding of agenda setting, or the politics of policy adoption, imple-
mentation and evaluation. Steeped as it is in the rational choice or utilitarian perspective, main-
stream policy analysis is poorly suited to helping us to understand why particular problems
might manifest themselves at given times, why some policy alternatives might appear politically
palatable while others will not, and why adopted policies often go through signicant trans-
formations during the implementation stage. In addition, technical approaches to programme
evaluation, while obviously necessary for guiding the measurement of programme eectiveness,
typically prescribe narrow data collection procedures that can leave highly relevant information
unexamined. Studies that dwell on assessing programme outcomes are unlikely to reveal the
multiple, and perhaps conicting, ways that programme personnel and programme participants
often make sense of programmes. In turn, this might cause analysts to misinterpret the motiva-
tions that lead programme personnel and participants to redene programme goals from those
originally intended by policy-makers. Problems of programme design or programme theory
might end up being ignored in favour of interpretations that place the blame on faulty imple-
mentation (Chen 1990). More generally, mainstream approaches to policy analysis can encou-
rage practitioners to hold tightly to assumptions about individual and collective behaviour that
are contradicted by the evidence. In the worst cases, this can lead to inappropriate specication
of proposals for policy change.
The foregoing observations might cause us to worry that mainstream training in policy ana-
lysis does not suciently equip junior analysts to become reective practitioners or practitioners
who listen closely to the voices of people who are most likely to be aected by policy change
(Forrester 1999; Schön 1983). Certainly, strong critiques of mainstream analytical approaches
have led to some rethinking of the questions that policy analysts should ask when working on
policy problems (Stone 2002). Yet it is a fact that many people who have gone on to become
excellent policy managers and leaders of government agencies began their careers as junior
policy analysts fresh out of mainstream policy programmes. This suggests that, within profes-
sional settings, heavy reliance is placed on mechanisms of tacit knowledge transfer, whereby
narrowly trained junior analysts come to acquire skills and insight that serve them well as policy
managers. Our sense is that the key components of this professional socialization can be codied
and are teachable (Mintrom 2003). But much of what it takes to be an eective policy analyst is
Public policy debate
11
not captured in the curricula of the many university programmes that now exist to train future
practitioners.
Beyond mainstream eorts to expand the supply of policy analysts, all of which place heavy
emphasis on the development of technical skills informed primarily by microeconomic theory,
other disciplines also contribute in signicant ways to the preparation of people who eventually
become engaged in policy analysis. In these cases, the pathway from formal study to the practice
of policy analysis is often circuitous. People with substantive training in law, engineering, natural
sciences and the liberal arts might begin their careers in closely related elds, only to migrate
into policy work later. For example, individuals trained initially as sociologists might gain pro-
fessional qualications as social workers and, after years in the eld, assume managerial roles that
require them to devote most of their energies to policy development. People pursuing these
alternative professional routes towards working as policy analysts can bring rich experiences and
diverse insights to policy discussions. The resulting multidisciplinary contributions to policy
discussions have been known to generate their share of intractable policy controversies (Schön
and Rein 1994). Yet, when disagreements that emerge from dierences in training and analy-
tical perspectives are well managed, these multidisciplinary forums can produce eective policy
design. Indeed, increasing eorts are now being made to address signicant problems through
joined-up government initiatives (Perri 6: 2004). Through these, individuals with diverse profes-
sional backgrounds who are known to have been working on similar problems are brought
together to work out cohesive policy strategies to address those problems. For example, pedia-
tricians, police ocers, social workers and educators might be asked to work together to devise
policies for eective detection and prevention of child abuse.
Two somewhat contradictory trends in the evolving supply of policy analysis have been noted
here. On the one hand, the growth of university-based professional programmes designed to
train policy analysts has contributed to a signicant degree of analytical isomorphism. No matter
which university or country such programmes are based, the students are required to study
much the same set of topics and to read from a growing canon of articles and books covering
aspects of policy analysis. These programmes promote ways of thinking about public policy that
owe heavy debts to the discipline of economics. On the other hand, researchers and practi-
tioners working out of other disciplines have increasingly become involved in the production of
policy analysis. These contributions from outside the mainstream have tended to promote analytical
diversity. Taken together, these contradictory trends dene the contemporary eld of policy
analysis. Often, the dierences are downplayed. For example, while the Journal of Policy Analysis
and Management publishes research articles and shorter pieces on teaching practice, all of which
can be informed by a variety of disciplinary perspectives, the overall impression given is that of a
journal devoted to the furtherance of mainstream methods of policy analysis. In contrast, con-
troversies in the interdisciplinary eld of evaluation studies have left a distinctly dierent
impression. As a result, courses on policy evaluation, when taught in professional public policy
programmes, can introduce perspectives that sit uncomfortably with those taught in other core
courses. Similarly, the eclecticism of contributions to organizational studies can transform other-
wise staid courses on public management and administration into eye-opening explorations of
organizational behaviour that present perspectives and analyses diering starkly from mainstream
economic interpretations.
The evolving supply of policy analysis is likely to continue to be dened by a mixture of
mainstream and alternative analytical perspectives. New policy problems generated by changing
social conditions, technologies and political agendas cannot be expected to readily lend them-
selves to mainstream policy analysis. Indeed, although policy analysis textbooks present specic
forms of market failure or government failure as defensible rationales for policy action, many
Mintrom and Williams
12
contemporary problems defy such categorization. For example, changing understandings of morally
appropriate behaviour (Mooney 2000) and diering perspectives on the degree to which parents
and the state should be trusted to act in the best interests of children (Nelson 1984; Shapiro 1999)
have provided impetus for a range of recent policy disputes. Mainstream approaches to policy
analysis are not well suited to assessing the relative merits of competing arguments and per-
spectives in these areas. This suggests that, for any headway to be made in addressing disputes of
this sort, the comparative strengths of alternative disciplinary perspectives must be drawn upon
to guide policy analysis. The frontiers of policy analysis are also being advanced by a growing
awareness of the degree to which national policies hold implications for international relations,
transnational norms, and global trade or environmental concerns (Sandler 2004; Tabb 2004).
These developments will require further innovation in the design and application of policy analysis
techniques. In many instances, the mainstream perspective will need to be augmented by alter-
native perspectives that oer sound analytical traction on otherwise dicult conceptual and
practical problems. Thus, denitions of policy analysis are likely to keep expanding and the set
of actors having relevant and important contributions to make will remain dynamic.
Prospects for the policy analysis movement
The policy analysis movement began to emerge in the mid-1960s. Today, it is large, diverse and
global. The phenomenon of many people generating policy analysis for consumption by an array
of audiences can be claimed to be a movement for several reasons. First, policy analysts, no matter
where they are located within society, all focus their energies in one way or another on iden-
tifying, understanding and confronting public problems. As techniques of policy analysis have
been more routinely applied to investigating public problems, new problems and new approaches
to addressing them have been revealed. While a nite set of known policy problems might exist
at any given time, that set is continually being revised, as particular problems are resolved and as
others become salient. Second, while people engaged in policy analysis work out of a variety of
perspectives and often make contradictory and con icting arguments, there is a widely shared
recognition that knowledge of public problems and how they can best be addressed requires thor-
ough, theory-driven, and evidence-based investigation. This is highly signicant, because chan-
ging perceptions of what kind of claims should guide public deliberations have made it harder
for long-entrenched groups to use their informal, quiet power to inuence government actions.
Third, the increasing reliance placed on this style of policy analysis has required a core of people
to routinely apply a well-established set of analytical and research methods. The result has been
the clear denition of a mainstream of policy analysis, and many university programmes have
been established to professionalize budding analysts. Fourth, the development of policy analysis
has not been restricted to those people applying mainstream techniques. Indeed, there has been
a level of openness to people from various disciplines oering alternative theoretical and empirical
arguments concerning particular policy matters. Critique of mainstream methods has often resul-
ted in signicant eorts to improve the analytical approaches employed. Finally, people engaged
in policy analysis, regardless of their substantive interests or their immediate purposes, have shared
an understanding that they are engaged in important, socially relevant work. They share a common
understanding that, at base, public policy involves systematic eorts to change social institutions.
The seriousness of this work helps to explain why policy disputes are often prolonged and heated.
Taken together, these various features of contemporary policy work clearly represent markers of
a policy analysis movement. Those associated with it are, in their many particular ways, con-
tributing to the ongoing task of dening the appropriate role of government in society, and
how governments can best mediate social and economic relations.
Public policy debate
13
What are the future prospects of this movement? How might it continue to evolve? Internal
and external dynamics are likely to ensure further expansion of the movement. With respect to
internal dynamics, a clear lesson of the foregoing discussion is that good policy analysis creates
its own demand. This happens because, in competitive settings like debates over policy choices,
opposing parties face strong incentives to nd ways to outsmart their opponents. If one partys
arguments are consistently supported by strong policy analysis and this appears to give them an
edge in debate, then other parties will soon see the merit in upping their own game. This can
involve emulating, revising or critiquing the methods of opponents. But, no matter what, the
result is further production of policy analysis. Aside from this, careful policy studies, especially
evaluations of existing programmes, often reveal aspects of policy design or implementation that
require further attention. When we are forced to return to the drawing board, further policy
analysis occurs. The lesson that good policy analysis creates its own demand suggests that the
currently observed momentum and vibrancy of that movement will continue.
The external dynamics that drive expansion of the policy analysis movement derive from chan-
ging social, economic and political conditions. In the future, the increasing integration of econo-
mies and societies, referred to generally as globalization, can be expected to generate new sets of
policy problems. In this regard, the changes associated with globalization echo the dynamics that
were observed from the late nineteenth century well into the twentieth century in federal sys-
tems. During that period, increasing commerce across state and provincial borders, and the
emergence of intensive inter-jurisdictional competition prompted new considerations of the role
of government in society. Extensive eort also went into determining what levels of government
were best suited to performing dierent functions. New times introduce new problems and
questions. Drawing lessons from the past, it seems clear that many new policy problems will arise
on government agendas and be the focus of extensive debates in the coming decades. While
globalizing forces will be responsible for generating many of these challenges, the challenges
themselves will be manifested at all levels of government, from the local upwards. As in the past,
people both inside and outside government can be expected to show intense interest in these
policy challenges, and they will call for further supply of innovative and high-quality policy
analysis to build their knowledge and strengthen their debating points.
Bibliography
Abelson, Donald. 2004. The think tank industry in the USA, in Diane Stone and Andrew Denham.
Think Tank Traditions: Policy Research and the Politics of Ideas. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Bardach, Eugene. 1977. The Implementation Game: What Happens After a Bill Becomes a Law. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
—— 2000. A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Eective Problem Solving. New
York: Seven Bridges Press/Chatham House.
Barrow, C.J. 2000. Social Impact Assessment: An Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.
Boardman, Anthony E., David H. Greenberg, Aidan R. Vining and David L. Weimer. 2006. Cost-benet
Analysis: Concepts and Practice. Englewood Clis, NJ: Pearson/Prentice Hall.
Boston, Jonathan. 1989. The Treasury and the organisation of economic advice: Some international
comparisons, in Brian Easton (ed.) The Making of Rogernomics. Auckland: Auckland University Press, 6891.
—— Stephen Church and Tim Bale. 2003. The impact of proportional representation on government
eectiveness: The New Zealand experience, Australian Journal of Public Administration 62(21).
Carlson, Deven. 2011. Trends and innovations in public policy analysis, Policy Studies Journal 39: 1326.
Chen, Huey-Tsyh. 1990. Theory-Driven Evaluations. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Cobb, Roger W. and Charles W. Elder. 1983. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building,
2nd edn. Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Cook, Thomas D. and Donald T. Campbell. 1979. Quasi-Experimentation: Design and Analysis Issues for
Field Settings. Boston, MA: Houghton Miin Company.
Mintrom and Williams
14
Dahl, Robert A. 1998. On Democracy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Derthick, Martha. 1979. Policymaking for Social Security. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Dolowitz, D. and D. Marsh. 2000. Learning from abroad: The role of policy transfer in contemporary
policy-making, Governance 13: 524.
Eckstein, Otto. 1958. Water Resource Development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Eisner, Marc Allen. 1993. Regulatory Politics in Transition. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Eyestone, Robert. 1978. From Social Issues to Public Policy. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Forester, John. 1999. The Deliberative Practitioner: Encouraging Participatory Planning Processes. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Goldnch, Shaun. 1998. Remaking New Zealands economic policy: Institutional elites as radical innovators,
Governance 11, 177207.
Heernan, Richard. 1999. New Labour and Thatcherism: Political Change in Britain. New York: St. Martins
Press.
Howlett, Michael. 2011. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. Abingdon: Routledge.
Kingdon, John W. 1995. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York: HarperCollins College Publishers.
Lindblom, Charles E. 1968. The Policymaking Process. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Lipsky, Michael. 1980. Street-Level Bureaucracy: The Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Services. New York:
Russell Sage Foundation.
—— 1984. Bureaucratic disentitlement in social welfare programs, Social Service Review 58(1): 327.
Lock, Karen. 2000. Health impact assessment, British Medical Journal 320: 13958.
McCraw, Thomas K. 1984. Prophets of Regulation. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
McGann, James and Erik Johnson. 2006. Comparative Think Tanks, Politics and Public Policy. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar Publishing.
Mintrom, Michael. 2003. People Skills for Policy Analysts. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
—— 2006. Policy entrepreneurs, think tanks, and trusts, in Raymond Miller (ed.) New Zealand Government
and Politics, 4th
edn, Melbourne: Oxford
University Press, 53646.
—— 2012. Contemporary Policy Analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.
——and Sandra Vergari. 1996. Advocacy coalitions, policy entrepreneurs, and policy change, Policy Studies
Journal 24: 42035.
Mooney, Christopher Z. (ed.) 2000. The Public Clash of Private Values: The Politics of Morality Policy. New
York: Chatham House Publishers of Seven Bridges Press.
Munger, Michael C. 2000. Analyzing Policy: Choices, Conicts, and Practices. New York: W.W. Norton.
Murray, Georgina and Douglas Pacheco. 2001. Think tanks in the 1990s, The Australian National University.
Myers, Samuel L. Jr. 2002. Presidential address - analysis of race as policy analysis, Journal of Policy Analysis
and Management 21: 16990.
Nelson, Barbara. 1984. Making an Issue of Child Abuse. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Niskanen, William A., Jr. 1971. Bureaucracy and Representative Government. Chicago: Aldine-Atherton.
—— 1988. Reaganomics: An Insiders Account of the Policies and the People. New York: Oxford University Press.
Oliver, W. Hugh. 1989. The labour caucus and economic policy formation, 1981-1984, in Brian Easton
(ed.) The Making of Rogernomics. Auckland: Auckland University Press, 1152.
Osborne, David and Ted Gaebler. 1993. Reinventing Government: How the Entrepreneurial Spirit is Transforming
the Public Sector. New York: Penguin Books.
Patton, Michael Quinn. 1997. Utilization-Focused Evaluation: The New Century Text. Thousand Oaks, CA:
Sage.
Perri 2004. Joined-up government in the western world in comparative perspective: A preliminary lit-
erature review and exploration, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 14: 10338. Available
at: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Perri_6
Pressman, Jerey L. and Aaron Wildavsky. 1973. Implementation. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Radin, Beryl A. 2000. Beyond Machiavelli: Policy Analysis Comes of Age. Washington, DC: Georgetown
University Press.
Rhoads, Steven E. 1985. The Economists View of the World: Government, Markets, and Public Policy. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Rochefort, David A. and Roger W. Cobb (eds). 1994. The Politics of Problem Denition:
Shaping the Policy
Agenda.
Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
Sabatier, Paul A. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy-oriented
learning therein, Policy Sciences 21: 12968.
Public policy debate
15
Sandler, Todd. 2004. Global Collective Action. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Savas, E.S. 1987. Privatization: The Key to Better Government. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House.
Schön, Donald A. 1983. The Reective Practitioner: How Professionals Think in Action. New York: Basic
Books.
——and Martin Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies. New
York: Basic Books.
Self, Peter. 1977. Econocrats and the Policy Process: The Politics and Philosophy of Cost-Benet Analysis. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press.
Shapiro, Ian. 1999. Democratic Justice. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Smith, James A. 1991. The Idea Brokers: Think Tanks and the Rise of the New Policy Elite. New York: The
Free Press.
Stevens, Joe B. 1993. The Economics of Collective Choice . Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Stokey, Edith and Richard Zeckhauser. 1978. A Primer for Policy Analysis. New York: W.W. Norton.
Stone, Deborah. 2002. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making, revised edn. New York: W.W.
Norton.
Stone, Diane 2000. Non-governmental policy transfer: The strategies of independent policy institutes,
Governance 13: 65.
——and Andrew Denham. 2004. Think Tank Traditions: Policy Research and the Politics of Ideas. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Tabb, William K. 2004. Economic Governance in the Age of Globalization. New York: Columbia University
Press.
True, Jacqui and Michael Mintrom. 2001. Transnational networks and policy diusion: The case of
gender mainstreaming, International Studies Quarterly 45: 2757.
Weimer, David L. and Aidan R. Vining. 2005. Policy Analysis: Concepts and Practice, 4th edn. Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Weiss, Carol H. 1998. Evaluation, 2nd edn. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1979. Speaking Truth to Power: The Art and Craft of Policy Analysis. Boston, MA: Little-Brown.
—— 1992. The New Politics of the Budgetary Process, 2nd edn. New York: Harper Collins Publishers.
Williamson, John (ed.). 1993. The Political Economy of Policy Reform. Washington, DC: Institute for International
Economics.
Wolf, Charles, Jr. 1979. A theory of nonmarket failures, Journal of Law and Economics 22: 10739.
Wood, Christopher. 1995. Environmental Impact Assessment: A Comparative Review. Burnt Mill: Longman
Scientic and Technical.
Yergin,
Daniel and Joseph
Stanislaw. 1998. The Commanding Heights: The Battle Between Government and the
Marketplace that Is Remaking the Modern World. New York: Touchstone.
Mintrom and Williams
16
2
The policy-making process
Michael Howlett and Sarah Giest
The policy cycle model of the policy process
The idea that policy development can be thought of as a series of steps in a decision-making
process was rst broached systematically in the work of Harold Lasswell, a pioneer in the eld
of policy research (Lasswell 1956, 1971). In most recent work, a ve-stage model of the policy
process has been most commonly used. In this model, agenda-setting refers to the rst stage
in the process when a problem is initially sensed by policy actors and a variety of solutions put
forward. Policy formulation refers to the development of specic policy options within
government when the range of possible choices is narrowed by excluding infeasible ones, and
eorts are made by various actors to have their favored solution ranked highly among the
remaining few. Decision-making refers to the third stage in which governments adopt a
particular course of action. In the fourth stage of policy implementation governments put their
decisions into eect using some combination of the tools of public administration in order to
alter the distribution of goods and services in society in a way that is broadly compatible with
the sentiments and values of aected parties. Finally policy evaluation refers to the fth stage in
the process in which the results of policies are monitored by both state and societal actors, often
leading to the reconceptualization of policy problems and solutions in the light of experiences
encountered with the policy in question (Howlett et al. 2009).
This idea of policy-making existing as a set of interrelated stages provides a general frame-
work for understanding the policy development process and points to several of the key
temporal activities and relationships that should be examined in furthering study of the issue.
However, it does not answer several key questions such as the actual substance of policy, the
number and type of relevant actors involved in the process and what motivates them, the exact
manner and sequence in which actual policy development processes occur, and whether there
exist basic patterns of development in dierent issues areas, sectors or jurisdictions (Sabatier 1991).
Empirical studies aimed at answering these questions and generating more detailed models of
the policy-making process, however, have developed some knowledge about the activities of
policy actors at each stage of the cycle, summarized below, which draw attention to the limited
number of common modes, or styles, which characterize policy processes throughout the world
and the factors which drive policy-making through the various stages.
17
Styles of policy behavior in the policy cycle
Agenda-setting
In the scholarly literature on agenda-setting, for example, a useful distinction is often drawn
between the systemic or unocial public agenda and the institutional or formal, ocial, agenda
which helps to conceptualize policy-making dynamics at this stage of the process. The systemic
agenda consists of all issues that are commonly perceived by members of the political com-
munity as meriting public attention and as involving matters within the legitimate jurisdiction of
existing governmental authority (Cobb and Elder 1972). This is essentially a societys agenda for
discussion of public problems, such as crime or health care, water quality or wilderness pre-
servation. The formal or institutional agenda, on the other hand, consists of only a limited number
of issues or problems to which attention is devoted by policy elites (Baumgartner and Jones 1991;
Kingdon 1984). Each society has literally hundreds of issues which some citizens nd to be
matters of concern and would have the government do something about. However, only a small
proportion of the problems on the public or systemic agenda are actually taken up by policy
actors actively involved in policy development and understanding how and why this movement
occurs is key to understanding process dynamics at the front-end of the policy process.
Almost 40 years ago the American political scientists Cobb, Ross and Ross developed a model
of typical agenda-setting styles based on this insight. In their analysis, they argued that three basic
patterns of agenda-setting could be discerned, distinguished by the origins of the issue as well as the
resources utilized to facilitate its inclusion on the agenda. In the outside initiation pattern issues arise
in nongovernmental groups and are then expanded suciently to reach, rst, the public [systemic]
agenda and, nally, the formal [institutional] agenda (Cobb et al. 1976). The mobilization case is quite
dierent and describes decision-makers trying to expand an issue from a formal to a public agenda.
In this model, issues are simply placed on the formal agenda by the government with no necessary
preliminary expansion from a publicly recognized grievance. In the third type of agenda-setting,
inside initiation,inuential groups with special access to decision-makers initiate a policy and do not
necessarily want it to be expanded and contested in public. This can be due to technical as well as
political reasons. Entrance is virtually automatic due to the privileged place of those desiring a decision.
Further research conducted by John Kingdon into the dynamics of agenda-setting in the US
Congress in the early 1980s focused on the timing of these processes of agenda entrance. In his
work, he focused on the role played by policy entrepreneurs both inside and outside government
in taking advantage of agenda-setting opportunitiespolicy windowsto move items onto formal
government agendas (Kingdon 1984). Kingdon argued that the characteristics of issues (the pro-
blem stream) combined with the characteristics of political institutions and circumstances (the
politics stream) and the development of policy solutions (the policy stream), lead to the opening and
closing of opportunities for agenda entrance. Such opportunities can be seized upon or not, as the
case may be, by policy entrepreneurs who are able to recognize and act upon them. The policy
window types which can lead to issue entrance include routine, spill-over, discretionary and random
types (Kingdon 1984; Howlett 1998). Empirical evidence suggests that the frequency of occurrence
of the window types varies by level of institutionalizationwith the most institutionalized types
occurring much more frequently than the least institutionalized (Howlett 1998).
Policy formulation
Studies of the second stage of the policy cycle, policy formulation, have also emphasized the impor-
tance of specic kinds of actors interacting to develop and rene policy options for government
Howlett and Giest
18
(Freeman 1965; Linder and Peters 1990) and the resulting small number of styles of policy for-
mulation. But unlike agenda-setting, where the public is often actively involved, in policy formula-
tion, the relevant policy actors are restricted to those who not only have an opinion on a subject,
but also have some minimal level of knowledge of the subject area, allowing them to comment,
at least hypothetically, on the feasibility of options put forward to resolve policy problems.
The power of the ideas held by these actors and their stability in policy subsystems, in particular,
has been a subject of much attention in studies of policy formulation in recent years. Carstensen
(2011), for example, has suggested that ideas change incrementally, when new elements of meaning
are added to them, resulting in a characteristic process of policy formulation in which similar
ideas inform similar policy options over long periods of time. This shifts the focus of the analysis
towards the inuence of discourses within certain institutional settings as a key factor aecting
the nature of the kinds of policy alternatives put forward in the policy formulation (Schmidt 2006,
2010, 2011). Focusing on the information or knowledge available to decision-makers has led policy
research in this vein to focus on concepts such as epistemic communities (ECs) in policy formula-
tion. These are loose groupings of experts or knowledge providers for the decision-making
processopening up new opportunities for inuence on policy alternatives. The suggested
mechanism underlying this is their ability to transfer policy by assuming control over knowledge
production and in doing so guiding decision-maker learning (Dunlop 2009: 290; Haas 1992).
Scholars over the years have developed a variety of such concepts in order to help identify who
are the key actors in these policy subsystems, what brings them together, how they interact, and what
eect their interaction has on policy development (Jordan 1990a, 1990b; Jordan and Schubert 1992).
Most of these distinguish between a large set of actors with some knowledge of the policy issue in
question, such as an epistemic community and a smaller set in which actors not only have the requisite
knowledge, but also have established patterns of more or less routine interactions with each other
and with decision-makers to allow them to inuence alternative formation (Knoke 1993).
Membership in knowledge-based policy communities extends to actors such as state policy-
makers (administrative, political, and judicial), members of non-governmental organizations (NGOs)
concerned with the subject, members of the media who report on the subject, academics who
follow or research the area, and members of the general public who, for whatever reason, have
taken an interest in the subject (Sabatier 1987, 1988). In many issue areas, the policy community
also involves members of other organizations such as businesses, labor unions, or various for-
malized interest groups or professional associations concerned with government actions in the
sector concerned. In some cases, international actors such as multinational corporations, inter-
national governmental or NGOs, or the governments of foreign states, can also be members of
sectoral policy communities (Haas 1992). The subset of these actors who interact within more
formalized institutions and procedures of government are dened as members of policy networks
(Coleman and Skogstad 1990; Marin and Mayntz 1991; Pross 1992). These policy networks
include representatives from the community, but are inner circles of actors, who eectively
hold the power to veto many policy options as untenable or unfeasible.
In this view, the likely results of policy formulation are contingent upon the nature and con-
guration of the policy community and network in the specic sector concerned. A key variable
that many observers have argued aects the structure and behavior of policy networks, for example,
is their number of members, which inuences their level of integration and the types of inter-
actions they undertake (van Waarden 1992; Atkinson and Coleman 1989, 1992; Coleman and
Skogstad 1990). What is important for policy communities, on the other hand, is not the number of
participants in the community but the number of relatively distinct idea sets which exist within
it. This aects the nature of conict and consensus which exists in the community and, as a
result, aects the behavior of community actors (Schulman 1988; MacRae 1993; Smith 1993).
The policy-making process
19
Taken together, these congurations can dene a policy formulation style, one which can be
quite long-lasting and resistant to change. In open subsystems where networks have many
members and communities share many idea sets, for example, it can be expected that a propensity
for new, radical, alternatives to the status quo may be generated in the policy formulation process.
In closed subsystems, where networks have few members and communities are dominated by a
single idea set, on the other hand, a status quo orientation will emerge in the policy options devel-
oped and put before decision-makers. In subsystems where only a few actors make up the network
but communities are open to new ideas, signicant alternatives to the status quo may emerge from
the formulation process, but usually over the opposition of network members. In subsystems
where many actors deal with few ideas, marginal or incremental options tend to develop.
Although the network framework has been criticized as being a descriptive metaphor, due to
the fact that the independent variables, (of policy-making) are not network characteristics per se
but rather characteristics of components within the networks (Dowding 1995: 137), it remains
helpful in that it provides a general mechanism to help organize the complex reality of multiple
actors, institutions, and ideas found in the policy formulation process (Howlett et al. 2009;
Smith 1994; Howlett and Ramesh 1998; Howlett 2002a).
Decision-making
Similar styles have been identied at the decision-making stage of the policy process. Many
early studies of policy-making in companies, governments, and organizations conducted largely
by students of public and business administration, for example, argued that decision-makers
attempt to follow a systematic method for arriving at logical, ecient decisions. They argued
that policy-makers achieved superior results when they rst established a goal; explored alter-
native strategies for achieving it; attempted to predict its consequences and the likelihood of
each occurring; and then chose the option which maximized potential benets at least cost or
risk (Gawthrop 1971; Carley 1980; Cahill and Overman 1990).
This model was rational in the sense that it prescribed a standard set of procedures for policy-
making which were expected to lead in all circumstances to the choice of the most ecient means
of achieving policy goals (Jennings 1987; Torgerson 1986). Pure rational models of decision-
making thought of policy-makers as neutral technicians or managers, who identify a problem
and then nd the most eective or ecient way of solving it (Elster 1991). Many of the latest eorts
to enhance the eciency and eectiveness of public policy decision-making, such as, for example,
the evidence-based policy movement (Pawson 2006), focuses on the application of a systemic
evaluative rationality to policy problems (Sanderson 2006; Mintrom 2007) in classic rational style.
Empirical research into decision-making processes, however, has discovered that political
processes of bargaining and negotiation often outweigh rational deliberations and calculations
of costs and benets are subject to substantive and procedural limitations. Policy-makers were
often found to be neither necessarily neutral nor competent and other models of the public
policy decision-making processes have argued that this is not an accidental situation but rather
an inherent and unavoidable characteristic of the policy-making exercise.
Perhaps the most noted critic of the rational model of decision-making was the American
behavioral scientist Herbert Simon. In a series of books and articles beginning in the early
1950s, he argued that there were several hurdles that prevented decision-makers from attaining
pure comprehensive rationality in their decisions (Simon 1955, 1957). Simon noted denite
cognitive limits to the decision-makers ability to consider all possible options, which forces them
to selectively consider alternatives. He concluded from his assessment of the rational model that
public decisions in practice did not maximize benets over costs, but merely tended to satisfy
Howlett and Giest
20
whatever criteria decision-makers set for themselves in the instance in question. This satiscing
criterion, as he put it, was a realistic one given the bounded rationality with which human
beings are endowed. This analysis did not rule out the use of rationality-forcing techniques but
pointed out that rational models would only result in optimal decisions in very specic situa-
tions where full information on options existed and could be mobilized by key decision-makers
(Smith and May 1980).
The well-known incremental model of policy-making developed by Yale University political
scientist Charles Lindblom incorporated these insights into limited or bounded rationality into
a general model of public policy decision-making (Dahl and Lindblom 1953; Lindblom 1955,
1958, 1959; Hayes 1992). Lindblom summarized the elements of his model as consisting of the
following a mutually supporting set of simplifying and focusing stratagems:
limitation of analysis to a few somewhat familiar policy alternatives diering only marginally
from the status quo;
an intertwining of analysis of policy goals and other values with the empirical aspects of the
problem (that is, no requirement that values be specied rst with means subsequently
found to promote them);
a greater analytical preoccupation with ills to be remedied than positive goals to be sought;
a sequence of trials, errors, and revised trials;
analysis that explores only some, not all, of the important possible consequences of a considered
alternative;
fragmentation of analytical work to many (partisan) participants in policymaking (each
attending to their piece of the overall problem domain).
(Lindblom 1979)
This resulted, as he put it in his oft-cited 1959 article on The Science of Muddling Through, in
decision-makers working through a process of continually building out from the current
situation, step-by-step and by small degrees or increments in which policies were invariably
developed through a process of successive limited comparisons with earlier ones with which
decision-makers were already familiar (Lindblom 1959).
Braybrooke and Lindblom (1963) argued that dierent styles of decision-making could be
discerned depending upon the amount of knowledge at the disposal of decision-makers, and the
amount of change the decision involved from earlier decisions. Other authors, like Graham
Allison, also developed similar models of distinct decision-making styles (Allison 1969, 1971),
but did not specify in any detail the variables which led to the adoption of a particular style
(Bendor and Hammond 1992).
Attempting to improve upon these models, John Forester (1984, 1989) suggested that
decision-making is aected by the number of agents involved in a decision, their organiza-
tional setting, how well a problem is dened, the information available on the problem, its
causes and consequences, and the amount of time available to decision-makers to consider possible
contingencies and their present and anticipated consequences. The number of agents can expand
and multiply almost to innity. The setting can include many dierent organizations and can be
more or less open to external inuences. The problem can be ambiguous or susceptible to
multiple competing interpretations. Information can be incomplete, misleading or purposefully
withheld or manipulated, and time can be limited or articially
constrained and manipulated. In
this model, decision-makers
situated in complex subsystems are expected to undertake adjust-
ment strategies while those dealing with simple congurations of actors and ideas will be more
prone to undertake search-type strategies. The nature of the decision criteria, on the other hand,
The policy-making process
21
varies with the severity of the informational, time and other resource constraints under which
decision-makers operate. Hence decision-makers faced with high constraints will tend to favor
satiscing over optimization, itself an outcome more likely to occur in situations of low con-
straint. Overall this would lead to a pattern in which most decisions would be incremental
except in specic circumstances where other kinds of decisions could emerge.
Policy implementation styles
Generally speaking, comparative implementation studies have also shown that governments tend
to develop specic implementation styles (Knill 1998; Hawkins and Thomas 1989; Kagan 1991;
Howlett 2002b) which combine various kinds of instruments into a more or less coherent whole
which is then applied in particular sectors (Howlett 2011; Wu et al. 2010). Linked to implementa-
tion, policy tools provide the substance or content to what was planned in the formulation stage
and decided upon afterwards in the decision-making stage of the policy process (Howlett 2011).
These tools fall into two types. Substantive instruments are those directly providing goods and
services to members of the public or governments. They include a variety of tools or instruments
relying on dierent types of governing resources for their eectiveness (Tupper and Doern 1981;
Vedung 1997; Woodside 1986; Peters and Van Nispen 1998; Salamon 1989). A useful way to
classify these (see Table 2.1) is according to the type of governing resource upon which they
rely: nodality or information; authority, treasure or nancial resources, or administrative or
organizations ones (Hood 1986).
Procedural instruments are dierent from substantive ones in that their impact on policy out-
comes is less direct. Rather than aect the delivery of goods and services, their principal intent is
to modify or alter the nature of policy processes at work in the implementation process (Howlett
2000; int Veld, 1998). A list of these instruments is provided in Table 2.2.
Why a particular combination of procedural and substantive instruments is utilized in parti-
cular policy issue areas is a key question (Gunningham and Young 1997; Dunsire 1993; How-
lett 2000; Salamon 2002; Clark and Russell 2009; McGoldrick and Boonn 2010). Some studies
suggest that policy mixes can be designed. Studies such as Gunningham, Grabosky and Youngs
work on smart regulation, for example, led to the development of eorts to identify com-
plementaries and conicts within instrument mixes or tool portfolios involved in more
complex and sophisticated policy designs (Barnett et al. 2009; Buckman and Diesendorf 2010).
Each tool mix decision combines advantages and disadvantages of each tool in its relationship
to other tools as well as the eect it has on costs and benets for government (Howlett 2011).
Table 2.1 A taxonomy of substantive policy instruments
Principal use Governing resource
Nodality Authority Authority Organization
Effectors Advice Licences Grants Bureaucratic
training Certication Loans administration
regulation Tax expenditures Public enterprises
user charges
Detectors Reporting Census-taking Polling Record-keeping
registration consultants policing surveys
Source: Howlett, Michael. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. New York: Routledge, 2011. Available at:
www.routledge.com/books/details/9780415781336/
Howlett and Giest
22
The preferences of state decision-makers and the nature of the constraints within which they
operate are key factors which many studies have highlighted as aecting instrument choices and
policy implementation styles (Bressers and OToole 1998). A state must have a high level of
administrative capacity, for example, in order to utilize authority, treasure, and organization-
based instruments in situations in which they wish to aect signicant numbers of policy targets.
When it has few of these resources, it will tend to utilize instruments such as incentives or
propaganda, or to rely on existing voluntary, community or family-based instruments (Howlett
et al. 2009). Similarly a key feature of procedural instrument choice is a governments capacity to
manipulate policy subsystems. Undertaken in order to retain the political trust or legitimacy
required for substantive policy instruments to be eective (Beetham 1991; Stillman 1974),
procedural policy instrument choice is also aected by the size of the policy target. Whether a
government faces sectoral delegitimation or widespread systemic delegitimation aects the types
of procedural instruments a government will employ (Habermas 1973, 1975; Mayntz 1975).
Policy evaluation styles
The last stage of the cycle is policy evaluation. For many early observers, policy evaluation was
expected to consist of assessing if a public policy was achieving its stated objectives and, if not,
what could be done to eliminate impediments to their attainment. Thus David Nachmias (1979)
dened policy evaluation as the objective, systematic, empirical examination of the eects ongoing
policies and public programs have on their targets in terms of the goals they are meant to achieve.
However, while analysts often resorted to concepts such as success or failure to conclude their
evaluation, as Ingram and Mann cautioned:
[T]he phenomenon of policy failure is neither so simple nor certain as many contemporary
critics of policy and politics would have us believe. Success and failure are slippery concepts,
often highly subjective and reective of an individuals goals, perception of need, and perhaps
even psychological disposition toward life.
(Ingram and Mann 1980)
Table 2.2 A resource-based taxonomy of procedural policy instruments
Principal use Governing resource
Nodality Authority Treasure Organization
Positive Education Agreements Interest-group
funding
Hearings
Exhortation Treaties Research Evaluations
Advertising Advisory-group
creation
Intervenor-
funding
Institutional-
bureaucratic reform
Training
Negative Misleading
information/
propaganda
Banning groups
and associations
Eliminating
funding
Administrative delay
Information
suppression
Source: Howlett, Michael. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. New York: Routledge, 2011. Available at:
www.routledge.com/books/details/9780415781336/
The policy-making process
23
That is, public policy goals are often not stated clearly enough to nd out if and to what extent
they are being achieved, nor are they shared by all key policy actors. Moreover, the possibilities for
objective analysis are also limited because of the diculties involved in the attempt to develop
objective standards by which to evaluate a governments level of success in dealing with subjective
claims and socially constructed problems.
What is signicant in the evaluative process is thus not so much ultimate success and failure, but
that policy actors and the organizations and institutions they represent can learn from the formal
and informal evaluation of policies in which they are engaged. This can lead them to modify their
positions in the direction of greater substantive or procedural policy change, or it can lead them to
resist any alteration to the status quo (Majone 1989). And, like with other stages of the policy process,
a few common or typical styles of learning have been identied in the literature on the subject.
A signicant variable in this regard is the capacity of an organization to absorb new information
(Cohen and Levinthal 1990). Only when state administrative capacity is high, for example,
would one expect any kind of learning to occur. If a relatively closed network dominates the
subsystem, then this learning is likely to be restricted to some form of lesson-drawing, in
which policy-makers draw lessons from past uses of policy instruments (Rose 1991; Bennett and
Howlett 1992). Open subsystems allow for social learning when administrative capacity is high
and more informal evaluation where the ability to adapt is rather low. Social learning occurs
when ideas and events in the larger policy community penetrate into policy evaluations. If the
policy subsystem is dominated by closed networks, one would expect to nd formal types of
evaluation with little substantive impact on either policy instruments or goals and lesson-drawing
attempts (Howlett et al. 2009).
Policy evaluations do not necessarily result in major policy change. That is, while the concept
of evaluation suggests that an implicit feedback loop is an inherent part of the policy cycle, in
many cases this loop may not be operationalized (Pierson 1993). Path dependence, in which
policies are set on trajectories following some critical juncture can hinder policy change
and learning (Pierson 2000). Organizational-institutional properties (Eising 2004; Olsen and
Peters 1996) are also often seen as barriers to learning from policy evaluations.
Conclusion: policy development as policy style
As Lasswell noted in the 1950s, envisioning policy development as a staged, sequential, and itera-
tive process is a useful analytical and methodological device. Methodologically such an approach
reduces the complexity of public policy-making by breaking down that complexity into a small
number of stages and substages, each of which can be investigated alone, or in terms of its rela-
tionship to any or all the other stages of the cycle. The policy cycle idea also helps to answer many
key questions about public policy-making regarding the eectiveness of dierent tools and the
identication of bottlenecks in policy processes. The stages allow for the identication of typical
actors and actions in dierent phases of tackling a problem which makes it easier to identify
independent and dependent variables in the study of policy processes and behaviour and moves
thinking forward by helping to identify the relatively limited range of styles of activity possible
at each stage of the cycle (Freeman 1985; Coleman 1994; Tuohy 1992; Vogel 1986).
Bibliography
Allison, G. 1969. Conceptual models and the Cuban missile crisis, American Political Science Review 63(3):
689718.
—— (1971) Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. Boston: Little Brown.
Howlett and Giest
24
Atkinson, M. and W. Coleman. 1989. Strong states and weak states: Sectoral policy networks in advanced
capitalist economies, British Journal of Political Science 19(1): 4767.
——and W. Coleman. 1992. Policy networks, policy communities and the problems of governance,
Governance 5(2): 15480.
Barnett, Pauline, Tim Tenbensel, Jacqueline Cuming, Clare Alyden, Toni Ashton, Megan Pledger and
Mili Burnette. 2009. Implementing new modes of governance in the New Zealand health system: An
empirical study, Health Policy 93: 11827.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1991. Agenda dynamics and policy subsystems, Journal of
Politics 53(4): 104474.
Beetham, D. 1991. The Legitimation of Power. London: Macmillan.
Bendor, Jonathan and Thomas H. Hammond. 1992. Re-thinking Allisons models, American Political Science
Review 86(2): 30122.
Bennett, Colin J. and Michael Howlett. 1992. The lessons of learning: Reconciling theories of policy
learning and policy change, Policy Sciences 25(3): 27594.
Braybrooke, David and Charles E. Lindblom. 1963. A Strategy of Decision: Policy Evaluation as a Social Process.
New York: Free Press of Glencoe.
Bressers, Hans Th.A. and Laurence J. OToole. 1998. The selection of policy instruments: A network-based
perspective, Journal of Public Policy 18(3): 21339.
Buckman, Greg and Mark Diesendorf. 2010. Design limitations in Australian renewable electricity policies,
Energy Policy 38(7): 336576.
Cahill, Anthony G. and E. Sam Overman. 1990. The evolution of rationality in policy analysis,in
S.S. Nagel (ed.) Policy Theory and Policy Evaluation: Concepts, Knowledge, Causes, and Norms. New York:
Greenwood Press.
Carley, Michael. 1980. Rational Techniques in Policy Analysis.
London: Heinemann Educational
Books.
Carstensen, Martin B. 2011. Ideas are not as stable as political scientists want them to be: A theory of
incremental ideational change, Political Studies 59(3): 596615.
Clark, C.D. and C.S. Russell. 2009. Ecological conservation: The problems of targeting policies and
designing instruments, Journal of Natural Resources Policy Research (1): 2134.
Cobb, Roger W. and Charles D. Elder. 1972. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building.
Boston: Allyn and Bacon.
—— J.K. Ross and M.H. Ross. 1976. Agenda building as a comparative political process, American Political
Science Review 70(1): 12638.
Cohen, Wesley M. and Daniel A. Levinthal. 1990. Absorptive capacity: A new perspective on learning
and innovation, Administrative Science Quarterly 35: 128 52.
Coleman, William D. 1994. Policy convergence in banking: A comparative study, Political Studies 42:
27492.
——and Grace Skogstad (eds). 1990. Policy Communities and Public Policy Canada: A Structural Approach.
Mississauga, ON: Copp Clark Pitman.
Dahl, Robert A. and Charles E. Lindblom. 1953. Politics, Economics and Welfare: Planning and Politico-economic
Systems Resolved into Basic Social Processes. New York: Harper and Row.
Dowding, K. 1995. Model or metaphor? A critical review of the policy network approach, Political Studies
43(1): 13658.
Dunlop, Claire A. 2009. Policy transfer as learning: Capturing variation in what decision-makers learn
from epistemic communities, Policy Studies 30(3): 289311.
Dunsire, Andrew. 1993. Manipulating Social Tensions: Collaboration as an Alternative Mode of Government
Intervention. Cologne: Max Plank Institute.
Eising, R. 2004. Multilevel governance and business interests in the European Union , Governance 17(2):
21145.
Elster, Jon. 1991. The possibility of rational politics,
in D. Held
(ed.) Political Theory Today. Oxford: Polity.
Forester, John. 1984. Bounded rationality and the politics of muddling through, Public Administration
Review 44(1): 2331.
—— 1989. Planning in the Face of Power. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Freeman, Gary P. 1985. National styles and policy sectors: Explaining structured variation, Journal of Public
Policy 5(4): 46796.
Freeman, J. Leiper. 1965. The Political Process: Executive - Bureaucratic - Legislative Relations, revised edn. New
York: Random House.
Gawthrop, Louis C. 1971. Administrative Politics and Social Change. New York: St. Martins Press.
The policy-making process
25
Gunningham, N., P. Grabosky and D. Sinclair. 1998. Smart Regulation: Designing Environmental Policy.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
——and M.D. Young. 1997. Toward optimal environmental policy: The case of biodiversity conservation,
Ecology Law Quarterly 24: 2438.
Haas, Peter M. 1992. Introduction: Epistemic communities and international policy coordination, International
Organization 46(1): 136.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1973. What does a legitimation crisis mean today? Legitimation problems in late
capitalism, Social Research 40(4): 64367.
—— 1975. Legitimation Crisis. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Hawkins, Keith and John M. Thomas (eds). 1989. Making Regulatory Policy. Pittsburgh, PA: University of
Pittsburgh Press.
Hayes, Michael T. 1992. Incrementalism and Public Policy. New York: Longmans.
Hood, Christopher. 1986. The Tools of Government. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House.
Howlett, Michael. 1998. Predictable and unpredictable policy windows: Institutional and exogenous
correlates of Canadian federal agenda-setting, Canadian Journal of Political Science 3(3): 495524.
—— 2000. Managing the hollow state: Procedural policy instruments and modern governance, Canadian
Public Administration 43(4): 41231.
—— 2002a. Do networks matter? Linking policy network structure to policy outcomes: Evidence from
four Canadian policy sectors, 19902000, Canadian Journal of Political Science 35(2): 23568.
—— 2002b. Policy instruments and implementation styles: The evolution of instrument choice in
Canadian environmental policy, in D.L. Van Nijnatten and R. Boardman (eds) Canadian Environmental
Policy: Context and Cases. Toronto: Oxford University Press, 25 45.
—— 2009. Governance modes, policy regimes and operational plans: A multi-level nested model of
policy
instrument choice and
policy design, Policy Sciences 42(1): 7389.
—— 2011. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. London and New York: Routledge.
——and M. Ramesh. 1998. Policy subsystem congurations and policy change: Operationalizing the
postpositivist analysis of the politics of the policy process, Policy Studies Journal 26(3): 46682
——M Ramesh and Anthony Perl. 2009. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. Toronto:
Oxford University Press.
Ingram, Helen M. and Dean E. Mann. 1980. Why Policies Succeed or Fail. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
int Veld, Roeland J. 1998. The dynamics of instruments, in B. Guy Peters and F. K. M. Van Nispen (eds)
Public Policy Instruments: Evaluating the Tools of Public Administration . New York: Edward Elgar, 15362.
Jennings, B. 1987. Interpretation and the practice of policy analysis, in F. Fischer and J. Forester (eds)
Confronting Values in Policy Analysis: The Politics of Criteria. Newbury Park, CA: Sage: 12852.
Jordan, A. Grant. 1990a. Policy community realism versus new institutionalist ambiguity, Political Studies
38(3): 47084.
—— 1990b. Sub-governments, policy communities and networks: Relling the old bottles?, Journal of
Theoretical Politics 2(3): 31938.
Jordan, G. and K. Schubert. 1992. A preliminary ordering of policy network labels, European Journal of
Political Research 21(1/2): 727.
Kagan, Robert A. 1991. Adversial legalism and American government, Journal of Policy Analysis and
Management 10(3): 369406.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Knill,
Christoph. 1998. European policies:
The impact of national administrative traditions, Journal of
Public Policy 18(1): 128.
Knoke, David. 1993. Networks as political glue: Explaining public policy-making, in W.J. Wilson (ed.)
Sociology and Public Agenda. London: Sage, 16484.
Lasswell, H.D. 1956. The Decision Process: Seven Categories of Functional Analysis. College Park, MD: University
of Maryland.
—— 1971. A Pre-View of Policy Sciences. New York: American Elsevier.
Lindblom, C.E. 1995. Bargaining: The Hidden Hand in Government. Los Angeles, CA: Rand Corporation.
—— 1958. Policy analysis, American Economic Review 48(3): 298312.
—— 1959. The science of muddling through, Public Administration Review 19(2): 7988.
—— 1979. Still muddling, not yet through, Public Administration Review 39(6): 517 26.
Linder, Stephen H. and B. Guy Peters. 1990. Research perspectives on the design of public policy:
Implementation, formulation, and design, in Dennis J. Palumbo and D.J. Calista. Implementation and the
Policy Process: Opening Up the Black Box . New York: Greenwood Press.
Howlett and Giest
26
McGoldrick, Daniel E. and Ann V. Boonn. 2010. Public policy to maximize tobacco cessation, American
Journal of Preventive Medicine 38(3) Supplement 1: S327S32.
MacRae, Duncan, Jr. 1993. Guidelines for policy discourse: Consensual versus adversarial, in Frank
Fischer and John Forester (eds) The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press: 291318.
Majone, Giandomenico. 1989. Evidence, Argument, and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Marin, Bernd and Renate Mayntz (eds). 1991. Policy Networks: Empirical Evidence and Theoretical Considerations.
Frankfurt-am-Main: Campus.
Mayntz, Renate. 1975. Legitimacy and the directive capacity of the political system, in Leon N. Lind-
berg, Robert Alford, Colin Crouch, and Claus Oe (eds) Stress and Contradiction in Modern Capitalism.
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books: 26174.
Mintrom, Michael. 2007. The policy analysis movement., in L. Dobuzinskis, M. Howlett and D.
Laycock (eds) Policy Analysis in Canada: The State of the Art. Toronto: University of Toronto Press:
784.
Nachmias, David. 1979. Public Policy Evaluation: Approaches and Methods. New York: St. Martins Press.
Olsen, Johan P. and B. Guy Peters (eds). 1996. Lessons from Experience: Experiential Learning in Administrative
Reforms in Eight Democracies. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.
Pawson, Ray. 2006. Evidence-Based Policy: A Realist Perspective. London: Sage.
Peters, B. Guy and F.K.M. Van Nispen (eds). 1998. Public Policy Instruments: Evaluating the Tools of Public
Administration. New York: Edward Elgar.
Pierson, Paul. 1993. When eect becomes cause: Policy feedback and political change, World Politics 45:
595628.
—— 2000. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, American Political Science Review
94(2): 25167.
Pross, A. Paul. 1992. Group Politics and Public Policy, Toronto: Oxford University Press.
Rose, Richard. 1991. What is lesson-drawing?, Journal of Public Policy 11(1): 330.
Sabatier,
Paul A. 1987. Knowledge,
policy-oriented learning, and policy change, Knowledge: Creation,
Diusion, Utilization 8(4): 64992.
—— 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy-oriented learning
therein, Policy Sciences 21(2 & 3): 12968.
—— 1991. Toward better theories of the policy process, PS: Political Science and Politics 24(2): 14456.
Salamon, Lester M. (ed.) 1989. Beyond Privatization: The Tools of Government Action. Washington, DC:
Urban Institute.
—— 2002. The new governance and the tools of public action, in L.M. Salamon (eds) The Tools of
Government: A Guide to the New Governance. New York: Oxford University Press: 11755.
Sanderson, I. 2006. Complexity, practical rationality and evidence-based policy making, Policy and
Politics 34(1): 11532.
Schulman, Paul R. 1988. The politics of ideational policy”’, Journal of Politics 50: 26391.
Schmidt, Vivien A. 2006. Discursive institutionalism: The explanatory power of ideas and discourse,
Annual Review of Political Science 1: 30326.
—— 2010. Taking ideas and discourse seriously: Explaining change through discursive institutionalism as
the fourth new institutionalism?, European Political Science Review 2(1): 125.
—— 2011. Speaking of change: Why discourse is key to the dynamics of policy transformation, Critical
Policy
Studies 5: 10626.
Simon, Herbert
A. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice, Quarterly Journal of Economics 69(1): 99118.
—— 1957. Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision-Making Processes in Administrative Organization, 2nd
edn. New York: Macmillan.
Smith, Gilbert. 1994. Policy networks and state autonomy, in S. Brooks and A.-G. Gagnon (eds) The
Political Inuence of Ideas: Policy Communities and the Social Sciences. New York: Praeger.
——and David May. 1980. The articial debate between rationalist and incrementalist models of decision-
making, Policy and Politics 8(2): 14761.
Smith, Martin J. 1993. Pressure, Power and Policy: State Autonomy and Policy Networks in Britain and the United
States. Aldershot: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Stillman, Peter G. 1974. The concept of legitimacy, Polity 7(1): 3256.
Torgerson, Douglas. 1986. Between knowledge and politics: Three faces of policy analysis, Policy Sciences
19(1): 3359.
The policy-making process
27
Tuohy, Caroline. 1992. Policy and Politics in Canada: Institutionalized Ambivalence. Philadelphia, PA: Temple
University Press.
Tupper, Allan and G.B. Doern. 1981. Public corporations and public policy in Canada, in Allan Tupper
and G.B. Doern (eds) Public Corporations and Public Policy in Canada. Montreal: Institute for Research on
Public Policy: 150.
van Waarden, F. 1992. Dimensions and types of policy networks, European Journal of Political Research
21(1/2): 2952.
Vedung, Evert. 1997. Policy instruments: Typologies and theories, in M.L. Bemelmans-Videc, R.C. Rist
and E. Vedung (eds). Carrots, Sticks and Sermons: Policy Instruments and Their Evaluation. New Brunswick,
NJ: Transaction Publishers: 2158.
Vogel, David. 1986. National Styles of Regulation: Environmental Policy in Great Britain and the United States.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Weiss, Carol H. 1977. Using Social Research in Public Policy Making. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
Woodside, K. 1986. Policy instruments and the study of public policy, Canadian Journal of Political Science
19(4): 77593.
Wu, Xun, M. Ramesh, Michael Howlett and Scott Fritzen. 2010. The Public Policy Primer: Managing Public
Policy. London: Routledge.
Howlett and Giest
28
3
Comparative approaches to the
study of public policy-making
Sophie Schmitt
Introduction: what is comparative public policy analysis?
Scholars of comparative public policy are interested in systematically studying public policies
and their origins in order to gain a better understanding of the causes, factors and institutional or
actor constellations that bring about dierent kinds of policy decisions. They try to advance our
understanding of the processes and determinants of public policy-making by comparing the
situations and contexts that lead policy-makers to agree on similar or diverging policies. In this vein,
these analyses include comparisons over time and/or over units (comparing, for example, national,
state or local governments). In a nutshell, comparative policy researchers seek to explain why
and under what conditions policy-makers agree on what policies (see, for example, Lerner and
Lasswell 1951; Windho-Héritier 1987; Howlett and Ramesh 2003). In an oft-cited denition,
Dye describes public policy as whatever governments choose to do or not to do (1976: 1). A
review of a number of subdisciplines of comparative public policy analysis shows that scholars of
dierent research traditions employ dierent strategies in order to probe this inclusive and vast
denition of public policy in both theoretical and empirical respects. While policy science
covers a broad eld that includes analyses of actors, institutions, instruments, programs, decision-
making processes, policy implementation or evaluation from various theoretical perspectives
(cf. Mayntz 1983; Howlett and Ramesh 2003), the analytical focus of the literature on
comparative policy analysis is on the policy decisions themselves and the explanatory factors.
Research on comparative policy-making can be classied into three groups according to its
analytical focus. First, while a number of approaches aim to compare public policies as such, other
subdisciplines address the patterns of policy-making or the decision-making processes from a com-
parative perspective. In this context, the rst category covers the entire policy change literature,
which is rather fragmented with regard to the dierent approaches for conceptualizing and dening
the subject of study (public policy).
Second, the patterns of policy-making are at the focus of scholars of policy diusion, policy
convergence, policy termination or policy dismantling. Whereas the policy diusion perspective
departs from the patterns of spread and the mechanisms of policy change, the policy con-
vergence literature does not try to explain the individual policy-making behavior of govern-
ments but focuses on the degree of similarity their policy decisions reach over time. Scholars of
29
policy termination and of policy dismantling compare decisions to completely or partially revoke
policies introduced in the past.
Third, the process-oriented strands of comparative policy research focus on particular expla-
natory factors or causes that determine the decision-making of governments. In this context,
research on policy learning or lesson-drawing analyzes how policy actors perceive and process
policy experiences made elsewhere, while the policy transfer perspective describes and explains
how policies travel from one unit (e.g. nation-state) to another. Institutional analysis is a useful
strategy to assess the impact of institutional constraints (e.g. veto players) on the actors policy
decision.
However, the broad eld of comparative policy research also diverges with respect to the
underlying methodological choices and to the range of causal explanations taken into account.
This has led to contradictory results and a variety of identied factors and constellations that
determine policy-making, its direction, extent and implications. Thus, in order to advance
this eld of research as a whole and to conceptually locate related research within the broader
eld, it is essential to have an overview of its dierent strands of research, approaches and
analytical foci.
This chapter provides a systematic review of the eld of comparative public policy research
with regard to the elds of environmental and social policy. The following sections address rst,
dierent ways of conceptualizing and operationalizing the subject of study (public policy),
second, dierent analytical perspectives of the patterns of public policies, and third, literature with
distinct foci on the processes and explanatory factors of public policy-making. Next, I will provide
a short review of the methods used to compare and analyze decision-making in the elds of
social and environmental policy. I will then conclude with a short discussion of the main strengths
and shortcomings of current approaches to comparing public policy-making over space and
time along with an outlook on the challenges for further research.
Varieties of comparative public policy research: policies, patterns
or processes
The broad eld of comparative public policy research comprises of research perspectives or
traditions, theoretical approaches, empirical scopes and research methods. Numerous sub-
disciplines and perspectives have emerged over the last decades. This development reects the
varietyand probably also limited commensurabilityof the dierent paradigms guiding
scholars of comparative public policy. So far, no dominant approach has emerged. In the fol-
lowing sections, I identify and discuss four dimensions along which studies of comparative
public policy diverge.
Comparing public policies
There is a variety of di erent approaches in the literature to depict and measure the subject of
study, namely public policy. This conceptual heterogeneity delimits the comparability and
consolidation of the ndings.
Scholars of comparative public policy analysis seek to systematically describe and explain the
decisions of dierent governments, their timing and content. To this end, several strategies
have emerged to determine governmental behavior and decisional outputincluding for
instance legislative acts, executive decrees or administrative circulars. A rst group of scholars
measures the impact of policies by analyzing the policies eects on the target of regulation. A
second group of researchers focuses on policy outcomes, namely the immediate consequences of a
Schmitt
30
policy decision, while the third approach refers to policy outputs, namely the content of the
decision. As an example from the social policy eld, one might consider unemployment pro-
tection policies. In this context, the decision to introduce monetary unemployment benets at a
certain level reects the immediate policy output. The same decision could also be approxi-
mated by referring to total government spending on this particular social protection scheme
(i.e. the outcome) or by measuring the eects of the policy decision on the regulatory target,
such as, for instance, the number or the quality of life of unemployed persons (i.e. the impact).
In the eld of environmental policy-making one could consider emission standards for industrial
plants. The denition of the standard itself, such as a limit value for the emission of sulfur
dioxide, connotes the policy output, whereas the policy impact would be measured by the
associated change in industrial emissions and air quality with respect to this particular sub-
stance. These brief examples illustrate the considerable risk of incomparability and incommen-
surability that result from the conceptualization and operationalization of the dependent variable
(government policy decisions). From a policy cycle perspective, policy output on the one
hand and policy outcome or impact on the other refer to dierent stages of the policy process.
While the former is more a part of the policy formulation stage, the latter concepts pertain to
the implementation phase (see Windho-Héritier 1987: 18f; cf. Sabatier and Mazmanian 1980,
Howlett and Ramesh 2003: 143.). There is, however, a divide between policy outputs
and their consequences (outcome and impact) not only with respect to the temporal patterns
but also with regard to the potentially high number of intervening factors that inuence the
eects of policy decisions. It is almost impossible to infer governmental decisions and intentions
based on indirect outcome and impact measures. Jänicke (1992) for instance nds that envir-
onmental policy performance and success crucially depend on institutional arrangements, eco-
nomic structures and international dynamics. Esty and Porter (2005) conducted an extensive
study in which a variety of dierent factors were analyzed to examine their inuence on
environmental performance (outcome data). The authors nd other factors besides institu-
tional arrangements to have an impact on the policy outcome in addition to the policy
outputs themselves including socio-economic and infrastructure-related factors. Thus, as this
example shows, selecting indicators for the subject of analysis or the dependent variable is far
from trivial.
The literature on both social and environmental policy shows that the majority of large-n
comparative studies rely on outcome or impact instead of output measures due to eased data
availability. Wälti (2004), for instance, approximates the dierent nation-states prioritization of
environmental protection by using air quality data on nitrogen and sulfur oxides levels. Others
argue that policy outcomes are the more appropriate and feasible way to measure a governments
commitment toward environmental protection since its willingness to reduce air pollution is not
only reected in single policy decisions (e.g. to lower limit values). It is rather the result of a series
of decisions including institutional ones that cannot be comprehensively assessed by comparing
single policy outputs (see Scruggs 2003: 20.). As a consequence, many scholars have opted for
environmental performance indices that are designed to reect the policy-makers overall
commitment for protecting the environment. These indices are compiled from various outcome
measures. They dier in their breadth in terms of the number of included pollutants (cf. Crepaz
1995; Jänicke 1996; Jahn 1998; Scruggs 1999, 2003).
Impact and outcome measures are also common in the literature on social policy. This might
also be due to the conceptual and notional focus given that most scientists belonging to this area
of research focus on the analysis of the welfare state as a whole rather than the explanation of
single social policies. Analogously to the eld of environmental policy research, policy output
studies are uncommon. Nevertheless, scholars of social policies are usually more careful to
Studying public policy-making
31
distinguish between approaches focusing on outcome measures and those addressing the poli-
cies impact. The former branch of research usually seeks to indirectly measure the politicians
commitment with respect to certain policy elds while the latter research takes more the form
of program evaluation studies. Outcome indicators in the eld of social policy dier with regard
to their conceptual closeness to the underlying policy decision.
On rather abstract levels, data on public expenditure allow for the comparison of public
commitment to policies, governments or time. Expenditure data are usually easily available proxies
for policy decisions. They are often used in quantitative comparative studies (cf. Stephens et al.
1999; Huber and Stephens 2001; Castles 2004, 2009; Clasen and Siegel 2007). However, as
with the case of environmental policy the direct linkage between policy outputs and outcomes
is questionable. A number of authors nd alternative factors that have an impact on public
spending levels (Wilensky 1974; Castles and Mitchell 1992; Pierson 1996; Castles 1999; Kit-
schelt 2001; Allan and Scruggs 2004). The comparison between the politics of pension reform
and unemployment protection, for instance, illustrates the complex interplay between socio-
economic conditions, government action and welfare expenditure and the risk of endogeneity
for the resulting analyses. On the one hand, demographic change and aging of the population
are likely to trigger policy-making by governments which then translates into (expected)
expenditure levels for this specic social policy program (Bonoli 2000). On the other hand,
socio-economic conditions might also lead decision-makers to adapt unemployment protection
policies. This is quite evident in the eld of unemployment policies, where altered rates of
unemployment directly impact on the resulting expenditure levels of the protection scheme
(Allan and Scruggs 2004). Again, these developments might motivate policymakers to take
action (Vis 2009). As these brief examples show, multidirectional eects cause problems of
endogeneity which in turn pose serious risks for the validity of the ndings obtained from such
analyses. Furthermore, expenditure analyses entail the risk of omissions, as stable outcome levels of
social policy might obscure underlying changes due to altered contexts (e.g. higher unemployment
replacement rates that coincide with lower unemployment rates, cf. Knill et al. 2010).
As a consequence of these problems and the goal to more closely reect actual political deci-
sions, scholars have turned toward the measurement of replacement rates instead of cumulated
expenditure levels (Martin 1996; Green-Pedersen 2004; Swank 2005; Clasen and Clegg 2007;
Kühner 2007). Replacement rates refer to the amount of monetary compensation paid to
retirees, unemployed persons or those unable to work because of illness. Social generosity from
this perspective is operationalized through the benet levels (e.g. pension, unemployment or
child allowances) for such people, usually industrial workers (Allan and Scruggs 2004). This strategy
allows for consistent cross-country or cross-time comparisons for certain sub-aspects of policy-
making. A major problem with this approach is that available data on replacement levels cover
only few aspects of the policy. On the one hand, the use of replacement rates is biased toward
policy decisions with monetary implications. On the other hand, by focusing on the benets for
representative standard employees, such studies often also neglect the full range of policy deci-
sions with regard to the dierent levels of benets. Thus, cross-country comparisons on the
basis of replacement rate indicators only incur serious risk of biased results due the systematic
focus on the monetary implications of social policies (Whiteford 1995; Lynch 2001; Bonoli
2007; Scruggs 2007; Knill et al. 2010).
The recent literature on social policy-making, however, shows a number of more sophisticated
ne-grained analytical frames to study and compare policy-making in dierent countries. Immergut
et al. (2007) as well as Häusermann (2010) systematically analyze and compare policy decisions
in the eld of pension politics in dierent countries. Altogether, the decision of how to con-
ceptualize and measure the subject of study (i.e. public policy) is of crucial relevance as it impacts
Schmitt
32
on the ability to describe and explain public policy-making. The comparative approach
often requires a certain degree of pragmatism and simplication with respect to the oper-
ationalization of the underlying conceptsparticularly when it comes to designing quantitative
large-n studies. However, as this brief overview of dierent ways of conceptualizing and oper-
ationalizing the dependent variables in comparisons of public policy-making illustrates, these
decisions might considerably inuence the validity of the ndings due to the choice of variables
and indicators.
In this context, policy (change) analyses with a direct focus on policy output are one way to
assess the underlying decision-making of governmentshence covering various stages of the
policy cycle including agenda-setting, policy formulation and decision-making (see Howlett and
Ramesh 2003: 162). They represent the eventual consensus that has been reached by the group
of involved policy actors. Policy outcome studies are based on rather indirect measures of the
underlying policy decisions. These include performance indices or pollution data for certain sub-
stances and expenditure data for the elds of environmental and social policy, respectively.
Given the supposedly complex processes that account for the outcomes, the direction of causal
mechanisms is far from evident, which again creates risks of endogeneity. Scholars of quantita-
tive comparative environmental policy research have partly acknowledged this challenge by
including certain policy outputs (e.g. limit values for emission) as only one set of explanatory fac-
tors for predicting policy outcomes (see above; cf. in particular Esty and Porter 2005). Nevertheless,
given the bi-directional causation between policy output and outcome, one could argue that
policy outcomes are crucial in explaining follow-up policy-making. As outcomes reect the
eectiveness of previous policy decisions (through records of either nancial expenditure or
pollution) they might also create incentives for future policy-making.
Furthermore, the heterogeneity of the dierent approaches found in the literature impacts on the
degree of comparability of the results of dierent studies themselves. Even within the subeld of
outcome studies, there are currently many dierent strategies to design environmental perfor-
mance indices or to compile expenditure indicators for social policies. This arbitrariness might
explain the limited comparability and inconsistency of the ndings.
Comparing patterns of public policy-making
The above discussion on the dierent ways to conceptualize and operationalize public policies
in comparative research on environmental and social policy-making illustrates that governmental
behavior and decision-making can be measured at dierent levels of abstraction depending on
the scientic aim of the research endeavor. As a consequence of the diculty in comparing the
policy-making behavior of governments in its entirety, various research traditions have emerged
to analyze and compare public policies from distinct perspectives. In this section, I present and
discuss three dierent research traditions that analyze public policy-making from a comparative
perspective by taking a particular analytical lens and focusing on the observed patterns of policy
change or adoption.
First, studies of public policy can be classied according to the direction or range of policy
change that follows from a governments choices. While the majority of scholars include positive
as well as negative decisions in the analysis, scholars of policy termination or dismantling focus exclu-
sively on decisions that are of reductive nature through the partial or complete abolishment of
policies.
Research on policy termination was initiated by Brewer in the early 1970s with the objective
directing scientic attention toward this nal stage of the policy cycle process. He dened this
type of policy choice as those adjusting policies and programs that have become dysfunctional,
Studying public policy-making
33
redundant, outmoded, and/or unnecessary (Brewer 1978: 338). His initiative led to a vital but
short-lived scholarly reaction to analytically advance research into this aspect of policy-making
(cf. Bardach 1976; Biller 1976; Behn 1978; deLeon 1978; Hogwood and Peters 1982). Despite
persistent theoretical problems and inconsistencies, a number of empirical studies followed
(e.g. Frantz 1992; Daniels 1995, 2001; deLeon and Hernández-Quezada 2001; Geva-May 2001;
Harris 2001; Graddy and Ye 2008). The policy termination approach develops types or forms of
policy termination that are of dierent scope and that are debated between groups of opponents
and proponents of dierent strengths (cf. in particular Bardach 1976).
Policy dismantling is a related concept in that it focuses on policy decisions to reduce public
generosity (distributive policies like social policy) or water down the rigidity of regulatory
policies (e.g. environmental policies). Policy dismantling has initially been studied in the context
of welfare state analyses. Scholarly attention has continuously been at a high level since Piersons
seminal book (1994). So far, various methods have been applied to analyze such policy decisions
mainly in the eld of social or welfare state policy (e.g. Esping-Andersen 1996; Clayton and
Pontusson 1998; Bonoli 2001; Kitschelt 2001; Green-Pedersen 2002; Korpi and Palme 2003;
Hacker 2004; Starke 2006, Starke et al. 2008).
A second criterion for case selection is based on the empirically observed patterns of spread of
certain policy innovations. The broad literature of policy diusion seeks to explain the dissemination
of certain policies among units at dierent levels (i.e. nation-states, states or local entities) by
identifying causes and factors that promote policy diusion. In order to reduce complexity in
comparing public policy-making over cases or units, policy diusion scholars analyze single
policies or policy innovations by describing the underlying adoption patterns over time and
units. Assuming that policy choices are interdependent (e.g. Braun and Gilardi 2006: 299),
diusion scholars try to explain the spread of policies by identifying the relevant domestic and
international factors at work. This way, diusion scholars seek to estimate the international
inuence on domestic policy decisions (cf. Frank et al. 2000; Busch et al. 2005; Elkins and
Simmons 2005; Elkins et al. 2006). Since its emergence in the 1970s (Gray 1973; Collier and
Messick 1975), policy diusion research has become ever more sophisticated especially with respect
to the development of ambitious research methods to detect diusion channels (cf. Tyran and
Sausgruber 2005; Brooks 2007; Volden et al. 2008; Marsh and Sharman 2009; Plümper and
Neumayer 2010).
Third, the policy convergence perspective is another way of comparing the patterns of policy-
making of dierent nation-states, states or local entities by focusing on and explaining the
degree of similarity they reach over time as a consequence of passing policies of similar
contents (Bennett 1991; Knill 2005). This rather indirect analysis of public policies does not
seek to explain the actual decision of a government but how it changes the status quo in rela-
tion to other cases (e.g. nation-states). There are a number of studies dealing with the degree of
transnational convergence in the elds of environmental and social policy (cf. Heichel et al.
2005; Jordan 2005; cf. Overbye 1994; Howlett 2000; Starke et al. 2008). The analytical moti-
vation of convergence scholars has often been twofold: to describe the dynamics of policy
change over time and in relation to other units, and to explain the observed patterns. This way,
they address the question of whether and under which conditions globalization leads to races
to the top or races to the bottom in for instance the adoption of environmental policies (see
e.g. Holzinger et al. 2008; cf. Drezner 2001, 2005; Busch and Jörgens 2005; Holzinger and
Knill 2005).
This brief summary of dierent analytical strands, that each address certain sub-aspects of policy-
making from a comparative perspective, highlights the complexity of the subject of investiga-
tion. Comparing public policies over space and time often requires narrowing the analytical lens
Schmitt
34
in favor of a more selective focus on policy-making. As a consequence of this conceptual sim-
plication the above approaches suer from certain theoretical limitations that impede on the
generalizability of the results with respect to public policy-making in general.
First, the risk of biased results cannot be excluded due to the one-directional analysis of
policy-making that is inherent to, for instance, the subdisciplines of policy dismantling, policy
termination and policy diusion research. While the former two perspectives make statements
about government decisions of reductive nature, the latter have traditionally exclusively dealt
with expansion policies (although this does not occur by denition).
Second, biases are likely to aect those studies that select their subject of study (i.e. the policy)
based on its empirically observed distribution. In other words, results from diusion studies
might only allow for valid inference with respect to policies that have reached a certain degree
of dissemination. Policies that do not reach the stage of a best practice are ex ante excluded
from analysis, which is why large-n diusion studies are most likely to overestimate the impact
of international factors, such as harmonization (for a critical analysis of the limitations of this
particular research perspective cf. Howlett and Rayner 2008).
Comparing processes of public policy-making
In the following paragraphs, I will provide a further criterion along which to classify the lit-
erature on comparative public policy: the processes and factors of public policy-making. While
the conceptualization and operationalization of the dependent variable (see above) crucially inu-
ences the validity of the ndings, the selection of policies according to their patterns of spread
(see above) primarily impacts on the generalizability of the results toward public policy-making
in general.
There are several subdisciplines of comparative research on public policies that explain policy
decisions or outputs by focusing on selective explanatory factors or processes. These include
scholars of policy learning and policy transfer as well as research on political institutions. One
common feature of these studies is the objective to analyze and compare the respective pro-
cesses of the decision-making and the behavior of the involved actors. As a consequence, the
results of these studies are often ex ante focused on specic explanations.
One way of narrowing down the empirical focus of comparative public policy analysis can be
found within the literatures on policy learning, policy transfer or emulation. Scholars belonging to
these research traditions identify certain mechanisms or factors that cause the dissemination of
policies with the aim of tracing and explaining the underlying processes. Similarly to the diu-
sion perspective, they describe the way in which policies travel from one unit (e.g. nation-state) to
another by focusing on distinct mechanisms or ways of communication. As opposed to the
previously discussed research perspective, policy transfer, learning or emulation take a process
orientation. In this context, policy learning (or lesson-drawing) refers to instances in which gov-
ernments adopt a certain policy based on the evaluation of a policy in place elsewhere (for a
thorough discussion of dierent forms of horizontal and vertical learning see Bennett and Howlett
1992; cf. Sabatier 1987; Rose 1991, 1993; Hall 1993; Meseguer 2006, 2009; Radaelli 2008).
Further, lesson-drawing may cause governments to decide on policies found elsewhere as trans-
fers can be voluntary or coercive or combinations thereof (Stone 2001: 9). Thus, the policy
transfer literature analyzes the role of actors by pointing to the importance of interest groups,
NGOs, think tanks, non-state policy entrepreneurs (as transfer agents) and the role of policy
networks in promoting the diusion of ideas and their intersubjective perceptions of solutions as
well as in providing social learning and building up epistemic communities (cf. Dolowitz and
Marsh 1996, 2000, Radaelli 2000; Stone 2000, 2001, 2004). Cases of negative lesson-drawing,
Studying public policy-making
35
in turn, might also lead governments to deliberately exclude policy options found elsewhere
(cf. Rose 1991, 1993).
The literature subsumed under the label of institutionalism provides another framework for the
analysis of government choices by explaining policies and their content based on the institu-
tional conditions that channel the decision-making processes. The point of departure of this
approach is veto players, individual or collective decision-makers whose agreement is required
for the change of the status quo (Tsebelis 2000: 442). According to this view, policy-making is
best explained by the systematic analysis of the institutional rules that delimit the actors leeway
and inuence on the eventual policy decision (cf. Tsebelis 1995; Hall and Taylor 1996; Scharpf
1997; Jupille and Caporaso 1999). Veto player (Bonoli 2001; Immergut and Anderson 2007)
and institution-centered analysis (Swank 2001; Streeck and Thelen 2005) are common approa-
ches in the comparative analysis of, for instance, social policy change. As the veto players
approach emphasizes the ways in which political decision-making institutions structure attempts
to change the legislative status quo (Immergut and Anderson 2007: 7), it allows for explaining
policy dierences between units (e.g. nation-states) for a range of issues. There are a number of
studies that illustrate the role of the fragmentation of political power (horizontal or vertical) for
reforming the pension systems of Western democracies (cf. Bonoli 2001, 2004; Swank 2001;
Baccaro 2002; Ferrera 2007; Baccaro and Simoni 2008; Häusermann 2010).
Research of comparative public policies that belong to the sub-disciplines of policy learning,
policy transfer or institutional analysis puts the analytical focus on understanding and describing
the processes that impact on and shape the policy decisions. As a consequence, the empirical
results of these studies might be of limited generalizability to policy-making in its complexity.
Given the individual conceptual points of departure, scholars belonging to these research traditions
are at risk to overestimate the inuence of certain explanatory concepts either through poten-
tially biased case selection (policy learning or transfer) or by the analytical focus on one expla-
nation only (institutionalism). As studies pertaining to these research traditions tend to select
their cases according to specic causal processes, their ndings might not hold for explaining
policy-making in general.
Altogether, the degree of specicity of the dependent variable diers over the analytical per-
spectives discussed in the previous two sections, which furthermore reduces the generalizability
of the results for public policy-making.
While transfer and diusion studies solely explain whether a certain policy has been passed or
not, policy learning studies allow for a more detailed conceptual calibration. Similarly, the analy-
tical precision of policy termination studies is rather low; dismantling or retrenchment studies in
turn apply rened conceptual approaches by considering dierent sub-aspects of policy outputs.
Policy convergence in this context, also allows for a multidimensional perspective on the depen-
dent variable (i.e. a governments decisions with respect to a range of regulatory aspects; e.g. the
emission standards designed to assess a countrys prioritization of regulating air quality). Never-
theless, they provide only indirect and selective accounts of the governments actual decisions
because they measure policy-making not in absolute terms but with respect to a certain threshold
(i.e. the average policy output of the sample included in the analysis).
Research methods and causal explanations in comparative public policy
There is a large number of empirical studies that analyze social and environmental policies based
on dierent methodologies (qualitative versus quantitative) and levels of analysis (micro versus
macro). Interestingly, the methodological lines of division are almost identical to the ones
separating the various research traditions discussed above.
Schmitt
36
More precisely, the question of whether to study policy outcomes instead of policy outputs is
predominantly an issue for scholars of quantitative research. Given the diculty of constructing
and obtaining comparable measures for policy-making over large numbers of cases, macro-
quantitative studies often switch to outcome indicators due to improved data availability. How-
ever, authors of case studies (e.g. Weidner and Jänicke 2002; Jordan et al. 2003; Jordan and
Lieerink 2004; Busch and Jörgens 2005; Hall 1993; Kersbergen 1995; Huber and Stephens 2001;
Taylor-Gooby 2004) seem to be less aected by the dependent variable problem (Green-
Pedersen 2004; Clasen and Siegel 2007; cf. Howlett and Cashore 2009) by taking a micro-analytical
perspective.
The division between quantitative and qualitative studies continues also within the dierent
subdisciplines of comparative public policy research as discussed earlier in this chapter. In this
context, policy learning and lesson-drawing are mostly addressed through comparative case
study designs (for an exception see Sommerer 2010), while diusion is often analyzed through
large-n designs (but see, for example, Tews et al. 2003).
The policy change literature also reects the methodological divide. While the policy termi-
nation literature almost exclusively consists of comparative case studies, welfare state retrench-
ment research of policy outcomes (comprising studies based on expenditure or replacement rate
data) usually involves large-n studies. In this context, analyses of the dismantling or termination
of environmental policies are still in general the exception (but see, for example, Knill et al.
2008). While research on policy dismantling or termination tends to overestimate the factors
that lead to negative policy choices, the diusion and transfer literature is biased toward policy
innovations and positive policy decisions, respectively. In spite of this potential bias, there have
been hardly any eorts in comparative analyses of social or environmental policies to system-
atically compare policy outputs of both directions, with the possible exception of the literature
on policy convergence. As already mentioned, output studies that provide in-depth analyses of
policies or policy change in social or environmental policy are almost exclusively limited to
qualitative case studies due to their conceptual and empirical complexity.
The literature on comparative social and environmental policy shows biases with respect to the
explanatory factors taken into account. Policy diusion, convergence or welfare- state retrench-
ment studies in these policy elds, for instance, tend to take a macro perspective focusing par-
ticularly on the eects of globalization and economic pressure (Castles 1998; Drezner 2001;
Sykes et al. 2001; Weidner and Jänicke 2002; Korpi and Palme 2003; Stone 2004; Swank 2005;
Holzinger et al. 2008). Looking at the role of political parties for public policy-making (from a
meso perspective), for instance, there is an interesting fragmentation between the literatures on
environmental and social policy. While this factor has received abundant attention in research
on the welfare state in general and welfare state retrenchment in particular (e.g. Huber and
Stephens 2001; Kitschelt 2001; Green-Pedersen 2002, 2007; Korpi and Palme 2003; Allan and
Scruggs 2004; Vis and Kersbergen 2007; Vis 2009), it has less frequently been studied in the
context of environmental policy-making (but see Shipan and Lowry 2001; Knill et al. 2010).
Similarly, the two elds of research dier with respect to the incorporation of institutional
explanations for policy-making. The concept of veto players is often applied to analyze reforms
of the welfare state and to explain the feasibility of cutbacks in public generosity (Bonoli 2001;
Crepaz 2001; Ganghof 2003; Immergut et al. 2007; Ha 2008). However, it is a concept scarcely
addressed in comparative analyses of environmental policy research (for an exception see Jahn
and Müller-Rommel 2010). In addition, institutional factors have received limited attention in
this eld of research (but see Dryzek et al. 2003).
This brief overview on the methods used and causal explanations tested in the analysis of
social and environmental policy-making points to systematic dierences between the approaches
Studying public policy-making
37
used in the two policy elds. Choices of methods and explanatory factors, which determine the
comparability of results, seem to be related to both the analytical perspective on the dependent
variable and the eld of research (e.g. social or environmental policy). These patterns of com-
parative policy research illustrate the internal fragmentation of this scientic discipline and the
limits of generalizability of its ndings.
Discussion and outlook
This brief presentation and discussion of dierent approaches toward the study of public policies
from the comparative perspective shows that we are still far from academic consensus with
respect to the meaning of the term public policy itself and in view of the range of explanatory
factors to be considered. Scholars of comparative public policy usually make an implicit statement
through either the conceptualization of the dependent variable, case selection based on certain
policy patterns, by focusing on certain processes or by choosing specic explanatory concepts.
These choices entail fundamental consequences for the expected degree of generalizability of
the results and the scope of explanation (see below Table 3.1).
On the one hand, process-oriented approaches toward public policy-making reveal a ten-
dency to focus on the explanatory factors (i.e. lesson-drawing, transfer or institutional determi-
nants in this context). On the other hand, pattern-oriented studies (termination, dismantling,
and diusion) tend to put more analytical emphasis on explaining and comparing certain types
of public policies themselves. Both subdisciplines share the narrow perspective on the subject of
study, i.e. public policy-making. As a consequence, the approaches are limited to policies with
certain characteristics or policy aspects. In this context, the literatures on policy learning, transfer
or institutional change consider policies that are inuenced by distinct explanatory factors. Policy
termination and policy dismantling studies incorporate exclusively negative policy decisions,
while research on policy diusion is biased toward policy innovations that have reached a certain
degree of dissemination.
These features might limit the generalizability of all these approaches. The policy change
literature claims to broaden the analysis of policy-makingat least theoreticallyby means
of an inclusive conceptualization of the dependent variable and explanatory processes and
factors (for a discussion of the decits in current policy change research, see Howlett and
Cashore 2009). As shown, however, in the discussion on the dierent ways to conceptualize
Table 3.1 Subdisciplines of comparative public policy research
Focus on generalizability
Low High
Focus on Explanans Policy termination Policy change
(outcome/impact analyses)
Policy dismantling
Policy diffusion
Explanandum Policy learning Policy change
(output analyses)
Policy transfer
Institutionalism
Source: Author
Schmitt
38
and measure public policies in practice, the policy change perspective also has its limits of
comparability.
This fragmentation in current public policy analysis illustrates the potential benets of more
integrated approaches that on the one hand, give primary attention to a more careful con-
ceptualization of the subject of research and comparison. On the other hand, the ndings call for
more exible combinations of research perspectives, methods, and dierent explanatory factors in
both elds of research. This would enhance the generalizability and the validity of the ndings and
enable theoretical progress to be made based on the consolidation of the dierent approaches.
Bibliography
Allan, J.P. and L. Scruggs. 2004. Political partisanship and welfare state reform in advanced industrial
societies, American Journal of Political Science 48(3): 496512.
Baccaro, L. 2002. Negotiating the Italian pension reform with the unions: Lessons for corporatist theory
Industrial and Labor Relations Review 55(3): 41331.
——and M. Simoni. 2008. Policy concertation in Europe: Understanding government choice, Comparative
Political Studies 41(10): 132348.
Bardach, E. 1976. Policy termination as a political process, Policy Sciences 7(2): 12331.
Behn, R.D. 1978. How to terminate a public policy: A dozen hints for the would-be terminate, Policy
Analyses 4(3): 393-413.
Bennett, C.J. 1991. What is policy convergence and what causes it?, British Journal of Political Science 21(2):
21533.
——and M. Howlett. 1992. The lessons of learning: Reconciling theories of policy learning and policy
change, Policy Sciences 25(3): 27594.
Biller, R.P. 1976. On tolerating policy and organizational termination: Some design considerations, Policy
Sciences 7(2): 13349.
Bonoli, G. 2000. The Politics of Pension Reform: Institutions and Policy Change in Western Europe. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
—— 2001. Political institutions, veto points, and the process of welfare state adaptation, in P. Pierson
(ed.) The New Politics of the Welfare State. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 23864.
—— 2004. The institutionalization of the Swiss multi-pillar pension system,inM.ReinandW.Schmähl(eds)
Rethinking the Welfare State: The Political Economy of Pension Reform. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar, 10221.
—— 2007. Too
narrow and too
wide at once: The welfare state as dependent variable in policy ana-
lysis, in J. Clasen and N.A. Siegel (eds) Investigating Welfare State Change: The Dependent Variable Problem in
Comparative Analysis. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2442.
Braun, D. and F. Gilardi. 2006. Taking Galtons problem seriously: Towards a theory of Policy diusion.
Journal of Theoretical Politics 18(3): 298322.
Brewer, G.D. 1978. Termination: Hard choicesharder questions, Public Administration Review 38(4): 33844.
Brooks, S.M. 2007. When does diusion matter? Explaining the spread of structural pension reforms
across nations, The Journal of Politics 69(3): 70115.
Busch, P.-O. and H. Jörgens. 2005. International patterns of environmental policy change and convergence,
European Environment 15(2): 80101.
—— H. Jörgens and K. Tews. 2005. The global diusion of regulatory instruments: The making of a new
international environmental regime, The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science
598(1): 14667.
Castles, F.G. 1998. Comparative Public Policy: Patterns of Post-war Transformation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
—— 1999. Decentralisation and the post-war political economy, European Journal of Political Research
36(1): 2753.
—— 2004. The Future of the Welfare State: Crisis Myths and Crisis Realities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
—— 2009. What welfare states do: A disaggregated expenditure approach, Journal
of Social Policy 38,
4562.
——and D. Mitchell. 1992. Identifying welfare state regimes: The links between politics, instruments and
outcomes, Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 5(1): 126.
Clasen, J. and D. Clegg. 2007. Levels and levers of conditionality: Measuring change within welfare
states, in J. Clasen and N.A. Siegel (eds) Investigating Welfare State Change: The Dependent Variable Problem
in Comparative Analysis. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 16697.
Studying public policy-making
39
——and N.A. Siegel (eds). 2007. Investigating Welfare State Change: The Dependent Variable Problem in
Comparative Analysis. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Clayton, R. and J. Pontusson. 1998. Welfare-state retrenchment revisited: Entitlement cuts, public sector
restructuring, and inegalitarian trends in advanced capitalist societies, World Politics 51(1): 6798.
Collier, D. and R.E. Messick. 1975. Prerequisites versus diusion: Testing alternative explanations of
social security adoption, The American Political Science Review 69(4): 1299315.
Crepaz, M.M.L. 1995. Explaining national variations of air pollution levels: Political institutions and their
impact on environmental policy-making, Environmental Politics 4(3): 391414.
—— 2001. Veto players, globalization and the redistributive capacity of the state: A panel study of 15
OECD countries, Journal of Public Policy 21(1): 122.
Daniels, M.R. 1995. Organizational termination and policy continuation: Closing the Oklahoma public
training schools, Policy Sciences 28(3): 30116.
—— 2001. Policy and organizational termination, International Journal of Public Administration 24(3): 24962.
deLeon, P. 1978. Public policy termination: An end and a beginning, Policy Analyses 4(3): 36992.
——and J.M. Hernández-Quezada. 2001. The case of the national solidarity program in Mexico. A study
in comparative public policy termination, International Journal of Public Administration 24(3): 289309.
Dolowitz, D.P. and D. Marsh. 1996. Who learns what from whom: A review of the policy transfer literature,
Political Studies 44(2): 34357.
—— 2000. Learning
from abroad: The
role of policy transfer in contemporary policy making, Governance:
An International Journal of Policy and Administration 13(1): 524.
Drezner, D.W. 2001. Globalization and policy convergence, International Studies Review 3(1): 5378.
—— 2005. Globalization, harmonization, and competition: The dierent pathways to policy convergence,
Journal of European Public Policy 12(5): 84159.
Dryzek, J.S., D. Downes, C. Hunold and D. Schlosberg. 2003. Green States and Social Movements: Envir-
onmentalism in the United States, United Kingdom, Germany, and Norway. Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press.
Dye, T.R. 1976. Policy Analysis: What Governments Do, Why They Do it, and What Dierence it Makes.
Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.
Elkins, Z., A.T. Guzman and B.A. Simmons. 2006. Competing for capital: The diusion of bilateral
investment treaties, 19602000, International Organization 60(4): 81146.
—— and B. Simmons 2005. On waves, clusters, and diusion: A conceptual framework, The Annals of
the American Academy of Political and Social Science 598(1): 3351.
EspingAndersen, G. (ed.). 1996. Welfare States in Transition: National Adaptations in Global Economies.
London and Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Esty, D.C. and M.E. Porter. 2005. National environmental performance: An empirical analysis of policy
results and determinants, Environment and Development Economics 10(4): 391434.
Ferrera, M. 2007. The European welfare state. Golden achievements and silver prospects, URGE
working paper, 4/07.
——and M. Jessoul. 2007. Italy: A narrow gate for path-shift, in E.M. Immergut, K.M. Anderson and
I. Schulze (eds) The Handbook of West European Pension Politics. Oxford, New York: Oxford University
Press, 396453.
Frank, D.J., A. Hironaka and E. Schofer. 2000. The
nation-state and the
natural environment over the
twentieth century, American Sociological Review 65(1): 96116.
Frantz, J.E. 1992. Reviving and revising a termination model, Policy Sciences 25(2): 17589.
Ganghof, S. 2003. Promises and pitfalls of veto player analysis , Swiss Political Science Review 9(2): 125.
Geva-May, I. 2001. When the motto is till death do us part: The conceptualization and the craft of
termination in the public policy cycle, International Journal of Public Administration 24(3): 26388.
Graddy, E.A. and K. Ye. 2008. When do we just say no? Policy termination decisions in local hospital
services, Policy Studies Journal 36(2): 21942.
Gray, V. 1973. Innovation in the states: A diusion study, The American Political Science Review 67(4):
117485.
Green-Pedersen, C. 2002. The Politics of Justi cation: Party Competition and Welfare-state Retrenchment in
Denmark and the Netherlands from 1982 to 1998. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.
—— 2004. The dependent variable problem within the study of welfare state retrenchment: dening the
problem and looking for solutions, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 6(1): 314.
—— 2007. More than data questions and methodological issues: Theoretical conceptualization and the
dependent variable problem in the study of welfare reform, in J. Clasen and N.A. Siegel (eds)
Schmitt
40
Investigating Welfare State Change: The Dependent Variable Problem in Comparative Analysis. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar, 1323.
Ha, E. 2008. Globalization, veto players, and welfare spending, Comparative Political Studies 41(6): 783813.
Hacker, J.S. 2004. Privatizing risk without privatizing the welfare state: The hidden politics of social
policy retrenchment in the United States, American Political Science Review 98(2): 24360.
Hall, P.A. 1993. Policy paradigms, social learning, and the state: The case of economic policymaking in
Britain, Comparative Politics 25(3): 27596.
——and R.C.R. Taylor. 1996. Political science and the three new institutionalisms, Political Studies 44(5):
93657.
Harris, M. 2001. Policy termination: The case of term limits in Michigan, International Journal of Public
Administration 24(3): 16580.
Häusermann, S. 2010. The Politics of Welfare State Reform in Continental Europe: Modernization in Hard Times.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heichel, S., J. Pape and T. Sommerer. 2005. Is there convergence in convergence research? An overview
of empirical studies on policy convergence, Journal of European Public Policy 12(5): 81740.
Hogwood, B.W. and G.B. Peters. 1982. The dynamics of policy change: policy succession, Policy Sciences
14(3): 22545.
Holzinger, K. and C. Knill. 2005. Causes and conditions of cross-national policy convergence, Journal of
European Public Policy 12(5): 77596.
——, C. Knill and T. Sommerer. 2008. Environmental policy convergence: The impact of international
harmonization, transnational communication, and regulatory competition, International Organization 62
(4): 55387.
Howlett,
M. 2000. Beyond legalism?
Policy ideas, implementation styles and emulation-based convergence
in Canadian and US environmental policy, Journal of Public Policy 20(3): 30529.
——and B. Cashore. 2009. The dependent variable problem in the study of policy change: Under-
standing policy change as a methodological problem, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 11(1): 3346.
——and M. Ramesh. 2003. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. Toronto: Oxford
University Press.
——and J. Rayner. 2008. Third generation policy diusion studies and the analysis of policy mixes: Two
steps forward and one step back?, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 10(4): 385402.
Huber, E. and J.D. Stephens. 2001. Development and Crisis of the Welfare State Parties and Policies in Global
Markets. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Immergut, E.M. and K.M. Anderson 2007. Editors introduction: the dynamics of pension politics,in
E.M. Immergut, K.M. Anderson and I. Schulze (eds) The Handbook of West European Pension Politics.
Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 145.
——, K.M. Anderson and I. Schulze (eds). 2007. The Handbook of West European Pension Politics. Oxford,
New York: Oxford University Press.
Jahn, D. 1998. Environmental performance and policy regimes: Explaining variations in 18 OECD-countries,
Policy Sciences 31: 10731.
——and F. Müller-Rommel. 2010. Political institutions and policy performance: A comparative analysis
of Central and Eastern Europe, Journal of Public Policy 30(1): 2344.
Jänicke, M. 1992. Conditions for environmental policy success: An international comparison, The Environmentalist
12(1): 4758.
——(ed.). 1996. Umweltpolitik der Industrieländer: Entwicklung BilanzErfolgsbedingungen. Berlin: Sigma.
Jordan, A. 2005. Policy
convergence: A passing fad or a new integrating focus in European Union studies?,
Journal of European
Public Policy 12(5): 94453.
Jordan, A. and D. Lieerink (eds). 2004. Environmental Policy in Europe: The Europeanization of National
Environmental Policy. London and New York: Routledge.
——, R.K.W. Wurzel and A.R. Zito (eds). 2003. ‘“New Instruments of Environmental Governance? National
Experiences and Prospects. London and Portland, OR: Frank Cass.
Jupille, J. and J. Caporaso. 1999. Institutionalism and the European Union: Beyond international relations
and comparative politics, Annual Review of Political Science 2: 42944.
Kersbergen, K. van 1995. Social Capitalism: A Study of Christian Democracy and the Welfare State. London and
New York: Routledge.
Kitschelt, H. 2001. Partisan competition and welfare state retrenchment: When do politicians choose
unpopular policies?, in P. Pierson (ed.) The New Politics of the Welfare State. Oxford, New York: Oxford
University Press, pp. 265302.
Studying public policy-making
41
Knill, C. 2005. Introduction: Cross-national policy convergence: Concepts, approaches and explanatory
factors, Journal of European Public Policy 12(5): 76474.
——, J. Tosun and S. Heichel. 2008. Balancing competitiveness and conditionality: Environmental policy
making in low-regulating countries, Journal of European Public Policy 15(7): 101940.
——, M. Debus and S. Heichel. 2010. Do parties matter in internationalised policy areas? The impact of
political parties on environmental policy outputs in 18 OECD countries, 19702000, European Journal of
Political Research 49(3): 30136.
——, K. Schulze and J. Tosun. 2010. Politikwandel und seine Messung in der vergleichenden Staat-
stätigkeitsforschung: Konzeptionelle Probleme und mögliche Alternativen, Politische Vierteljahresschrift 51
(3): 40932.
Korpi, W. and J. Palme. 2003. New politics and class politics in the context of austerity and globalization:
Welfare state regress in 18 countries, 197595, American Political Science Review 97(3): 42546.
Kühner, S. 2007. Country-level comparisons of welfare state change measures: Another facet of the
dependent variable problem within the comparative analysis of the welfare state, Journal of European
Social Policy 17(1): 518.
Lerner, D. and H.D. Lasswell (eds). 1951. The Policy Sciences: Recent Developments in Scope and Method.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Lynch, J. 2001. The age-orientation of social policy regimes in OECD countries, Journal of Social Policy 30
(3): 41136.
Marsh, D. and J.C. Sharman. 2009. Policy diusion and policy transfer, Policy Studies 30(3): 26988.
Martin, J.P. 1996. Measures of replacement rates for the purpose of international comparisons: A note,
OECD Economic Studies 26(1): 99115.
Mayntz,
R. 1983. The conditions
of eective public policy: A new challenge for policy analysis, Policy
and Politics 11(2): 12343.
Meseguer, C. 2006. Rational learning and bounded learning in the diusion of policy innovations,
Rationality and Society 18(1): 3566.
—— 2009. Learning, Policy Making, and Market Reforms. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Overbye, E. 1994. Convergence in policy outcomes: Social security systems in perspective, Journal of
Public Policy 14(2): 14774.
Pierson, P. 1994. Dismantling the Welfare State? Reagan, Thatcher, and the Politics of Retrenchment. Cambridge
and New York: Cambridge University Press.
—— 1996. The new politics of the welfare state, World Politics 48(2): 14379.
Plümper, T. and E. Neumayer. (2010. Model specication in the analysis of spatial dependence, European
Journal of Political Research 49(3): 41842.
Radaelli, C.M. 2000. Policy transfer in the European Union: Institutional isomorphism as a source of
legitimacy, Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 13(1): 2543.
—— 2008. Europeanization, policy learning, and new modes of governance, Journal of Comparative Policy
Analysis 10(3): 23954.
Rose, R. 1991. What is lesson-drawing? Journal of Public Policy 11(1): 330.
—— 1993. Lesson-Drawing in Public Policy: A Guide to Learning Across Time and Space. Chatham, NJ: Chatham
House.
Sabatier, P.A. 1987. Knowledge, policy-oriented learning, and policy change: An advocacy coalition framework,
Science
Communication 8(4): 64992.
——and D.
Mazmanian. 1980. The implementation of public policy: A framework of analysis, Policy
Studies Journal 8(4): 53860.
Scharpf, F.W. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor-Centered Institutionalism in Policy Research. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
Scruggs, L. 1999. Institutions and environmental performance in seventeen Western democracies, British
Journal of Political Science 29: 131.
—— 2003. Sustaining Abundance: Environmental Performance in Industrial Democracies . Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
—— 2007. Welfare state generosity across space and time, in J. Clasen and N.A. Siegel (eds) Investigating
Welfare State Change: The Dependent Variable Problem in Comparative Analysis. Cheltenham: Edward
Elgar, 13365.
Shipan, C.R. and W.R. Lowry. 2001. Environmental policy and party divergence in Congress, Political
Research Quarterly 54(2): 24563.
Schmitt
42
Sommerer, T. 2010. Transnationales Lernen als Faktor von Policy-Wandel: Eine vergleichende Analyse der
Umweltpolitik in 24 OECD-Staaten. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.
Starke, P. 2006. The politics of welfare state retrenchment: A literature review, Social Policy and Administration
40(1): 10420.
——, Obinger, H. and F.G. Castles. 2008. Convergence towards where: In what ways, if any, are welfare
states becoming more similar? Journal of European Public Policy 15(7): 9751000.
Stephens, J.D., E. Huber and L. Ray, L. 1999. The welfare state in hard times, in H. Kitschelt, P. Lange,
G. Marks and J.D. Stephens (eds) Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Stone, D.L. 2000. Non-governmental policy transfer: The strategies of independent policy institutes,
Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 13(1): 4562.
—— 2001. Learning lessons, policy transfer and the international diusion of policy ideas (Electronic
Version). Warwick Centre for the Study of Globalisation and Regionalisation (CSGR) Working Paper
No. 69/01. Available at www2.warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/csgr/research/workingpapers/2001/wp6901.pdf
—— 2004. Transfer agents and global networks in the transnationalisation of policy, Journal of European
Public Policy 11(3): 54566.
Streeck, W. and K.A. Thelen (eds). 2005. Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political
Economies. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Swank, D. 2001. Political institutions and welfare state restructuring: The impact of institutions on social
policy change in developed democracies, in P. Pierson (ed.) The New Politics of the Welfare State. Oxford
and New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 197237.
—— 2005. Globalisation, domestic politics, and welfare state retrenchment in capitalist democracies,
Social Policy and Society 4(2): 18395.
Sykes, R., B. Palier and P.M. Prior (eds). 2001. Globalisation and European Welfare States: Challenges and
Change. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
Taylor-Gooby, P. (ed.). 2004. New Risks, New Welfare: The Transformation of the European Welfare State.
Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Tews, K., P.-O. Buschand and H. Jörgens. 2003. The diusion
of new environmental
policy instruments,
European Journal of Political Research 42(4): 569600.
Tsebelis, G. 1995. Decision making in political systems: Veto players in presidentialism, parliamentarism,
multicameralism and multipartyism, British Journal of Political Science 25(3): 289325.
—— 2000. Veto players and institutional analysis, Governance: An International Journal of Policy and
Administration 13(4): 44174.
Tyran, J.-R. and R. Sausgruber. 2005. The diusion of policy innovations: An experimental investigation,
Journal of Evolutionary Economics 15(4): 42342.
Vis, B. 2009. Governments and unpopular social policy reform: Biting the bullet or steering clear?, European
Journal of Political Research 48(1): 3157.
——and K. van Kersbergen. 2007. Why and how do political actors pursue risky reforms? Journal of
Theoretical Politics 19(2): 15372.
Volden, C., M.M. Ting and D.P. Carpenter. 2008. A formal model of learning and policy diusion, The
American Political Science Review 102(3): 31932.
Wälti, S. 2004. How multilevel structures aect environmental policy in industrialized countries, European
Journal of Political Research 43(4): 599634.
Weidner, H. and M. Jänicke (eds). 2002. Capacity Building in National Environmental Policy: A Comparative
Study of 17 Countries. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Whiteford, P. 1995. The use of replacement rates in international comparisons of benet systems, International
Social Security Review 48(2): 330.
Wilensky, H.L. 1974. The
Welfare State and
Equality: Structural and Ideological Roots of Public Expenditures.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Windho-Héritier, A. 1987. Policy-Analyse: Eine Einführung . Frankfurt and New York: Campus Verlag.
Studying public policy-making
43
4
International dimensions and
dynamics of policy-making
Anthony Perl
The days when policy researchers could count upon domestic politics and society to contribute
sucient data for a satisfactory analysis are now a memory. Whether policy researchers are
prepared to enter another analytical universe or not, the accelerating ow of ideas, information,
goods and money across national borders has aected the nature of policy problems, reshaped
the attempts to engage these problems and thus reoriented the way in which explanations of
policy-making can be productively pursued. The big questions that animate policy studies may
not have changed, but the available data and the concepts needed to analyze them have been
shifting. This chapter will seek to connect these emerging global dynamics to long recognized
drivers of policy-making and present a conceptual framework that can help in understanding
the resulting interactions. Enhancing the linkage between theoretical frameworks that have
informed international relations and public policy concepts promises a better understanding of
policy-making in a volatile universe.
Despite the growing awareness of globalization as an inuence on many aspects of policy-
making, there remains a knowledge gap among the ndings produced by those who seek to
explain policy-making on its own terms, and those who are more interested in interrogating the
transnational forces that have evolved in recent years. While international relations scholars
are perhaps more experienced in assessing how interactions across boundaries aect politics, they
are also less inclined to extend these eorts to elucidating the internal workings of a policy
subsystem. Such sectoral interpretations can appear mundane to those who are focused on
matters of global conict and governance.
Conversely, students of public policy may be quite motivated to consider how global dynamics
aect policy-making within a subsystem, in search of a better understanding about how exo-
genous inuences can shape the authoritative dynamics within that domain. But researchers
who have been trained to explore policy-making in a single government or administration, or
perhaps compare those eorts, are likely to lack the conceptual tools that are required to inte-
grate a global interplay of policy inputs into the workings of a particular subsystem. The most
promising approach to taking the measure of global inuences on policy subsystems thus appears
to extend the policy researchers ability to assess these exogenous forces from an international
perspective. Extending the capacity of policy researchers to better interpret international interac-
tions could enhance the prospects for a fruitful dialogue between policy studies and international
44
relations. As policy studies have more to say about the increasing global inuences and interactions,
those engaged in international political research could become more attracted to engaging such
ndings about how global forces inuence policy subsystems.
This examination of how to account for international forces in policy studies will draw upon
concepts that have been developed to examine meso-level political relationships between the
state and society. This tradition includes identifying congurations of actors and classifying them
into a typology of policy communities (i.e. ranging from the collaborative partnerships of cor-
poratism to the competitive advocacy of pluralism). More sophisticated classications of authority
can be found in the literature on policy networks, and as the scope of such relations has broadened,
the term governance network has been put forward. These approaches to analyzing policy dynamics
that cross organizational and jurisdictional boundaries can be particularly eective in assessing global
inuences on policy-making because they draw upon relational measures of authority. Assessing
these relationships in the international arena is a natural conceptual progression. Furthermore, the
analytical skills that are developed through analyzing policy networks and communities could be
readily scaled up to examining global forces aecting policy, unlike some conceptual approaches.
We will consider the value of applying a network perspective on understanding global inuences
through four stages of consideration. Initially the chapter will examine the concept of globali-
zation and briey assess the implications that it raises for studying policy-making. Next, we will
turn to the literature on policy communities and policy networks to highlight tools that can be
used in assessing global inuences on policy subsystems. Then, the chapter will consider the con-
cept of policy paradigms and contemplate the role that ideational inuences play in modulating
global impacts on policy. Finally, a fourfold typology of internationalized policy environments
will be presented, in order to illuminate how particular congurations of policy communities
and networks can refract the global inuences on governance. In conclusion, the dynamic role
of policy community mediators in trying to steer subsystem responses to global forces will briey
be considered.
Seeking policy explanations in a time of increasingly permeable
political boundaries
The political boundaries that have structured many examinations of policy-making are less de-
nitive than at any time since the mid-twentieth century. And as a result, political factors and
forces that could once be safely ruled out of bounds in studying policy, because they were seen
to have little impact on the policy subsystems within a given jurisdiction, have to be considered
in ways that take account of contemporary reality without hopelessly cluttering the scope of a
given investigation. Cerny (1995) contended that global forces have reshaped the way that states
function when they make policy by providing policy actors with cues of equal or greater inuence
than the domestic interests and institutions which previously determined both the political cal-
culus and the substantive assessment of policy options. His claims were provocative when rst
asserted, but appear increasingly self-evident in the early twenty-rst century.
For example, American auto manufacturers had successfully resisted changes to fuel economy
regulations for decades when the US surface transportation subsystem was governed by a cohesive
domestic cluster of interests and institutions (Perl and Dunn 2007). It is not a coincidence that
the US government has established a much higher fuel economy standard for motor vehicles
following the 2008 global nancial crisis. A multi-billion dollar bailout that saved both Chrysler
and General Motors from liquidation opened the window for changing technical standards in
ways that had previously been anathema to industry leaders in the domestic subsystem. In this
instance, the international drivers of policy change dramatically, obviously because the inuence
International dimensions and dynamics
45
of these forces was concentrated in a global nancial crisis, but many subsystems have been
reshaped by international inuences in a less dramatic fashion.
Even cultural characteristics which once informed the values behind distinct traditions of the
state in policy-making (Dyson 1980) have become harder to operationalize as independent
variables. From the social welfare traditions of Scandinavian states to the neoliberalism embraced
by Anglo-American polities, state-specic ideas on the role of government no longer provide a
clear and consistent policy orientation. Instead, virtual communities of interest spread ideas and
values across social networks that span the globe at the same time that supranational institutions
develop explicitly global values that foster convergence in policy-making.
Not surprisingly, scholars in international relations have been drawing attention to the global
inuences on policy-making for some time already. During the 1970s, Keohane and Nye (1977)
had identied interdependence as a driving force behind international economic and political
relationships. Gourevitch (1978) proposed an explanation of how these international forces could
directly aect domestic politics, which would then reverberate by inuencing foreign policies in
a formulation that he labeled the second image-reversed. This dynamic was shown to extend
from domestic politics into policy-making by Robert Putnam (1998) through his two-level games
perspective on policy negotiations in the international arena. While this attention to international
policy inuences grew out of a focus on the workings of formal governing arrangements across
political boundaries, another stream of thinking that is closer to home in policy studies has sought
to understand how societal forces can inuence policy when they cross organizational boundaries.
In this broader consideration of transnational political forces, globalization has become a
commonly used term to encompass economic, political and cultural inuences that cut across
borders, not only those of formal state structures but also societal organizations from corporations
to virtual networks. Held has characterized such globalization as
the stretching and deepening of social relations and institutions across space and time such
that, on the one hand, day-to-day activities are increasingly inuenced by events happening
on the other side of the globe and, on the other, the practices and decisions of local groups
or communities can have signicant global reverberations.
(1995: 20)
The eects of such globalization have reshaped the roles and routines of policy subsystems. Policy
inputs from subnational, national, regional, and international levels are likely to expand the range
of ideas and interests that are interacting within the subsystem, yielding less stable relationships
among actors and less predictable actions at dierent stages of the policy cycle.
This expansion of global inuences can be seen following the liberalization of capital move-
ments in the 1980s and the subsequent impact of global nancial considerations that has played
out within just about every policy subsystem. Facing the need to engage with these global
nancial dynamics, most governments have sought to cooperate at scales ranging from informal
dialogue and information sharing (e.g. the Asia-Pacic Economic Cooperation) to creating
supra-national currencies and reserve banks (e.g. the Euro and European Central Bank). These
initiatives have further amplied global inuences on policy subsystems, since the economic
fundamentals shaping many policy contexts have become increasingly transnational.
And while the eects of globalization vary across subsystems, there are few, if any, domains
that have been left unaected by this erosion of political boundaries. Even subsystems supporting
core areas of state sovereignty, such as the military and national security, have been aected
by the globalization of combat and terrorism. The multinational military intervention that
determined
the outcome of
Libyas civil war in 2011 illustrates the inuence of global forces on
Perl
46
at least two dierent levels. On the one hand, global communications and social networks sparked
rebellions in autocratic regimes across the Arab world. And on the other hand, nations that had
not previously allied in Middle East military intervention jointly took a side in the Libyan conict,
responding partly to domestic appeals that democratic ambitions and human rights must not be
extinguished by the Qadda counteroensive.
Other policy subsystems have experienced less dramatic, but no less important, changes from
beyond their borders as states have more or less explicitly pooled their sovereignty to address
environmental, nancial, trade, and other policy challenges. The common characteristic in each of
these diverse instances where global forces have modied the interaction of ideas and interests
within a policy subsystem is that more permeable political boundaries have let in ideas, information,
and interests that had not previously exerted a direct aect on the actors and organizations.
This augmenting encroachment of global inuences into a policy subsystem, mirrors and
often stimulates another kind of change that has impacted the nature of policy-making in recent
years. The rules and norms that once demarcated the duties of public ocials from the actions
of civil society participants in a policy subsystem have also changed, with a tendency toward
blurring the distinction between public and private spheres of responsibility. The relationship
between the public realm and the private sector can no longer be counted upon to conform to
Weberian administrative norms. Scholars in public policy have thus had to develop their own
concepts and analytical tools that could better interpret this reconguration of activities and
relationships between the public realm and the private sector, leading into a post-Weberian
universe where states make policy through governance (Kooiman 2003).
Assessing the potentials and the pitfalls of policy-making that unfold beyond the bureau-
cracys formal accountability for translating democratically attained decisions into policy out-
comes has taken policy studies into the more interactive and contingent deliberations occurring
in governance networks. Scholars such as Rhodes (1996) claimed that societies were experien-
cing a new mode of policy-making in which governance provided the capacity for governing
without government. Examining political dynamics that span the boundary between the state
and society is thus increasingly familiar to scholars who look at how policy communities and
policy networks have changed the way that policy gets developed. This approach can develop the
skills needed to extend such analysis to explain the political eects of globalization on policy.
When the interactions between state and society have grown more convoluted as their bound-
aries have blurred, the analysis of how these relationships are managed requires some robust
guiding principles. Coleman and Perl (1999) proposed two conceptual axes that can orient navi-
gation through the many intricacies of governance and globalization. First, they draw attention
to the degree and patterns of integration of relationships among policy actors. Next, they highlight
the extent and manner in which public power is shared between state and civil society actors.
Since these dimensions are interdependent, the potential for confusion is best avoided by linking
each axis to an established analytical viewpoint in the study of meso-level policy-making. By
focusing on participants, the policy community perspective can capture the interaction of actors
and organizations within a given governance structure. (Coleman and Skogstad 1990) And similar
to van Waardens (1992) usage, the concept of policy network will characterize the institutional
dimension in which public power can be shared by members of the policy community.
Policy communities can be conceptualized as the cognitive and discursive space where issues
are problematized as appropriate, or inappropriate, objects of public engagement. Where such
debates used to emphasize the merits and disadvantages of placing a problem onto the public
policy agenda, thus triggering a governments subsequent engagement with formulating and
implementing a course of action, the trend toward governance has led policy communities to
remain continuously, although variably, engaged in eorts to pursue policy options. The degree of
International dimensions and dynamics
47
integration within policy communities is determined by their boundary rules, and represents one
of two dening characteristics. Boundaries can be more or less restrictive depending on the nature
and enforcement of rules that specify size (Jordan and Schubert 1992), openness (Hassenteufel
1995) and stability of membership (Le Gales 1995). These rules also have a bearing on the quantity
and nature of information that is exchanged (Laumann and Knoke 1987).
Another signicant aspect of the boundary dening a policy community is the extent of shared
values and norms among its membership. The most well developed conceptualization of such
ideational ties can be found in Sabatier and Jenkins-Smiths (1993) Advocacy Coalition Frame-
work in which core beliefs about the causes and eects of policy intervention focus participants
on a common understanding of problems and draw them into shared political pursuit of a pre-
ferred solution. The number of advocacy coalitions and the relationship between their preferred
policy solutions can greatly aect the character of a policy community. A similar concept has been
put forward from international relations scholarship, the epistemic community (Haas 1992).
Here, it is ostensibly objective expertise, rather than more subjective beliefs, that draw policy actors
together into shared knowledge and cooperative action that can transcend national boundaries.
By specifying the boundaries of policy communities, and then analyzing what goes on inside
these spaces, policy scholars have been able to link the participants state of mind to their
interactions both within and outside the policy community, and then correlate these relation-
ships with actual policy orientations. One important nding from this line of analysis has been
that the greater the degree of integration of actors within a policy community, the higher the
likelihood of collaborative approaches to policy-making. Scharpf (1997) claims that instead of a
short-term focus, and zero sum calculus of competition, more integrated policy communities
can pursue policy options which go beyond the lowest common denominator and address the
needs of a broader cross-section of policy actors than would be able to work together in less inte-
grated contexts. Another nding has been that once a particular advocacy coalition or epistemic
community has become widely recognized for its inuence or expertise, then that groups values
and norms will convey legitimacy on some actors while denying it to others (Smith 1995).
Some policy preferences will thus become more legitimate than others for the time that con-
sensus on values persists. But when consensus within a policy community erodes, political
conict over options at each stage of policy-making can be expected.
When it comes to assessing the ways in which political authority plays out in a policy sub-
system, the policy network perspective looks beyond the cognitive and discursive attributes of
policy community participants and focuses on a scarce resource that is essential to overcoming
the policy-making constraints that are posed by organizational interdependencies, technical com-
plexities, and factual uncertainties. That resource is power, in particular the power that ows
either directly or indirectly from state sovereignty.
During the strategic manoeuvring of policy actors, the sharing of information and ideas, and
the negotiation of competing interests and perspectives, outcomes will be shaped considerably
by who has the power to make decisions binding across all of society based on the sovereign
authority of government. This authority may well be delegated and shared across the policy com-
munity, but in one form or another, power inuences the outcome of policy-making. And it is
through those dierent congurations of power that inuence how particularly congured
policy networks can make a signicant impact on the policy process.
Policy network typologies have made it possible to move analysis of governance beyond the
blunt distinction between pluralism and corporatism (van Waarden 1992: 30). With the blending
of public and private roles in policy formulation and delivery, more precise network cong-
urations such as state corporatism and clientelism are able to capture the eects of delega-
tion of public authority to coalitions or to particular entities within the policy community. This
Perl
48
precision can be even more helpful in sorting out the authoritative dynamics of transnational
policy communities in which public actors operating at multiple levels of government interact
and share their authority over policy-making, either with one another or with a subset of societal
actors and organizations. The more hybridized such relationships become, and the further that
policy-making dynamics blur the distinction between public and private spheres of account-
ability, the greater value that more nuanced policy network categories can oer in highlighting
both the ecacy and the accountability of particular governance modes.
In a world where some of the boundaries that used to matter most for policy-makingthose
between government and the private sector, and those demarcating one states sovereignty from
anotherare no longer preeminent, other structures that can integrate the ideas and interests of
policy communities with the inuence and power deployed in policy networks merit greater
analytical attention. Instead of concentrating on the forces of cohesion within policy subsystems
that emanate from formal state structures, the inuence of ideas that cut across state and societal
boundaries need to be given greater weight in attempts to explain policy-making.
These ideas about what is to be done, and how it is to be done, comprise the essence of a
policy paradigm. As Peter Hall has illustrated, such globally established paradigms as the role of
monetary policy and the nancial institutions that implement it can be more inuential than
any governments formal economic policy capacity. Policy paradigms thus oer an intellectual
center of gravity that can serve some of the role that state actors and structures have traditionally
played in shaping the dynamics of policy subsystems. The following section will consider the
policy paradigm as a conceptual construct that can oer guidance in interpreting a policy universe
containing more varied international forces than ever before.
How policy paradigms guide governance networks through an
accelerating policy universe
The growing permeability of boundaries, both among nations and between the state and society,
has increased the volume and velocity of forces from the policy universe that are transmitted
into policy communities, raising the level of instability in policy-making. But this growing
exposure to exogenous forces has also enhanced the dissemination of a particular type of ideas
that can bring, or return, coherence to volatile governance networks by fashioning a common
point of view among policy actors. Numerous scholars have noted the inuence that a coherent
set of ideas can exert in aligning the vision of policy actors toward a shared set of goals (Jobert
and Muller 1987; Hall 1993; Shon and Rein 1994). Oering advice on which problems are
critical and which ones are less important, which policy instruments provide appropriate means
to address these problems and which do not, and what instrument settings could best resolve a
problem, are the stock in trade of policy practitioners work. Hall has labeled the guiding principles
that support such deliberations as a policy paradigm. Shon and Rein characterize these ideas
as policy frames, while Jobert and Muller speak of a reference system that guides French
policy-making. Each of these concepts highlights the shared vision that can be created by a set
of norms which focus policy communities on commensurate goals and build condence in the
causal relationships that will guide actors within those communities to agree that particular instru-
ments should be deployed in specic ways. These policy paradigms exert inuence by evoking
images or generative metaphors that help policy actors to make sense of a complex and
contingent policy universe. Examples of such inuential images have included Energy Security,
Universal Health Care, and Free Trade. These ideas and images provide certain actors in
the policy community, and their beliefs, with greater legitimacy in the policy process than other
groups and individuals can muster.
International dimensions and dynamics
49
The acceleration in speed and volume of communication across boundaries has often aided
the dissemination of consistent, if not always convergent, policy paradigms. One such vector has
been the rise of a global cadre of policy consultants who perceive material incentives to sell
similar solutions across a range of policy jurisdictions (Perl and White 2002). Another driving
force for consistent thinking about how to approach problems has been the role of public and
private nancial institutions from the International Monetary Fund to nancial rating agencies
that apply analogous measures of risk and ecacy to public policies and programs across the
globe. These and other inputs present policy actors with consistent signals, along with incentives
to follow them and potential penalties for straying too far from the global consensus on
appropriate policy options and eective solutions.
When these transmission mechanisms are working well, a policy paradigm will be widely
accepted, and the policy subsystem settles into a period of political quiescence. Policy commu-
nities abridge the discourse and engagement in their given policy domain, often corresponding
with a delegation of power from state actors to certain policy community participants. These
terms of engagement can enable a particular policy community to dominate all stages of the
policy cycle, from agenda-setting through policy evaluation. More often than not, the actors or
advocacy coalitions granted legitimacy by the policy paradigm become the principal civil society
actors who participate in key decisions, conduct informal or formal oversight, and even deliver
program outputs. Policy discourse becomes more technical as issues of day-to-day management
and ne tuning of policy instruments are deemed relevant subjects for discourse.
But the same transmission of ideas and information that can encourage consistency in outlook
across political boundaries, and among a critical mass of policy actors throughout civil society,
can also undermine the consensus that had been fostered by a policy paradigm. From the sudden
revelation of condential information through sources disseminated by Wikileaks through the
ash mobs that are mobilized to protest policy options on Facebook and Twitter, experiences
and ideas that challenge conventional wisdom can be shared more immediately, and more exten-
sively, than ever before. When faced with such challenges, policy-makers rst instinct is to turn
inward toward the policy community participants they know best and seek a modest revision of
the recipes that are most familiar to them. The second level of response to a global perturbation
would see the state changing its relationship with actors in the policy community. Such recon-
guration could go in either of two directions. Either new actors could be admitted into the
corridors of power and with them, the range of outcomes that could be considered acceptable
would expand. Or the number of actors with a recognized role in the governance network
could be pruned back in order to make space for a new paradigm to emerge eventually. Such a
redenition of boundary rules and a reallocation of inuence may reequip the policy community
to better manage the process of policy change.
When neither of these tactics to adjust the policy paradigm from within the policy commu-
nity succeeds, the debate is likely to shift from resolvable dierences to deeper disputes where
an existing policy paradigm is called into question, and directly challenged with a contending
paradigm. Faced with conicting opinions, political leaders will have to choose who to recog-
nize as authoritative, especially on matters of technical credibility. Under these circumstances,
the policy community is most likely to engage in a political contest over the issues at hand (Hall
1993: 281). In such times of widespread contention over goals and values, engagement spreads
beyond the policy community itself engaging political actors from unfamiliar, and less pre-
dictable, corners of the policy universe. Contributions from unfamiliar sources of expertise,
among them the sub-elites that Etzioni-Halevy (1993: 194) has identied as playing an
inuential role by developing alternative policy options in between points of political decision-
making (e.g. elections), will broaden the discourse to include new approaches and ideas. And
Perl
50
without the paradigmatic consensus established to screen out nonconforming perspectives, the
policy community will experience more wide-ranging debates about what is to be done. At
such times, political ideologiesexplicit meaning systems that profess universal principles to
guide policy-making (Swidler 1986)will contend to sway the hearts and minds in the policy
community, and the wider engaged public, toward embracing a new paradigm.
During periods of such widespread conict over policy, changes in policy communities and
networks will be more profound. Levels of integration within policy communities will decline as
the rules for appropriate discourse and action become relaxed, if not entirely suspended. As conict
levels increase, state actors may pull back their delegation of authority to societal actors, or they
may shift such a delegation of authority from one set of actors to another. Corporatist policy
networks would thus be most susceptible to restructuring, while more loosely organized issue net-
works would see less change in their structure, as the content of their discourse shifted. In the event
that the level of conict surpasses some threshold, which might vary across jurisdictions, the state
may take the lead in reorganizing a policy community, creating a state-directed policy network.
Broadly speaking, the more unsettled the dierences of opinion regarding policy options, the
less likely it is that the policy community will be capable of managing the entire spectrum of
change. Multiple sources of input into policy formulation, implementation and evaluation will
arise, with growing potential for transnational engagement in the stages of policy development.
There may even be an international ratication of policy, such as when the European Central
Bank prescribes and proscribes scal options for countries like Greece, Portugal and Ireland that
are struggling to renance their public debt. Joberts (1995) analysis of French policy paradigm shifts
suggested that during times of heightened conict, the deference to expert consensus in a policy
community evaporates and competing interests and ideologies tend to pull policy actors apart. When
this happens, the disjointed inputs and unpredictable combinations of ideas and interests can take
on the character of Cohen, March and Olsens (1972) garbage can model of policy-making.
As the velocity and volume of global communication accelerates, policy paradigms can thus
provide a structure for managing the ood of ideas and information that inundates policy domains
around the clock, 365 days a year. But the same channels of discourse and sources of expertise that
often manage to interpret and lter the policy inputs in a way that focuses policy communities
on a common approach, can also transmit information and interpretations that will undermine the
consensus behind a policy paradigm. In this schizophrenic twist to policy formulation in an
unpredictable world, the same policy actors who have embraced open borders and global norms can
suddenly be disrupted by these same sources of input. Structures such as policy communities,
and modes of governance practiced in policy networks, which had appeared fully functional
within a particular policy paradigm will quickly degenerate into confusion and conict under the
inuence of transnational ideas and information. An explicit focus on supranational governance
arrangements, or lack thereof, can better make sense of tendencies and trajectories when the global
inuences on policy-making shift from promoting consensus to destabilizing it. The following
section will oer such a schema for considering the inuence of supranational governance forces.
The mediating inuence of internationalized policy environments
The relational focus of policy community and policy network analytical approaches make them
well suited to examining the forces that cross the borders between states as well as traversing the
boundary between state and society. Whether policy paradigms are in force or in ux, the levels
of shared understanding, common discourse and the locus and distribution of authority that are
gauged by taking account of policy communities and networks enables an appreciation of how
policy-making now occurs in open environments where exogenous inuences can ow freely.
International dimensions and dynamics
51
Some have expressed skepticism about the utility of scaling up concepts that were developed
to examine policy-making at the national and subnational levels to gain insight into the policy
dynamics of supranational governance (Kassim 1994). Policies made in the European Union or
eorts by the United Nations to develop binding agreements on climate change, for example,
can pose challenges for meso-level analysis because of their transnational dynamics. When exo-
genous sources give rise to borderless bursts of disruptive information, the functioning of policy
communities and networks can be aected in unpredictable ways. But analogous instabilities
within statesociety relations have not undermined policy community and network analyses of
volatile political contexts. Risse-Kappen (1995) has suggested that contemporary transnational
governance arrangements include the same type of horizontal coordinating networks that cross
national borders, as well as bridging the boundaries between state and society.
In extending the utility of policy community and network concepts into policy-making
contexts that experience high levels of global inuence, Coleman and Perl (1999) advanced the
concept of internationalized politics to explore a context in which at least some stages of the
policy cycle take place at a more encompassing level than the nation-state. Thus dened, and illu-
strated in Table 4.1, internationalized policy environments may be dierentiated according to
their level of public sector activism and by the degree to which supranational governing arrange-
ments are institutionalized. Public sector activism refers to the direct involvement of politicians
and senior civil servants in managing governance dynamics within and among policy commu-
nities. Societal actors will take on a dominant role in managing governance through policy
communities and networks when public sector activism is low, and politicians and senior civil
servants will steer such governance when public sector activism is high.
The second dimension of internalized politics is expressed in the degree to which international
institutions have a developed role in policy-making. In some policy domains, international institu-
tions play a role that is mandated in supranational law. With a legal mandate, international
institutions gain a capacity to manage governance in policy communities and networks. Where
supranational laws do not establish an explicit role for international institutions, national policy
actors will maintain greater autonomy in responding to international inuences. Applying these two
dimensions of internationalized politics to the ways in which policy communities and networks
are aected by global inuences, one can distinguish between the four ideal-typical internationalized
policy environments which are depicted in Table 4.1. These are briey described below.
When the levels of public sector activism and institutionalization of supranational governing
arrangements are both high, policy-making will be characterized by a dynamic of multilevel governance
(MLG). In places where MLG is common, like the European Union, both national and supra-
national governments are well developed institutionally. As a result, politicians, bureaucrats, and
Table 4.1 Supranational governance dynamics
Public sector activism in governance
Institutionalization
of supranational
governing
arrangements
High Low
High Multilevel governance Self-regulatory and
private regimes
Low Intergovernmental negotiations Loose couplings
Source: Adapted from Coleman and Perl (1999)
Perl
52
civil society actors and organizations engage in a multitude of cooperative working arrangements
that cross organizational boundaries and lead to well-integrated policy communities. Public
authority for policy-making is more likely to be delegated under such conditions. While MLG
is most advanced in Europe, the activity of international institutions in trade, nance, and the
environment extends well beyond Europe and has advanced the conditions in which this mode
of internationalized politics is inuential in the workings of policy communities and networks.
When they are well integrated, national level policy communities are likely to take on consider-
able responsibilities in multilevel policy implementation. There are also likely to support trans-
national policy communities, composed of actors from both national and international levels that
link these dierent national policy communities while connecting them to international institu-
tions. Transnational policy communities can be very inuential in the formulation of policy options,
and transnational experts are likely to work closely with national policy communities during the
implementation stage. Over time, the relative level of integration in domestic and transnational
policy communities will shape the trajectory of how MLG adapts to global drivers of change.
The more integrated that the transnational policy community is, the more it will be able to
focus inputs entering the domestic policy arena, as well as the more coherent its proposals for
policy options to address those inputs are likely to be. The more integrated the domestic policy
community is, the more discretion it will exert in ltering those inputs and (re)interpreting those
policy prescriptions. Given the diversity of interests and the uidity of participation, transna-
tional policy communities are often likely to be less integrated than their domestic counterparts.
Considering the ways in which these dierent layers interact to either reinforce a policy paradigm
or to undermine it is a research area that promises interesting ndings as examinations of the
2008 global nancial crisis and its ongoing eects begin to unravel the intricacies of transnational
policy community activity and inuence.
When governments remain active in steering policy communities, but do so in an interna-
tional environment that is lacking in supranational governance structures, policy eects will
likely be seen through the mode of intergovernmental negotiations. This is the well-explored
domain of international relations scholarship, and one of the most inuential models of how
such negotiations relate to domestic policy can be found in Putnams (1988) two-level games
metaphor, as elaborated by Evans et al. (1993). Here, heads of state or their delegated nego-
tiators work to craft agreements at the international level that can be accepted, either through
formal ratication or some other form of political enactment, at the domestic level. The
anticipated degree of diculty in such ratication, or acceptance, creates smaller or larger win
sets (i.e. possible agreements that can be accepted) for the negotiators.
Intergovernmental negotiations will thus reinforce a strong role for national policy commu-
nities in the agenda-setting, ratication, and implementation stages of policy-making. When
intergovernmental negotiations become regularized, as in the regularly scheduled conferences of
parties to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change or meetings of the
Group of Eight (G8) heads of state, ad hoc coalitions of political actors will be drawn beyond
domestic policy communities to participate in peoples summits that are held alongside, yet
outside, the ocial negotiations. Here, opposition groups de ne and publicize policy alternatives
to the options being discussed in ocial negotiations. These alternatives are not envisioned as
replacing the options being considered by authorized negotiators. But they are expected to inuence
these options by building support back home for alternative positions, or stirring up opposition
to the negotiations, and thus narrowing the set of what the ocial negotiators can expect to be
accepted by their respective domestic political jurisdictions.
In many policy subsystems, the rules of the game were established by private actors who have
maintained a prominent role in both elaborating norms and enforcing them. A prime example
International dimensions and dynamics
53
of such a regime can be found in markets for equities, bonds, and the arcane derivative instru-
ments that have weighed so heavily on the global nancial system since 2008. These privately
led governance systems emerged for various reasons. In some circumstances, private organiza-
tions held a monopoly, or oligopoly, over the technical knowledge needed to design and
operate the policy subsystem. In other situations, jurisdictional or scal constraints (i.e. feder-
alism) fostered gaps in public sector capacity that private organizations moved in to ll. These
self-regulating policy communities rarely remained purely private.
States would give assent to these privately established rules and practices by incorporating
them into law or by delegating the authority to pursue self-regulation in the public interest.
Private entities, usually non-prot industry associations, would police a policy sector under such
delegated authority, leading to the evolution of private interest governments (Streeck and
Schmitter 1985). Such self-regulatory and private regimes have played important roles in policy
domains that experienced the greatest volume and velocity of global interchange. These formal
and informal institutions have become the epicentre of governance in important elements of the
architecture of globalization, such as nancial transactions that reach beyond the borders of most
states and create new norms of behavior and obligation.
In the context of self-regulatory and private regimes, transnational policy communities are
likely to be much more tightly integrated than those operating in multilevel governance or
intergovernmental negotiations contexts. The leading role played by private actors in the
domestic nodes of these transnational policy communities (e.g. domestic nancial organizations)
will favor the establishment and maintenance of clientelist policy network relationships. Private
regimes will derive authority from the imbalance of resources, especially knowledge, between
state and private actors, giving them strong incentives to avoid transparency in their activities.
The internationalized policy environment that gives rise to a context of loose couplings is
dened largely by the absence of institutionalized structures and the lack of any obvious dele-
gation of public authority. High levels of scienti c and technical uncertainty associated with
new domains of innovation (e.g. social networks) may discourage state actors from intervention,
while no stable private organization exists to support a privately led policy regime. In some
cases, physical or political crises can undermine previous structures, leading to new congura-
tions of global and local initiative to restructure rogue states (e.g. Bosnia, Iraq) or rebuild
devastated local jurisdictions (e.g. New Orleans, Port-au-Prince).
Implementing policy under conditions of pragmatic alliances among policy actors can bring
about what Browne (1990) has termed issue niches in which a transient policy community
coalesces around particular understandings of an issue and the options to address it. The vener-
able garbage can model of Cohen et al. (1972) can be helpful in conceptualizing the arbitrary
outcomes that arise from such unstructured interaction between policy problems, solutions,
participants, and choice opportunities. Under such circumstances, policy community structure
will be quite uid, with state and societal actors drifting in and out of dierent stages of policy-
making. The conguration of authority will resemble an issue network in which participants are
more likely to share information and ideas, as opposed to values and interests.
Conclusion
In seeking to better understand the dynamic eects of global inuences on public policy, policy
researchers and international relations scholars can cumulate their insights by focusing on the rela-
tional dynamics of authority found in policy community and policy network analytical perspec-
tives. Both elds have pursued such relational measures in drawing attention to the importance
of horizontal coordination eorts in decision-making. From international accords to impromptu
Perl
54
coalitions of the willing, these policy actor groupings can generate rules and norms that ow
across boundaries in the wake of information and resources that move beyond borders ever
more quickly.
As further research is pursued on the governance of globalized policy domains, insights will
accumulate about various congurations of transnational policy communities from both the
policy studies and international relations avenues of enquiry. These ndings can be expected to
illuminate the role of policy community mediators who are active in several transnational policy
communities and could thus be expected to inuence the interactions between global and
national, or local, politics at their points of intersection and overlap. Such mediators could
function as pragmatic policy brokers, akin to Sabatier and Jenkins-Smiths (1993) understanding
of a policy broker or Kingdons (2003) conceptualization of a policy entrepreneur who
connects problems with solutions by opening windows of political opportunity.
Another mode of mediation that may be even more signicant in an expanding policy uni-
verse occurs through the translation of policy paradigms between policy communities that become
connected through ows of information or interests that cross established boundaries. Kuhn
anticipated that in situations where scientic paradigms conict, some experts would function as
translators between the dierent linguistic communities. Schön and Rein (1994) posit that such
translation can oer the key to resolving conict between dierent paradigms or frames. To
overcome such conict, the policy community mediator must construct a view of the world that
can engage the ideas and interests of multiple policy communities and open a dialogue among
them. Such transversal policy deliberations may provide a means to accommodate the disruptive
forces generated by unfamiliar, and often unintelligible, information and ideas that ow freely
across the boundaries of contemporary policy subsystems.
Bibliography
Browne, William P. 1990. Organized interests and their issue niches: A search for pluralism in a policy
domain, Journal of Politics 52(2): 477509.
Cerny, Philip. 1995. Globalization and the changing logic of collective action, International Organization
49(4): 595625.
Cohen, Michael James March, and Johan Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational choice,
Administrative Science Quarterly 17(1): 125.
Coleman, William and Anthony Perl. 1999. Internationalized policy network environments and policy
network analysis, Political Studies 47(4): 69709.
——and Grace Skogstad (eds). 1990. Policy Communities and Public Policy in Canada: A Structural Approach,
Toronto: Copp Clark Pittman.
Dyson, Kenneth. 1980. The State Tradition in Western Europe: A Study of An Idea and an Institution. Oxford:
M. Robertson.
Etzioni-Halevy, Eva. 1993. The Elite Connection: Problems and Potentials of Western Democracy. Cambridge,
MA: Polity Press.
Evans, Peter, Harold Jacobson and Robert Putnam. 1993. Double-edged Diplomacy: International Bargaining
and Domestic Politics. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Gourevitch, Peter. 1978. The second image reversed: The international sources of domestic politics,
International Organization 32(4): 881912.
Haas, Peter. 1992. Introduction: epistemic communities and international policy coordination, International
Organization 46(1): 135.
Hall, Peter, 1993. Policy paradigms, social learning and the state: The case of economic policymaking in
Britain, Comparative Politics 25(3): 27596.
Hassenteufel, Patrick. 1995. Do policy networks matter?, in P. Le Gales and M. Thatcher (eds) Les réseaux
de politique publique: Débat autour des policy networks. Paris: LHarmattan, 91108.
Held, David. 1995. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
International dimensions and dynamics
55
Jobert, B. 1995 Rhétorique politique, Controverses scientiques et construction des normes institutio-
nelles: Esquisse dun parcours de recherche, in A. Faure, G. Pollet and R. Warin (eds) La construction du
sens dans les politiques: Débats autour de la notion de référentiel. Paris: LHarmattan, 1324.
——and Pierre Muller. 1987. LÉtat en action: Politiques publiques et corporatismes. Paris: Presses Universités
de France.
Jordan, G. and K. Schubert. 1992. A preliminary ordering of policy network labels, European Journal of
Political Research 21(12): 727.
Kassim, Hussein. 1994. Policy networks and European Union policy making: A skeptical view, West
European Politics 17(4): 1527.
Keohane, Robert and Joseph Nye. 1977. Power and Interdependence: World politics in transition. Boston: Little,
Brown.
Kingdon, John. 2003. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York: Longman.
Kooiman, Jan 2003. Governing as Governance. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Laumann, Edward. and David Knoke. 1987. The Organizational State: Social Choice in National Policy
Domains. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 22648.
Le Gales, P. and M. Thatcher. 1995. Les réseaux de politique publique. Paris: Editions LHarmattan.
Perl, Anthony and Donald White. 2002. The changing role of consultants in Canadian policy analysis,
Policy, Organisation and Society 21(4): 4973.
Perl, Anthony and James A. Dunn Jr. 2007. Reframing automobile fuel economy policy in North
America: The politics of punctuating a policy equilibrium, Transport Reviews 27(1): 135.
Putnam, Robert. 1998. Diplomacy and domestic politics: The logic of two-level games, International
Organization 42(3): 42760.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 1996. The new governance: Governing without government, Political Studies 44(3):
65267.
Risse-Kappen,
T. 1995. Bringing transnational
relations back in: Introduction and Governance and
transnational relations: What have we learned, in Thomsa Risse-Kappen (ed.) Bringing Transnational
Relations Back In. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 336, 280 313.
Sabatier, Paul A. and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith. 1993. Polity Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition
Approach. Boulder: CO: Westview Press.
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor Centred Institutionalism in Policy Research. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press.
Schön, D and M. Rein, 1994. Frame Reection, Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies. New
York: Basic Books.
Smith, A. 1995. Réintroduire la question du sens dans les réseaux daction publique, in P. Le Gales and
M. Thatcher (eds) Les réseaux de politique publique: Débat autour des policy networks. Paris: LHarmmattan,
10920.
Streeck, Wolfgang and Philippe Schmitter. 1985. Community, market and state associations?, in Wolfgang
Streeck and Philippe Schmitter (eds) Private Interest Government, London: Sage, 129.
Swidler, Ann. 1986. Culture in action: Symbols and strategies, American Sociological Review 51(2): 27386.
van Waarden, Frans 1992. Dimensions and types of policy networks, European Journal of Political Science
21(1): 2952.
Perl
56
Part II
Conceptualizing public
policy-making
5
State theory and the rise of the
regulatory state
Darryl S.L. Jarvis
Theories in the social sciences fall into dierent types or orders depending upon the type and
range of social phenomena they attempt to explain and the basic method they use to derive their
insights and hypotheses. That is, social scientic theories dier according to their level of analysis,
method of analysis and unit of analysis (Almond and Genco 1977: 489522). With respect to their
level of analysis, some social scientic theories are general or macro-level social theories that
attempt to explain all phenomena within their purview. Others are less wide-ranging and focus
only on a few very specic subsets of social life, either at a micro-ormeso-level of analysis (Ray
2001: 35588). Similarly, social theories also dier according to their method of analysis: some
are deductive theories developed largely on the basis of the application of general presuppositions,
concepts or principles to specic phenomena. Others are less deductive and more inductive,
developing generalizations only on the basis of careful observation of empirical phenomena and
subsequent testing of these generalizations against other cases (Lundquist 1987; Przeworski 1987:
3149; Hawkesworth 1992: 291392). And, with respect to their units of analysis, some social
theories focus attention on individuals as the basic social actor whose behaviour and actions must be
explained, while some view aggregate collections of individuals, or groups, as the relevant analytical
unit. Still, others consider larger social structures to have an independent impact on individual
and collective actions (Hay and Wincott 1998: 9517; Clark 1998: 24570; Tilly 1984).
If all the permutations within these three variations are considered, the list of policy-relevant
social theories would be almost innite. However, for most purposes, this task can be simplied
somewhat by focusing only on general, or macro-level, social theories. This is acceptable
because policy-relevant academic disciplines such as economics and political science are inter-
ested in all social behaviour and activities and tend to view public policy-making as only a
subset of such behaviour, amenable to the general theories and explanations prevalent in each
eld. As such, only a few representative cases exist, therefore, based on dierences in the char-
acteristic basic unit of analysis they employ and their method of theory construction (see Table 5.1)
(Dessler 1999: 12337).
State theory focuses on the impact and evolution of social structures and political institutions
on policy-making. Many analyses in this mould focus solely on the state, seeing it as the leading
institution in society and the key agent in the political process. Others, however, attribute
explanatory signicance to other organized social actors, such as business or labour, in addition
59
to the state. Both interpretations have their origin in the works of late nineteenth-century
German historical sociologists and legal theorists who highlighted the eects of the development
of modern state institutions on the development of society. Rather than argue that the state
reected the nature of a nations populace or social structure, theorists such as Max Weber and
Otto Hintze noted how the states monopoly on the use of force allowed it to re-order and
structure social relations and institutions (Hintze 1975; Nettl 1968: 55992; Weber 1978).
Sociological or historical neo-institutionalism which focuses on the role of the state in
policy-making has been summarized by Stephen Krasner as follows:
An institutionalist perspective regards enduring institutional structures as the building blocks
of social and political life. The preferences, capabilities, and basic self-identities of individuals
are conditioned by these institutional structures. Historical developments are path dependent;
once certain choices are made, they constrain future possibilities. The range of options avail-
able to policymakers at any given time is a function of institutional capabilities that were put
in place at some earlier period, possibly in response to very dierent environmental pressures.
(1988: 67)
This perspective explicitly acknowledges that policy preferences and capacities are usually
understood in the context of the society in which the state is embedded (Nettl 1968: 55992;
Przeworski 1990; Therborn 1986: 20431). Like its more deductive counterpart, the kinds of
actor-centred institutionalism found in the work of scholars such as Elinor Ostrom, Peter Hall
described a statist institutionalist analysis as one focused on the impact of large-scale structures
on individuals and vice versa. As he put it (Hall 1986: 19):
The concept of institutions refer[s] to the formal rules, compliance procedures, and
standard operating practices that structure the relationship between individuals in various
units of the polity and economy. As such, they have a more formal status than cultural
norms but one that does not necessarily derive from legal, as opposed to conventional,
standing. Throughout, the emphasis is on the relational character of institutions; that is to
say, on the way in which they structure the interactions of individuals. In this sense it is the
organizational qualities of institutions that are being emphasized.
This form of historical or sociological neo-institutionalism diers from its deductive counterpart
in several critical areas. First, there is no eort made in this approach to reduce institutions to
Table 5.1 General approaches to political phenomena and illustrative theoretical examples
Method of theory construction
Deductive Inductive
Unit of
Analysis
Individual Rational choice theories
(Public choice)
Sociological individualism
(Welfare economics)
Collectivity Class analysis (Marxism) Group theories
(pluralism/corporatism)
Structure Actor-centred Institutionalism
(Transaction cost analysis)
Socio-historical
neo-institutionalism (Statism)
Source: Howlett, Michael, M. Ramesh, and Anthony Perl. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems.
Oxford University Press (2009)
Jarvis
60
less organized forms of social interaction, such as norms, rules or conventions. Second, there is
no attempt made to reduce institutions to the level of individuals and individual activities such
as economic or social transactions. And, third, institutions are simply taken as givens, that is, as
observable social entities in themselves, with little eort made to derive the reasons for their
origins from a priori principles of human cognition or existence (March and Olsen 1994).
Using such a socio-historical line of analysis yields, to use Theda Skocpols terms, a state-
centric as opposed to society-centric explanation of political life, including public policy-
making (Skocpol 1985: 343). In a strong version of the statist approach, as Adam Przeworski
put it in a pioneering book:
states create, organize and regulate societies. States dominate other organizations within a
particular territory, they mould the culture and shape the economy. Thus the problem of
the autonomy of the state with regard to society has no sense within this perspective. It
should not even appear. The concept of autonomy is a useful instrument of analysis only
if the domination by the state over society is a contingent situation, that is, if the state
derives its ecacy from private property, societal values, or some other sources located
outside it. Within a true state-centric approach this concept has nothing to contribute.
(1990: 478)
In the statist version of neo-institutional analysis the state is viewed as an autonomous actor
with the capacity to devise and implement its own objectives, not necessarily just to respond to
pressure imposed upon it by dominant social groups or classes. Its autonomy and capacity
are based on its stang by ocials with personal and agency interests and ambitions and the
fact that it is a sovereign organization with unparalleled nancial, personnel, and in the
nal instance coercive resources. The proponents of this perspective claim that this emphasis
on the centrality of the state as an explanatory variable enables it to oer more plausible
explanations of long-term patterns of policy development in many countries than do other
types of political theory (Krasner 1984: 22346; Skowronek 1982; Orren and Skowronek
19989: 689702).
It is dicult to accept statism in the strong form described above, however. It cannot easily
account for the existence of social liberties and freedoms or explain why states cannot always
enforce their will, as in times of rebellion, revolution, or civil disobedience. In fact, even the most
autocratic governments make some attempt to respond to what they believe to be the popula-
tions preferences. It is, of course, especially impossible for a democratic state to be entirely
autonomous from a society with voting rights. And, as Lindblom and others pointed out, in
addition to eorts to maintain and nurture support for the regime among the population,
capitalist states, both democratic and autocratic, need to accommodate the imperatives of the
marketplace in their policies. Second, the statist view suggests implicitly that all strong states
respond to the same problem in the same manner because of their similar organizational fea-
tures. This is obviously not the case, as dierent states (both strong and weak)
often have
dierent policies dealing
with the same problem. To explain the dierences, we will need to
take factors into account other than the features of the state (Przeworski 1990).
To be fair, however, few subscribe to statism in the strong form described above.
Instead of replacing the pluralist notion of the societal direction of the state with the statist
notion of the states direction of society, most inductively oriented institutionalist theorists
merely want to point out the need to take both sets of factors into consideration in their ana-
lyses of political phenomenon (Hall and Ikenberry 1989; McLennan 1991). As Skocpol herself
has conceded:
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
61
In this perspective, the state certainly does not become everything. Other organizations and
agents also pattern social relationships and politics, and the analyst must explore the states
structure in relation to them. But this Weberian view of the state does require us to see it
as much more than a mere arena in which social groups make demands and engage in
political struggles or compromises.
(1985: 78)
This milder version of statism thus concentrates on the links between the state and society in
the context of the formers pre-eminence in pluralist group theory. To that extent, statism
complements rather than replaces society-centredness and restores some balance to social and
political theorizing which had lost its equilibrium (Orren and Skowronek 1993; Almond 1988:
853901; Cortell and Peterson 2001: 76899).
Theorizing the regulatory state: power, structural orientations,
capacities towards a typology
Many more specic policy-related theories nd their basis in statist thinking. One such con-
temporary mode of thinking is the theory of the regulatory state. The rise of the regulatory
state is more often asserted than theorized. What precisely constitutes a regulatory state remains
a vexed question, and what forms, functions, modalities, operational and institutional mechanisms
dene its parameters tend to be inferred rather than systematically outlined.
Part of the explanation for this state of aairs rests in the multiple discourses that have con-
tributed to conceptions of the regulatory state. Rather than a singular school of thought or a
compact literature, the regulatory state emerges from a conation of debates as much about the
rise of transnational capital, globalization, and perceptions of the decline of the state as it does
concerns with regulation and the growth of state power. Liberal internationalist perspectives on
foreign policy, for example, conate the emergence of the regulatory state with the rise of a
neo-liberal order, seeing the regulatory state as part reaction to the loss of scal authority, and
part reaction to the rising power of markets. Waves of tomes since the 1970s have thus declared
the decline of the state. Susan Strange, for example, proclaims that the state is in full retreat, its
authority and absolute power shrinking. Heads of governments, she notes, may be the last to
recognize that they and their ministers have lost the authority over national societies and
economies that they used to have (Strange 2000: 3). For Strange, this progressive loss of real
authority masks the emergence of transnational actors, international nance, and the rise of
market dominance, each of which are evolving non-state authority and legitimacy over their
functional domains (ibid., 919; see also van Creveld 1999: 336414).
More consequential for many theorists has been the ascent of markets combined with glo-
balization. As markets have become transnational and capital mobility heightened through
nancial liberalization, the power of the state to tax and control its economic domain has
been seen as increasingly imperiled, imposing scal constraints on the state or, at worse, hol-
lowing out the state and its capacity for governance (see Rhodes 1994: 13840; Holliday 2000:
1678). In this view, states are now disciplined by market sentiment and neo-liberal ration-
alism, forcing nation-states to conform to the demands of capital lest capital migrates to more
attractive jurisdictions. The decline of the welfare state is thus explained as a combination of
diminishing state scal capacity due to the pressures of globalization, mobile capital and labour
migration too high a tax regime and mobile, highly qualied labour will migrate (see Razin
and Sada 2005). Similarly for Ulrich Beck, the advent of increasing capital mobility forces
Western nation-states to abandon the very tools that for so long made them successful: the
Jarvis
62
ability to pool economic, social and individual risk through state-provisioned health and
unemployment insurance, state ownership of key resources and utilities, and state-guaranteed
entitlements in respect of education and social security (see Beck 1999; Jarvis 2007; Strange
2000; 83). For Beck, the absolute power of the state relative to capital is now inverted,
forcing nation-states in a race to the bottom (one of the few exceptions to the decline of
the state thesis is the work of Linda Weiss (1999)). The regulatory state thus represents the
triumph of capital, with the state forced to retreat to managerialism a hollow shadow of its
former self.
Still others proer the decline of the state as a process of the globalization of regulatory
norms and standards as power is transferred between agential actors. Cobden et al., along with
other liberal internationalists, see the power of the state being systematically transferred to
international organizations and global rule regimes, depriving the state of absolute political and
economic sovereignty because of the exigencies of globalization and the transnationalization of
an increasing spectrum of economic, political and social activity everything from growing
international trade, investment and the movement of people that require the formation of global
standards, codes and practices to facilitate a global political-economy (Cobden et al. 2005; see
also Braithwaite and Draos 2000; Scott 2004). Global governance thus transposes the functional
imperatives of state-based governance, systematically diminishing the propinquity of state agential
authority and the raison dêtre of the state itself.
All these approaches share a common conceptual framework, assuming state power to be
predominantly located in the scal capabilities of the state and derived from its taxing authority
over markets, where the power of each is inversely related to the other; a kind of zero-sum
continuum as markets rise, states decline, and vice versa. Such approaches have a particularly
narrow conceptualization of the sources of state power, however, perhaps unfairly characteriz-
ing the regulatory state as weak, eviscerated and powerless. But as Majone (1996: 54) observes,
the sources of state power are more diuse and spread across several functional domains:
1 Redistributive function where resources are transferred between groups to correct social
inequalities, or public goods provisioned to groups who are then compelled to consume
them (elementary education, public transportation, public health care, for example), and
nanced through taxation, borrowing and the spending power of the state.
2 Stabilization function in which the state manages employment, ination and interest rates
through a determination of industrial and labour policy and the manipulation of scal and
monetary policy.
3 Regulatory function in which the state sets rules that dene the allocative and settlement
mechanisms of markets and the requirements for market participation; dene standards,
procedures and practices, and enunciate codes that order social, economic and political
engagement.
In this schema, state power is essentially dichotomized between scal authority; that is the
ability of the state to tax, borrow and spend, and between regulatory authority; that is the ability
of the state to set and make rules, enforce compliance and delegate authority (Majone 1997: 13;
Majone 1999: 46). The importance of this distinction for the state is that scal constraints or a
diminished legitimacy to tax and spend does not imply a diminished capacity to make rules and
regulate. Rather than a reduction in state power the means by which the state exercises its
authority is simply transposed from direct to indirect forms of government. More importantly,
as Majone observes, rule-making is largely free and imposes few scal burdens on the state apart
from the time, eort and paper needed to make and print rules: the public budget is a soft
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
63
constraint on rule makers because the real cost of regulatory programs is borne not by the
regulators but by those who have to comply with the regulation (Majone 1997: 13). Measuring
the extent, reach or impact of the state simply in terms of its interventionist or scal capacities is
thus a poor proxy of state power since states can govern and exercise authority equally as
eectively through rule making and regulation. As the US Oce of Management and Budget
observes:
Budget and revenue gures are good summaries of what is happening in welfare, defence
or tax policy, and can be used to communicate eectively with the general public over the
fray of program-by-program interest group contention In the world of regulation,
however, where the government commands but nearly all the rest takes place in the private
economy, we generally lack aggregate numbers to describe what is being taxed and spent
in pursuit of public policies.
(quoted in Majone 1997: 13)
These twin sources of state power, however, are not always reconciled. For Susan Strange, it
represents a paradox; what she observed as an obvious decline of state power but at the same
time the increasing intrusion of governments into our daily lives in a quantum that is palpably
greater than at any time before in history:
Statutory or administrative law now rules on the hours of work, the conditions of safety in
the work-place and in the home, the behavior of citizens on the roads. Schools and uni-
versities are subject to more and more decisions taken in ministries of education. Planning
ocials have to be consulted before the smallest building is started or a tree is cut down.
The government inspector has become a familiar and even fearful gure.
(Strange 2000: xi)
Yet for theorists like Majone this paradox lies at the heart of the rise of the regulatory (rule-
making) state and the decline of the interventionist (tax and spend) state. It produces both a
reduction in the size of government while expanding its powers of governance. At one and the
same time we thus observe the implementation of a neo-liberal agenda (downsizing the state,
shedding bureaucracies, cutting taxes, reducing scal expenditures) simultaneously with the emer-
gence of greater regulatory authority (more rule-making, and more indirect forms of state
control). In the United Kingdom this transpired into a 25 per cent reduction in the number of
civil servants between 1976 and the early 1990s, but a relative explosion in stang levels in
regulatory bodies, growing by over 90 per cent (Hood et al. 1999: 2931; LeviFaur 2005: 20).
Indeed, a casual glance at the composition of the unied civil service in the UK in the late
1980s compared to the mid-1990s might indeed lead one to assume government and the state
had shrunk. The Next Steps programme commenced in 1988, for example, announced a ratio-
nalization of the number of civil servants in ministerial departments, preserving only a small core
engaged in the function of servicing ministers and managing departments (quoted in Dowding
1995: 72). By 1994, ministerial departments had stang levels only about a third of levels at the
commencement of the programme. Yet the sense in which government shrank or its power to
govern diminished is problematic. The profusion of statutory bodies and regulatory agencies
witnessed fully 62 per cent of civil servants in ministerial departments transfer directly into
statutory and delegated agencies charged with regulatory oversight (Dowding 1995: 723;
Majone 1997: 10). At the same time, rule-making and the depth of regulatory direction over
domain specic areas, increased enormously. In the last year of its administration, for example,
Jarvis
64
the Brown government issued 2,500 pages of directives to the UK police forces concerning
protocols of conduct, governance, and directives about policing, without any changes to the
scal expenditures on policing (BBC 15 September 2010).
For Majone, the regulatory state is thus not necessarily a weaker, less powerful state, but a recon-
gured state that uses alternative modalities of governance to eect its power. Indeed, for many
proponents the regulatory state strikes the right balance and modality of governance. In the UK,
the regulatory state became synonymous with the Third Way, New Labour and the premier-
ship of Tony Blair, and was constructed around a range of governance programs that relied on
managerial and institutional arrangements to enhance market operation and eciency for the
broader social good (Jayasuriya 2005: 12).
Towards a typology of the regulatory state: modalities of governance
These images of the regulatory state produce mutually reinforcing and contradictory theoriza-
tions as to its rise. On the one hand, the regulatory state is seen as an outcome of the
decline of traditional forms of statist power amid the rise of markets, and on the other, the
outcome of changing modalities of governance that preserve the centrality of the state but in
ways that conne it to new, less interventionist instruments of government. Both acknowl-
edge the rise of markets, the globalization of rule-governed behaviour and the formation of
global rule regimes, and thus both accept these new modalities as legitimate and, in a sense,
optimal given the new political economy of markets. For these theorists, the adoption of reg-
ulatory modes of governance is thus seen as a necessary condition for the functioning of mar-
kets and not just a compromise between economic imperatives and political and social values
(Levi-Faur 2005: 19).
As a typology of the composite elements of the regulatory state, however, rule-making
does not get us very far. So governments are making rules, and perhaps more of them, and
exercise power through the issue of rules and directives. But governments have always made
rules, issued decrees and directives, and exerted power through doing so (Hood and Scott 1996:
323). How does this constitute the emergence of a fundamentally new state entity the reg-
ulatory state? Again, the answer to this question lies across multiple literatures, suggesting a
composite set of images. For Majone, one of the major theorists of regulatory governance, its
distinctive modalities are situated in increasing levels of administrative decentralization, the
break-up of unied forms of administrative control (central bureaucracies), the creation of
single-purpose regulatory units with budget autonomy, delegation of public service delivery to
prot/not-for prot agencies, competitive tendering and the introduction of contractual/
quasi-contractual relationships where budgets and decision-making powers are devolved to
purchasers who, on behalf of their client group, buy services from the supplier oering the
best value for money (Majone 1997: 10, 1999: 39; LeviFaur 2010). Essentially, the reg-
ulatory state is thus distinctive because of the reorganization of how the state does business: who
provides services, how tendering, contracts and quality assurance is administered, and through
what instrumentalities this is achieved. It is this latter element that is perhaps most important:
the rise of a new breed of specialized agencies and commissioners operating at arms length
from central government that represents the most obvious structural consequence of the shift
to a regulatory mode of governance (Majone 1999: 17). The delegation of authority to statu-
tory, independent agencies marks a fundamental change in how rules are made, and, in turn, a
fundamental reallocation of power among government instrumentalities, moving it progres-
sively towards decentralized administrative units (Majone 1997: 21; Blankart 1990: 2306;
Legaspi 2006: 139).
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
65
For proponents, the agency model oers a series of distinctive advantages over previous
modalities of governance. First, it allows specialized agencies to develop domain-specic expert
knowledge, improving governance capacity especially in domains where technical complex-
ities operate (nancial services, for example). Second, it depoliticizes governance, moving
decision-making to technical and expert domains, where decisions are more likely to be ren-
dered via evidence-based assessment and determination, balancing social and economic objec-
tives. Third, it provides technical-expert decision-makers with autonomy, creating technocratic
policy spaces that are not subject to short-termism or political pressures, but able to plan and
design policy in support of the longer-term sustainability of the sector. Fourth, freed of short-
termism or political pressures, the agency model improves the prospects for policy continuity,
increasing policy certainty and the eciency of governance in the sector. Fifth, the agency
model enhances the credibility of regulatory commitments, reducing uncertainty by removing
the prospects for devastating ministerial interference and thus, in turn, helping to mobilize
private capital into the sector. Finally, agency-based modalities of governance are seen to engineer
high levels of legitimacy: [F]aith in the power of expertise as an engine of social improvement,
notes Majone, which neither legislators, courts nor bureaucratic generalists possess provides an
important source of legitimization for regulators (Majone 1997: 17, 1999: 12; see also Cook
and Mosedale 2007: 458). The twin pillars of expertise combined with independence thus provide
the cornerstone that cements regulatory governance as an eective, if not superior modality of
governance.
For others, the regulatory state is more than just a modality of governance: it is also a means
of reform and suggests an alternative, depoliticized agency through which to achieve market opera-
tion, eciency and thus development. Indeed, for many it represents a modality able to over-
come obstacles to reform, reform blockages and transform the whole of government incentive
structures in developing countries, where reforms have historically been bogged down by the
operation of perverse incentives, inecient bureaucracies, poor institutional design, account-
ability and oversight systems. For such proponents, while the regulatory state is thus about the
design and construction of new regulatory institutions and regulatory instruments, more fun-
damentally it is also about the realization of state-market outcomes (International Finance
Corporation 2010: 212; see also Hira et al. 2005; United Nations 2006: 1289). As the IFC
observes, Reforms that increase quality in regulatory procedures and requirements and more
importantly, in regulatory institutions, capacities and incentives can simultaneously improve a
countrys quality of social life and the conditions for economic activity (2010: 1). In the eyes of
the IFC, the regulatory state model is thus seen as a means to:
making public policy more ecient by allocating national resources to higher value users, by
reducing the risk of policy failures, and by nding eective policy designs that respect market
principles;
lowering policy costs and barriers to market entry for rms, goods, and services, which in
turn boosts foreign direct investment (FDI) and trade, increases the returns on participation
in formal markets, speeds the uptake of new technologies and other innovations, and frees
resources for other uses;
reducing policy risks for market actors by increasing transparency in the design and use of
policy and by involvement of stakeholders in shaping policies important to them;
improving business security and market neutrality of policy by increasing accountability for
policy implementation and results, and lowering corruption and vulnerability to capture
government functions.
(International
Finance Corporation 2010:
13)
Jarvis
66
Conclusion
Clearly, this image of the regulatory state is laden with objectives that go beyond a modality of
governance and encompass forms of policy transfer designed to construct markets and a series of
specic institutional types dened by neo-liberal market rationalism. The regulatory state thus
assumes a larger political project, one designed to embed developing states in a specic eco-
nomic and political order. As Julia Black notes, the focus on regulatory techniques (agency-
based regulation, stakeholder engagement and transparency practices, etc.) can result in a radical
rethinking of the ways in which societal ends can be achieved. However, it can [also] divert
attention from the issue of how those ends should be dened, and by whom (Black 2000: 598).
The danger, as Black observes, is that in pursuit of an increasingly proceduralized approach to
regulation, the literature and practices of regulation become technicized; the predominant
concern being the implementation of regulation rather than the values that are pursued: that the
focus on the epistemological character of regulation is obscuring issues of its moral form (ibid.;
see also Levi-Faur 2005: 14; North 1990).
While Black is correct to suggest that technicized discourses can conceal the values that
underlie them, it remains the case that constructing regulatory states in the global South of
whatever moral form rests on a series of technical instrumentalities. These fall into three main
areas: rst, design of regulatory instruments, including institutional composition, functional
structure and rule deployment; second, capacity and operational requirements, including
resource, technical, administrative and analytical capacities; and third, institutional technologies
for normalizing and proceduralizing the various dimensions of regulation, including the instan-
tiation of legitimacy, trust, and compliance regimes. In the most visceral sense, these require-
ments speak to the displacement and redesign of entire institutional landscapes in a process that
involves new rules, new ways of making and enforcing rules, new incentive systems for
engendering compliance and distributing costs and economic gains among sectoral actors, and
new accountability, participation, and transparency instruments that serve as functional
mechanisms to sustain governance and eciency in the sector. While, of course, much atten-
tion focuses on the institutional design elements of regulatory governance, the greater and
more signicant quantum rests in evolving a series of highly complex reexive relationships
between agential actors, formal institutions, procedural authority and norms that instantiate
the new institutional and rule environment (Cook and Mosedale 2007: 45). It is this latter
series of institutionalsocio-political technologies that suggests a much greater, more compli-
cated, problematic, and costly set of relationships to construct and a political space where,
potentially, errors, possibilities for malecence, regulatory capture, corruption and less than
optimal sector outcomes, ultimately rest. Constructing governance regimes that are legitimate
and perceived to be so, that are observed to be transparent and free from special interest
capture, and function in a way that is seen to balance public and private sector interests while
delivering enhanced social and economic outcomes, is a highly complex regulatory exercise.
These dimensions of regulatory governance thus suggest a much greater series of costs,
capacities and institutional technologies across a wide spectrum of socio-political sites (the
judiciary, administrative review systems, tribunals and appeals processes, enforcement and com-
pliance regimes, consultation and engagement systems, etc.), than might rst appear to be
the case. Indeed, while proponents of regulatory modes of governance launder their cost-
eectiveness and suggest they impose few scal burdens on the state, in reality the acquisition
and realization of the soft-institutional technologies necessary to ensure their ecient func-
tioning represent extensive acquisition, set up, implementation, and maintenance costs (see
Minogue 2004).
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
67
Table 5.2 A comparative typology of the interventionist and regulatory state
Attributes Quasi-patrimonial state Interventionist
state
Regulatory
state
Required capacities and attributes
Functional
roles
Reproduction and maintenance of social,
political and economic order
Redistribution Constructing markets Institutional technologies for the
collection, ordering and
dissemination of information
Servicing socio-political-economic networks Macroeconomic stabilization
(economic growth, employment,
ination and interest rates)
Enhancing market
efciency
Technical and institutional
platforms to overcome
information asymmetries
Preserving and enhancing existing authority
structures
Enhancing access to social,
economic and political resources
Facilitating capital
mobilization
Access to information provisions
and state-based information
mechanisms of disclosure
Protecting vested interests Providing credible
commitments
Participatory processes in
decision-making
Controlling dissent Consultative and review
mechanisms
Effective accountability
mechanisms
Institutional capacity for third
parties to enforce/seek redress to
enforce government
commitments
Market-based clearing and
settlement systems across various
sectors
Institutional/market design
capacity
Table 5.2 (continued)
Attributes Quasi-patrimonial state Interventionist
state
Regulatory
state
Required capacities and attributes
Instruments Patron-client-based access to/distribution of
resources
Taxation Rule-making Institutional mechanisms to
ensure information
transparencies
Indirect coercion through access/denial of
patronage
Borrowing Compliance and
enforcement
Effective, functioning and
impartial judiciary
Dispensation of access/denial to state
resources/revenue streams
Fiscal expenditures Administrative review
and adjudication
Judicial legitimacy and
recognized authority
Control and access to markets/business/
governance domains
Budget allocations and resource
transfers between groups
Competitive tendering Negligible to low levels of judicial
corruption
Monetary policy Issuance of contracts Adequate judicial capacity
Fiscal policy Licenses Administrative review/tribunals
proceduralization
Industrial policy Setting standards and
codes
Compliance and audit capacities
across various institutional
spectrums
Dening and controlling
procedural mechanisms
Functional property rights
Enforcement and punitive
mechanisms across various
institutional spectrums
Probity monitoring and
enforcement mechanisms
(Continued on next page)
Table 5.2 (continued)
Attributes Quasi-patrimonial state Interventionist
state
Regulatory
state
Required capacities and attributes
Key actors Oligarchs Political parties Regulators Adequate and independent
resources for regulators and
regulatory affairs
Political elites Civil servants Industry/private sector
groups
Platform capacity for stakeholder
engagement/review in decision-
making
Business/economic elites Corporate groups Civil society groups Sufcient analytical and human
capacity to populate regulator
Nominated mandarins Trade unions Technocrats and experts Adequate compensation to
attract and retain personnel with
sufcient analytical and expert
knowledge capacity
Administrative tribunals Sufcient capacity and resources
to operationalize transparent
administrative review processes
Judiciary/Judges Operational accountability
mechanisms to ensure regulator
is held accountable for decisions
Disclosure, transparency and
freedom of information
mechanisms to ensure against
regulatory capture by sectional
interests
Realized legitimacy of the
regulator in discharge of
regulatory mandate
Table 5.2 (continued)
Attributes Quasi-patrimonial state Interventionist
state
Regulatory
state
Required capacities and attributes
Conict arenas Relationships between oligarchs Budgetary allocations Competition for control
over rule-making
Review and disputation
procedures are in place and
operative
Elite competition for access to oligarchs Entitlements Disputes/inter-agency
competition for rule
ownership
Enforcement mechanisms for
compensation
Competition/disputes over patronage
entitlements
Budget transfers Disputes over domain
authority, reach and
extensity
High-capacity administrative
review
Factionalism and disputes between political
and social networks
Ministerial control over resource
allocation
Disputes over rule
interpretation
Compliance to and respect for
administrative proceduralism
Inter-ministerial/ministry
competition
Key Institutions and
governance modalities
Oligarch/elite control of key
decision-making institutions/apparatus
Parliament Parliamentary
committees
Ability to reallocate power from
centralized bureaucracies to
independent administrative units
Nominated senior political mandarins Civil service/bureaucracy Independent agencies Ability to mediate inter-agency
resource competition
Elite-controlled executive branch Ministerial departments Commissions Ability to coordinate among
polycentric nodes of governance
State-owned enterprises Tribunals
Command and control Public hearings
Polycentric decision-
making structures
Policy style Top-down, elite-dominated, command and
control, low levels of accountability or
transparency
Discretionary, populist, political Rule-bound, mandated,
legalistic
(Continued on next page)
Table 5.2 (continued)
Attributes Quasi-patrimonial state Interventionist
state
Regulatory
state
Required capacities and attributes
Political culture Oligarch/elite-based power Corporatist, hierarchical,
centralized, top-down; statist
Pluralist, diffuse,
administrative, technical,
specialist, domain specic,
market-orientated
personal/family power networks
Dominance of oligarchic/elite political/
social/economic networks
Circulation of power positions among
elites
Political accountability Nominal accountability Direct/representative
democracy
Indirect/agency-based
Intra-elite informal accountability through
patron-client networked based consent
Source: Adapted from Majone 1997: 1215. Jarvis, D. S. L., Regulatory states in the South: Can they exist and do we want them? The case of the Indonesian power sector (1 December
2010). Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy Research Paper No. LKYSPP10-11. Available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1738189 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1738189
Bibliography
Almond, Gabriel A. 1988. The return of the state, American Political Science Review 82(3): 85374.
Almond, Gabriel A. and Stephen J. Genco. 1977. Clouds, clocks, and the study of politics, World Politics
29 (4): 489522.
Ananta, Aris and Yohanes Eko Riyanto. 2006. Riding along a bumpy road: Indonesian economy in an
emerging democratic era, ASEAN Economic Bulletin 23(1): 110.
BBC World Service, September 15, 2010.
Besant-Jones, John E. 2006. Reforming power markets in developing countries: What have we learned?
Energy and Mining Sector Board Discussion Paper no. 19, World Bank, Washington, DC.
Beck, Ulrich. 1999. World Risk Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Black, Julia. 2000. Prodecuralizing regulation: part 1, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20(4): 597614.
Blankart, Charles B. 1990. Strategies of regulatory reform: An economic analysis with some remarks on
Germany, in Giandomenico Mojone (ed.) Deregulation or Reregulation? Regulatory Reform in Europe and
the United States. London: Pinter Press, 21122.
Braithwaite, John and Peter Draos (eds). 2000. Global Business Regulation.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.
Carroll, Toby. 2010. Delusions of Development: The World Bank and the Post-Washington Consensus in
Southeast Asia. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Clark, William Roberts. 1998. Agents and structures: Two views of preferences, two views of institutions,
International Studies Quarterly 42(2): 24570.
Cobden, Richard, David Mitrany and Kenichi Ohmae. 2005. Liberal Internationalism and the Decline of the
State. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Cook, Paul and Sarah Mosedale. 2007. Regulation, Markets and Poverty. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Cortell, Andrew P. and Susan Peterson. 2001. Limiting the unintended consequences of institutional
change, Comparative Political Studies 34(7): 768 99.
Dessler, David. 1999. Constructivism within a positivist social science, Review of International Studies 25:
12337.
Dowding, Keith. 1995. The Civil Service. London: Routledge.
Hall, John A. and G. John Ikenberry. 1989. The State .
Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Hall, Peter. 1986. Governing
the Economy: The Politics of State Intervention in Britain and France. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hawkesworth, Mary. 1992. Epistemology and policy analysis, in William N. Dunn and Rita M. Kelly
(eds) Advances in Policy Studies since 1950. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Hay, Colin and Daniel Wincott. 1998. Structure, agency and historical institutionalism, Political Studies
46(5): 9517.
Held, David. 1995. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Hintze, Otto. 1975. The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hira, A., D. Huxtable, and A. Leger. 2005. Deregulation and participation: An international survey of
participation in electricity regulation, Governance 18(1): 5388.
Holliday, Ian. 2000. Is the British state hollowing out?, The Political Quarterly 71(2): 16776.
Hood, Christopher and Colin Scott. 1996. Bureaucratic regulation and new public management in the
United Kingdom: Mirror-image developments?, Journal of Law and Society 23(3): 32145.
——, Colin Scott, Oliver James, George Jones and Tony Travers. 1999. Regulation Inside Government.
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
International Finance Corporation. 2010. Regulatory governance in developing countries, Investment
Climate Advisory Services, Washington, DC, World Bank.
Jarvis, Darryl S.L. 2007. Risk, globalization and the state: A critical appraisal of Ulrich Beck and the world
risk society thesis, Global Society, 21(1): 2346.
—— 2010. Institutional processes and regulatory risk: A case study of the Thai energy sector, Regulation
and Governance 4: 175202.
Jaswal, Pragya and Mitali Das Gupta. 2006. Energy demands and sustaining growth in Southeast Asia,
Asia 2015: Promoting Growth, Ending Poverty. Available at: www.asia2015conference.org
Jayasuriya, Kanishka. 2005. Economic constitutionalism, liberalism and the new welfare governance,
Working Paper no. 121, June, Asia Research Centre, Murdoch University, Perth, Western Australia.
Jordana, Jacint, David Levi-Faur and Xavier Fernandez Marin. 2009. The global diusion
of regulatory
agencies: Channels
of transfer and stages of diusion, IBEI Working Papers, 2009/28, Barcelona.
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
73
Kapur, Devash, John P. Lewis and Richard Webb, 1997. The World Bank: Its First Half Century.
Washington, DC: The Bookings Institution.
Krasner, Stephen D. 1984. Approaches to the state: Alternative conceptions and historical dynamics,
Comparative Politics 16(2): 23246.
—— 1988. Sovereignty: An institutional perspective, Comparative Political Studies 21(1): 6694.
Legaspi, Perla E. 2006. Reform and practices in local regulatory governance: The case of the Philippines,
in Martin Minogue and Ledivina Cariño (eds) Regulatory Governance in Developing Countries. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar, 13856.
Levi-Faur, David. 2005. The global diusion of regulatory capitalism, Annals of the American Academy of
Political and Social Science 598: 1232.
—— 2010. Regulation and regulatory governance, Jerusalem Papers in Regulation and Governance,
Working Paper 10, February, Jerusalem Forum on Regulation and Governance, Hebrew University, Israel.
——and Jacint Jordana. 2005. Regulatory capitalism: Policy irritants and convergent divergence, Annals of
the American Academy of Political and Social Science 598: 1917.
Lundquist. 1987. Implementation Steering: An Actor-Structure Approach.
McLennan, Gregor. 1991. Marxism, Pluralism and Beyond: Classic Debates and New Departures. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Majone, Giandomenico. 1996 The rise of statutory regulation in Europe, in Giandomenico Majone and
Jeremy Richardson (eds) Regulating Europe . London: Routledge, 4760.
—— 1997 From the positive to the regulatory state: Causes and consequences of changes in the mode of
governance, Estudio/Working paper 1997/93, Centro de Estudios Avanzados en Ciencias Socales,
Instituto Juan, Madrid, Spain.
—— 1999 The regulatory state and its legitimacy problems. West European Politics 22(1): 124.
—— 2006 The internationalization of regulation: Implications for developing countries,
in Martin Min-
ogue and Ledivina
Cariño (eds) Regulatory Governance in Developing Countries. Cheltenham: Edward
Elgar, 3960.
March, J.G. and J.P. Olsen. 1979a. Organizational choice under ambiguity, in J.G. March and J.P. Olsen
(eds) Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations. Bergen: Universitetsforlaget, 1023.
——and J.P. Olsen. 1979b. Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations. Bergen: Universitetsforlaget.
——and Johan P. Olsen. 1994. Institutional Perspectives on Political Institutions.
Mason, Edward S. and Robert E. Asher. 1973. The World Bank since Bretton Woods. Washington, DC: The
Bookings Institution.
Minogue, Martin. 2004. Public management and regulatory governance: Problems of policy transfer to
developing countries, in Paul Cook, Colin Kirkpatrick, Martin Minogue and David Parker (eds) Leading
Issues in Competition, Regulation and Development. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 16581.
—— 2006. Apples and oranges: Comparing international experiences in regulatory reform, in Martin
Minogue and Ledivina Cariño (eds) Regulatory Governance in Developing Countries. Cheltenham: Edward
Elgar, 6181.
Nettl, J.P. 1968. The state as a conceptual variable, World Politics 20(4): 55992.
North, Douglas. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Orren, K. and S. Skowronek (eds). 1993. The Dynamics of American Politics: Approaches and Interpretations.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——and S. Skowronek. 1994. Beyond the iconography of order: Notes for a new2 institutionalism,in
L. Dodd and C. Jillson (ed.) Dynamics of American Politics. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——and Stephen Skowronek. 19981999. Regimes and regime building in American government: A
review of literature on the 1940s, Political Science Quarterly 113(4): 689702.
Phillips, Nicola. 2006. States and modes of regulatory governance in the global political economy,in
Martin Minogue and Ledivina Cariño (eds) Regulatory Governance in Developing Countries. Cheltenham:
Edward
Elgar, 1738.
Przeworski, Adam.
1987a. Methods of Cross-National Research, 197083: An Overview,3149.
——(ed.). 1987b. Comparative Policy Research: Learning from Experience. Aldershot: Gower.
—— 1990. The State and the Economy under Capitalism. London: Routledge.
Ray, James Lee. 2001. Integrating levels of analysis in world politics, Journal of Theoretical Politics 13: 35588.
Razin, Assaf and Efraim Sadka. 2005. The Decline of the Welfare State. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 1994. The hollowing out of the state: The changing nature of the public service in
Britain, The Political Quarterly 65(2): 13851.
Jarvis
74
Robison, Richard and Andrew Rosser. 2000. Surviving the meltdown: Liberal reform and political oli-
garchy in Indonesia, in Richard Robison, Mark Beeson, Kanishka Jayasuriya and Hyuk-Rae Kim (eds)
Politics and Markets in the Wake of the Asian Crisis. London and New York: Routledge, 171 91.
Sari, Agus P. n.d. Power sector restructuring and public benets, World Resources Institute. Available at:
http://pdf.wri.org/power_politics/indonesia.pdf
Scott, Colin. 2004. Regulation in the age of governance: the rise of the post regulatory state, in Jacint
Jordana and Davi Levi-Faur, (eds) The Politics of Regulation: Institutions and Regulatory Reforms for the Age of
Governance. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 14574.
Skocpol, Theda. 1985. Bringing the state back in: Strategies of analysis in current research, in Peter B. Evans,
Dietrich Rueschemeyer and Theda Skocpol (eds) Bringing the State Back In. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 343.
Skowronek, Stephen. 1982. Building a New American State: The Expansion of National Administrative Capacities
18771920. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, David. 1999. Will Europe Work? London: Prole Books.
Spiller, Pablo T. 1996. Institutions and commitment, Industrial & Corporate Change 5(2): 42152.
——and Mariano Tommasi. 2005. The institutions of regulation: An application to public utilities,in
C. Menard and M.M. Shirley (eds) Handbook of New Institutional Economics. Dordrecht: Springer, 51543.
Stern, Jon. 1997. What makes an independent regulator independent, Business Strategy Review 8(2): 6774.
—— 2000. Electricity and telecommunications regulatory institutions in small and developing countries,
Utilities Policy 9: 13157.
——and Stuart Holder. 1999. Regulatory governance: Criteria for assessing the performance of regulatory
systems. An application to infrastructure industries in the developing countries of Asia, Utilities Policy 8:
3350.
Strange,
Susan. 2000. The Retreat
of the State: The Diusion of Power in the World Economy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Thomas, Steve, David Hall and Violeta Corral. 2009. Electricity privatization and restructuring in Asia-Pacic.
Available at: www.psiru.org (accessed 14 June 2010).
Therborn, Göran. 1986. Neo-Marxist, pluralist, corporatist, statist theories and the welfare state,inA.Kazancigil
(ed.) The State in Global Perspective , Northampton, NH: Gower, 20431.
Tilly, Charles. 1984. Big Structures, Large Processes, Huge Comparisons. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
United Nations. 2006. Diverging growth and development: World economic survey 2006, Department
of Economic and Social Aairs, United Nations, New York.
van Creveld, Martin. 1999. The Rise and Decline of the State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Weiss, Linda. 1999. The Myth of the Powerless State. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Williams, J.H and N.K. Dubash. 2004. Asian electricity reform in historical perspective, PacicAairs 77:
41136.
Wu, Xun and Priyambudi Sulistiyanto. 2006. Independent power producer (IPP) in Indonesia and the
Philippines, in Michael Howlett M Ramesh (eds) De-regulation and Its Discontents: Rewriting the Rules in
Asia. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 10923.
Yoo, S.H. 2006. The casual relationship between electricity consumption and economic growth in the
ASEAN countries, Energy Policy 34: 357582.
Zhang, Yin-Fang and Margo Thomas. 2009. Regulatory reform and governance: A survey of selected
developing and transition economies, Public Administration and Development 29(4): 3309.
State theory and the rise of the regulartory state
75
6
The public choice perspective
Andy Whitford
Introduction
Over the last ve decades, few research agendas in the social sciences have brought about more
controversy about the proper role of government than public choice theory. On the one hand,
public choice researchers have built theories and empirical studies that start with the core intuitions
of economics but extend from that to describe a range of activities in government. On the other
hand, political scientists and those working in the policy sciences often point to public choice
theory as a primary example of the excesses and pathologies of the rational choice paradigm.
This chapter describes some of the contributions to the study of public policy processes of
those who have helped build that agenda. I start with two assumptions: that public choice oers
some fundamental insights about how policy is made and implemented, and that some of the
insights drawn from public choice theory are fundamentally awed. Public choice, like many other
research agendas, is a collection of imperfect attempts to understand complex and dynamic phe-
nomena. One reason for this imperfection is that unlike in physics where the particles rarely
learn from the researchers, those who make or implement policyor at least want to bend policy
for their own purposeshave often used public choice as a way of justifying those purposes.
Public choice is an important argument about the proper role of government (Majone 1989).
In brief, public choice theory uses the tools of economics to understand why politicians and
the people who elect them do what they do when they make decisions about what governments
will or should do. The ngerprints of economists are all over public choice theory, and this is
for good reason: many of those who founded public choice theory have gone on to receive
great acclaim for their contributions, including winning the Nobel Prize. Names like Kenneth
Arrow, Duncan Black, James Buchanan, Gordon Tullock, Anthony Downs, and Mancur Olson
are known largely in economics because of the contributions they made to the theoretical infra-
structure of this eld. Other names like William Riker and Elinor Ostrom are knowneven
though most of their footprints have been in political sciencebecause of their contributions to
public choice theory.
Specically, public choice has changed how we understand the inner workings of democratic
decision-making. For scholars like James Buchanan, who as much as (and probably more) than
any other person put public choice on the intellectual map, public choice is dierent from how
76
political science (at least political science pre-public choice) sees the world, because public choice
is politics without romance. For many people, public choice is largely associated with one set
of people and in fact one state of the Union: Virginia. What public choice brought to the table
was a willingness to ignore most of what we thought we knew about politics by situating
every analysis in a logical framework built on the assumption that ocials (either elected or
unelected) are not public-spirited: that they do not necessarily pursue the public interest as
servants of the people. Indeed, many debates in public choice have raged around the question
of whether we can ever know what the people wantwhether there is a knowable social
welfare function.
In traditional economics, a person wants to maximize his or her own utility, and while one
of the signature results of public choice is that this assumption does not require that people fail
to care about others, outsiders often see it as a restrictive assumption that people are mostly
guided by their own self-interest. Of course, people outside government, living in markets,
sometimes seem to follow their own interests, so public choice theorists did not see much of a
problem assuming the same about people in governmentthat they are just like the rational
actors that populate traditional economic theories of markets.
Economists see the world through the lens of methodological individualism (a focus on
individuals over groups), which is dierent from how political science circa the 1950s largely
saw politics. But another signature contribution of public choiceone not always recognized in
either political science or the policy sciencesis that the agenda changed how economists saw
the world: that in government, the costs and benets of choice are often collective, rather than
individual. So public choice theorists had to throw out many of the intuitions of the traditional
economic model because this means that an individual is aected by the decisions they make in
complicated ways.
This chapter will tell the story of public choice theory by walking through the canon: the
insights that most people who have added to the literature would count among the foremost
contributions, the things that they can hang their hats on. I engage these insights by considering
six basic questions that public choice theory has sought to answer about the electors, the elec-
ted, and the governments they create and maintain. I want to be clear that there are other ways
to recount these insights. For instance, Shughart sees the contributions as revolving around the
dierent ways political preferences are aggregated and/or expressedof how theorists have
come to understand elections, legislatures, bureaucracies, and other institutions such as the courts
(Shughart 2008). Many people have tried to summarize the eld, with varying degrees of thick
description for example (Mueller 2003; Rowley and Schneider 2004; Shughart and Razzolini
2001). The approach taken in this chapter has as its inspiration Mueller (1976).
Public choice tells us that:
electing better people will not, by itself, lead to much better government. Adopting the
assumption that all individuals, be they voters, politicians, or bureaucrats, are motivated
more by self-interest than by public interest evokes a Madisonian perspective on the pro-
blems of democratic governance. Like that founding father of the American constitutional
republic, public choice recognizes that men are not angels and focuses on the importance
of institutional rules under which people pursue their own objectives.
(Shughart 2008)
As such, the agenda is similar to other, aliated theories in economics, such as new institu-
tional economics, that also worry about institutional design and eectiveness in a variety of
economic and political settings. That topic is the focus of the next chapter in this volume.
The public choice perspective
77
Six questions and the canon
This overview of public choice theory centers on six important questions this literature has
sought to answer over the past ve decades. The rst question can be written as why is there
collective choice? One way we can write the second question is do we need politicians?
The third question follows from the second: what happens when we have politicians? While the
fourth question is narrower than the rst three, it shows how important public choice theory
has been to the evolution of both economics and the policy sciences. The fourth question is
what we do about those pesky public goods? While the fth question is not unique to public
choice theory, public choice theory has helped to answer this question in ways that are both
unique and novel. The fth question this review will discuss is what should society want?
While the sixth question has involved only a select subgroup of public choice theorists and
researchers, this question is particularly important for a review that describes the importance of
public choice theory for those interested in public policy processes. The sixth question is what
about those who implement public policy?
One reason to evaluate the canon of public choice theory from the perspective of these six
questions is that those outside the canon often see it as a monolith. Specically, readers often see
public choice theory as solely centered on not using the state to improve public policy outcomes.
This is understandable if only because of the aforementioned conservative bias sometimes expres-
sed by those who founded and have continued to expand the eld. Yet, as this review hope-
fully will make clear, public choice is sometimes less a well-constructed and synthetic paradigm
than it is a starting point for evaluating a wide array of institutions we observe every day in
governments around the world. Together these questions show the breadth, reach, and even
internal disputes that are hallmarks of public choice theory.
It is abundantly clear that a full review of these questions is beyond the scope of this chapter.
Interested readers are directed to the other reviews noted above, and those interested in a full
discussion of certain topics are directed to classics such as (Arrow 1963; Black 1958; Buchanan
and Tullock 1962; Downs 1957; Niskanen 1971; Olson 1965; Riker 1962). For instance, Shughart
and Razzolini (2001) provide a range of perspectivesincluding showing public choice theorys
fractures.
Why is there collective choice? As noted above, public choice theory builds on the axioms of
traditional microeconomic theory (e.g. atomistic competition, having many buyers and sellers,
particular information conditions, and other attributes of perfect competition), which build on
simple assumptions about individuals being both rational and self-interested. In markets, while
all the attributes of traditional microeconomic theory lead to outcomes that economists would
call socially preferable (namely, Pareto ecient outcomes), that is not the case in some important
situations.
The simplest context to see this is the well-known prisoners dilemma, which shows that two
individuals, both pursuing their self-interest and acting rationally, may achieve outcomes that
benet neither one. As Dennis Mueller puts it in his classic survey of public choice theory,
problems of collective choice exist in all but a purely Hobbesian, anarchistic society and are
coterminous with the existence of recognizable groups and communities (Mueller 1976: 397).
For public choice theorists, these situations happen when people debate and select dierent levels
or attributes of the provision of public goods. Examples include national defense, public safety,
and other attributes of free and civilized societies. Theorists and empiricists have debated dierent
solutions to the problem of public goods provision. Because of these eorts, we now know that
how society solves these kinds of problems depends in part on the size of the group and how
long individuals expect to interact (Buchanan 1965; Olson 1965).
Whitford
78
As Mueller puts it, Thus, democracy, formal voting procedures for making and enforcing
collective choices, is needed by communities of only a certain size and impersonality (Mueller
1976: 398). This shows that in some situations individuals choose to make decisions collectively
and these decisions must be governed by rules of the game, the purpose of which is to reg-
ularize the interactions to reduce the chance that people will make decisions individually that
lead to socially suboptimal outcomes.
In one sense, public choice theory became an attempt inside the discipline of economics to
understand and perhaps formulate dierent rules, given that individuals are rational, self-serving,
and cognizant of the need for collective choice. This was dierent from what political scientists
were doing at that time because of a modeling technology that owed from traditional micro-
economics. Essentially, public choice theory had pure microfoundations. Yet, inside economics,
those foundations had led most economists to ignore collective choice. An example of this is
the Keynesian approach to macroeconomic analysis, which included government as almost an
omniscient and pure dictator/planner. Other views, such as those expressed within rational
expectations theory, also modeled the politician and/or bureaucrat in naïve waysin this case,
the planner is largely inept (Mitchell 2001).
In sum, public choice theory sees a need for collective choice but also envisions collective
choice as fraught with opportunities for individuals to subvert the collective process for their
own ends.
Do we need politicians? Recognizing the need for collective choice does not answer the ques-
tion of what kind of collective choice we need. For this, public choice theorists turned to the
tools of formal modeling, and in doing so they encountered an array of subsidiary questions.
First, what happens if people try to make decisions under unanimity rule? The answer largely
has been it isnt easy. Specically, public choice theory asked whether people, making decisions
under a unanimity rule, could decide to support the provision of public goods. Writers argued
for processes that essentially auctioned o goods (using a variant of Walrasian tâtonnement, with
prices discovered through a series of bids) (the so-called Lindahl equilibrium) (Lindahl 1919;
Milleron 1972). The diculty with this outcome is that it must be discovered, over time, through
interactions that are themselves costly (Black 1958; Buchanan and Tullock 1962). Also, the
process is susceptible to strategic behavior.
A consequence is that theorists then tried to understand optimal decision rules in a demo-
cratic society. If unanimity increased costs, was another rule less costly? For Mueller, studies like
Buchanan and Tullock (1962) and Breton (1974) show us that the optimal rule is thus the one for
which the expected gain in utility from redening the bill to gain one more supporter just equals
the expected loss in time from doing so (Mueller 1976: 402). Mueller goes on to say that the
problem is that the optimal rule will vary across issues.
Many societies use majority rule, and while a full discussion of its advantages and disadvantages is
beyond the scope of this chapter, a few key aspects warrant emphasis. Essentially, Rae (1969)
and Taylor (1969) show that majority rule is the only rule that reduces the potential bad out-
comes, or what we might call regret, that a supporter would feel if her proposal does not pass
(or one that she opposes does pass). The diculty with majority rule, though, is the prospect of
cycling. Discussing cycling can be particularly technical but the intuition is quite straightfor-
ward. In some cases, when individuals have certain types of preferences, there is a chance that
no one proposal can gain a majority that is impervious to the introduction or consideration of
an alternative proposal. Debates have raged over what this means in practice, even though the
technical literature is fairly consistent on this possibility. A reason for this consistency is that we
have studied cycling for at least 200 years, and technical work has conrmed long-held intui-
tions (McKelvey 1976; Satterthwaite 1975; Schoeld 1978). Some models suggest cycling is less
The public choice perspective
79
likely to happen in some situations, usually involving large numbers of voters or unusual deci-
sion rules (Saari 2006; Tovey 2010).
Of course, political scientists have also helped us to extend our early understanding of the
diculties of direct representation. Economists contributed much of the early legwork in this
area, but political scientists and others working in positive political theory have helped to
broaden those early intuitions. This is now mostly associated with the arena of social choice and
welfare than with public choice theory, although the roots are similar. Instead, public choice
theorists are associated with their development of the consequences of cycling such as log-
rolling. Buchanan and Tullock described some of the issues involved in logrolling extensively in
their classic 1962 book. Essentially, logrolling ows from dierent individuals nding issues dif-
ferently salient. Views vary on logrolling and its usefulness in voting systems, partly due to some
beliefs that logrolls may reduce eciency rather than increase it. Commonly cited examples
include tax policy and pork barreling.
What happens when we have politicians? Most people think of logrolling in the context of legislatures,
and since we have elected politicians in most democracies, public choice theorists sought to under-
stand how individuals, considering their own preferences and their options, choose representatives.
Moreover, how do politicians, given those preferences and options, compete for votes?
The central result in this area is the median voter theorem, which says that if preferences
lie in a single (liberal-conservative) dimension, and if people vote for the candidate closest to
their own position on that dimension, then the winning candidate will pick the position of the
median voter. This result, rst oered in Hotelling (1929) but elaborated most notably by
Downs (1957) and Black (1958), is considered the pioneering contribution in public choice
(Mueller 1976: 408, fn. 22). The power of the theorem has led to a host of renements, some
of which are particularly important for understanding public policy processes. For instance,
when candidates are elected in stages (e.g. primaries followed by general elections), the candi-
dates are pulled apart in terms of the policy positions they select (e.g., Aronson and Ordeshook
1972). When the model moves to two policy dimensions, the situation becomes even more
complicated, if only because of the importance of the cycling theorems noted above.
The literature on the median voter theorem then moved on to even more rened versions.
For instance, what happens when some voters are alienated? What happens when the distributions
of policy preferences are multi-modal? What happens when we take into account logrolling
(especially when a group with minority policy preferences supports a candidate)? In all of these
and other situations, the constant worry about cycling remains. As Downs (1957) notes, there
are real implications of cycling if it leads to the regular defeat of incumbents since policy is essen-
tially swinging in the two-dimensional space. While in some systems (like the US) incumbents
seem to enjoy regular advantages at the point of re-election, in other situations (e.g. municipal
elections, school boards) incumbents often lose.
In Hotellings original model, voters choose from among two candidates, but this is not so
for much of the world since multiple parties often compete for votes. The canonical position in
public choice theory recognizes that single-member plurality, rst-past-the-post (SMP) systems
are a specic rule chosen to govern the operation of democratic systems, and that other systems,
such as proportional representation (PR) can lead to qualitatively dierent outcomes. Following
pioneering work by political scientists like Riker (1962), which showed that dierent systems
converged to coalitions of roughly the same sizes, scholars like Schoeld added numerous
wrinkles to the study of multiparty democracies. Much of this follows from the search for stability
in systems where there are two policy dimensions.
The public choice canon also sought to understand what happens to voters when politicians
are asked to represent constituents. For instance, Mueller describes how public choice studies
Whitford
80
broke the vote decision into components that depended on comparing the costs (of voting),
with the potential benets (e.g. the risky public benets and the expected private benets). This
focus, found in writings like Downs (1957) and Tullock (1967), is important if only because it
led to one of the classic statements about politics held by those working in public choice theory:
that the costs of gathering political information or voting, as they grow, will swamp the benets
of information acquisition or votingwith the eect that people may not vote or acquire
information. This rational ignorance or rational abstention argument is particularly attractive
because it helps to explain the lack of attention or involvement by some people in (what others may
consider) important policy decisions. The upshot: For most people the outcome of an election
is a public good and political participation is vulnerable to free-riding (Mueller 1976: 411).
Another important contribution is a statement about how politicians try to control those who
implement public policy. Below, I will briey discuss one position in this literature (the budget-
maximizing bureaucrat), but much of the work in the public choice canon contributed to
what we know now as the Congressional dominance perspective. As Shughart notes:
In that model, government bureaucracies are not free to pursue their own agendas. On the
contrary, agency policy preferences mirror those of the members of key legislative com-
mittees that oversee particular areas of public policy that constrain bureaucratic discre-
tion by exercising their powers to conrm political appointees to senior agency positions,
to mark up bureau budget requests, and to hold public hearings.
(2008)
The congressional dominance model has received serious challenge in political science (Miller
2005), but remains signicantly inuential in public choice theory.
What do we do about those pesky public goods? As is apparent above, public choice theorists have
made signicant contributions to the study of public goods. The purpose of this discussion is to
describe three important basic ndings that economists have discovered about public goods in
practice. Recent advances in the theory of public goods provisiontheoretically, empirically,
and (especially) experimentallyare also relevant here, although space constraints limit thorough
coverage (Scotchmer 2002).
In 1956 Tiebout described a key point in public choice theory about public goods provision
(Tiebout 1956). Note that there are many dierent kinds of goods and that many variations in
publicness are possible. On the one hand, markets are ecient at delivering private goods; on
the other hand, pure public goods require true collective choice. Tiebout essentially showed that
individuals could select from dierent levels of public goods provision by voting with their
feet and moving from one community to another. In this decentralized model, individuals
compare and select, and Pareto optimality is achieved by grouping individuals together in politics
of homogenous tastes (Mueller 1976: 412), though having a large number of public goods neces-
sitates having a large number of communities to select from. It is hard to overstate the impact of
the Tiebout paradigm (Mieszkowski and Zodrow 1989). Increasingly, we understand Tiebout
sorting as part of a broader, more complex dynamic process.
If we can exclude people from partaking in the public good, then a host of other strategies
are available for guring out what goods people want, how much they want, and how to get
them
to reveal their
demand for the goods. In the public choice canon, these situations are
treated as access to club goods. The basic issue here is how, as we add individuals to the club, the
average cost of providing the good changes. When the average cost falls throughout, the opti-
mal group size is the entire population. However, if at some point in adding individuals the cost
of provision starts to rise, then the club will be smaller.
The public choice perspective
81
Buchanan (1965) laid the groundwork for understanding situations involving club goods with
the result that a host of studies have followed trying to understand settings as diverse as social
clubs and churches. One of the early issues encountered in the canon was how homogenous the
preferences were of those who wanted to join the club. In those situations, it is easier to form
the club and decide the optimal level of membership. The key is the size of the population
compared to the optimal size of the clubs, because we could see optimal provision through a
series of clubs as people select one from a set, and perhaps leave existing ones to start new ones
with people more like themselves (Mueller 1976). The real advantage of club goods, presumably,
is that Tiebout-type solutions require some sort of geographic colocation to allow people to
vote with their feet.
Since the advent of the Tiebout and club goods perspectives on the public goods problem, a
whole host of studies have sought to extend and enrich our understanding of these situations in
which traditional microeconomic perspectives rooted in perfect competition seem decient.
Some have been theoretical, while others have been empirical or experimental techniques. For
the purposes of this chapter, the reader is pointed to broader treatments of the development of
this literature. However, it is important to describe the impact of one strand of this literature for
understanding public policy processes generally.
Elinor Ostrom was awarded the Nobel Prize in Economics in 2009 (jointly with Oliver
Williamson, the progenitor of transactions costs economics), largely for her studies in new insti-
tutional economics and other new avors of political economy. Her signature contributions
have come from providing a uniquely political science-inuenced view of how people manage
common pool resources (CPRs) (which is one way the public goods literature has evolved). CPRs
are public goods involving natural or human-made resource systems (e.g. sheries or water
sources) for which it is either too dicult or costly to exclude individuals, so club goods theory
mostly does not apply. CPRs can suer from congestion because adding an additional user will
damage the current or future usage of this good by others. In her Governing the Commons: The
Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action, Ostrom identied design principles that societies
(perhaps governments but often autonomous collectivities of individuals) might use to manage
access to the CPR and reduce damage from congestion (Ostrom 1991). Widely known as the
Institutional Analysis and Design (IAD) framework, her approach is dierent from traditional
public choice theory, but can be seen as a logical continuation of debates central to the public
choice canon. Two themes warrant emphasis. First, individuals often select the solutions; they
are not imposed from outside (sometimes referred to as covenants without the sword
(Ostrom et al. 1992). Second, this research stream is dierent from broader public choice because it
relies heavily on thousands of case studies gleaned from CPRs around the world, along with
traditional theory and experimental research.
What should society want? As is apparent from the above discussion, it is an open question
whether public choice is mostly positive or mostly normative. It is impossible to discern this
and silly to group normative approaches as a separate question in this chaptermainly because
contributors to any research paradigm bring their own concerns and preferences whenever they
focus on a specic research question. Many associate the public choice paradigm with con-
servative movements and think tanks (Cato or the Liberty Fund) if only because many active
researchers are also policy commentators.
Consider public goods research. The Tiebout model is a positive statement of mobility and
goods selection by individuals in a geographic space populated by competing political jurisdic-
tions; the club goods model also makes positive statements. Yet, both have normative implica-
tions. Likewise, researchers use Ostroms IAD framework to understand how people provide
and manage CPRs. But Ostrom herself refers to distilled rules in this paradigm, especially in
Whitford
82
the case of irrigation systems, as design principles. Physics is useful for studying machines, just
as the positive tools of public choice theory help us to understand public goods. But just as the
use of machines implies engineers, the public choice paradigm has spawned normative claims
about what society should do. In this section, I briey review three important strands that
have helped us better to understand policy processes. Outsiders may not associate these with
public choice but the canon itself claims them as founding debates that have framed the elds
evolution. The three are the study of justice, the construction of constitutions, and the qualities
of social welfare functions.
First, the public choice canon claims Rawls theory of justice as an example of how theorists
could engage normative analysis from rst principles (Rawls 1971). Specically, Rawls starts
with ideas present in public choice theory: rational, egoistic individuals, who are not altruistic.
He then overlays a game of chance on this participation: people nd themselves in segments of
society that determine their happiness, but individuals can imagine what their location in these
segments might have been had the game of chance turned out dierently. Stepping behind the
veil of ignorance, individuals stand in the original position and choose the rules of the social
contract. For Rawls, justice is fairness.
Extensions, renements, and reassessments followed Rawls, but the main pointthe game of
chanceappears in other normative theories in the public choice paradigm. As Mueller notes,
What is important to the theory of public choice, however, is not the principles Rawls arrives
at, but the process by which he gets there (Mueller 1976). For instance, Mueller points to
similarity between Rawls and Buchanan and Tullocks theory of the constitution as a social
contract (Buchanan and Tullock 1962). If an individual is uncertain about who he will be in the
future, he will select a constitution that aects his welfare over a long period of time by placing
themselves in the envisaged positions of all future citizens (Mueller 1976). People are uncertain
about future circumstances, to the end that actual constitutions formed under unanimity rules
become just political contracts (ibid.). Uncertainty also shows up in Harsanyis view of constitu-
tions as social welfare functions, because individuals assume that they might be any other person in
the society in the future (that they might have a dierent persons preferences) (Harsanyi 1953).
Justice and constitutions clearly have normative aspects, but economists have long taken a
positive approach to social choice, like how they study individual choice. Individuals choose to
do the best they can with reference to their own utility functions. For over 70 years, economists
have considered the possibility of a social welfare function, but working with them seemed to
require making interpersonal comparisons of utility. In the case of a system of justice or a con-
stitution, the problem was deciding what we wanted from society: this debate also arises with
regard to a social welfare function. It is easier if people share an ethical belief. Arrows Impossibility
Theorem helps us to understand this better (Arrow 1963).
Given ve basic attributes of a society, Arrow argued that no social welfare function always
satises
all ve. The ve are
values that show up regularly in the public choice literature as well
as literatures on democratic theory. The rst is that the welfare function should allow for any
possible set of individual preferences. The second is that the welfare function should be Pareto
ecient. The third is that function should be consistent (transitive). The fourth is that it should
be non-dictatorial (no person should be able to overrule all other preferences). The last is that
preferences over irrelevant options should not be able to aect the choice between two other
alternatives. Public choice theorists want society to have a decision rule that would never violate
these postulates.
The public choice and social choice and welfare literatures have debated which postulate to
relax to make it possible to get a social welfare function. Many theorists who have rened or ela-
borated on Arrows theorem think a way out of this trap is to relax the assumption of universal
The public choice perspective
83
domain: that individual preferences should not be able to take any possible ordering. But this means
people cannot be free to choose as they are in markets because allowing that makes it dicult
for us to know what society as a whole wants. Or we could relax the independence assumption.
As Mueller notes:
Each in turn raises questions of what issues are to be decided, who is to decide, and of
those who decide, which preferences shall be weighted. Such choices directly or indirectly
involve interpersonal utility comparisons and must rest on some additional value postulates,
which if explicitly introduced would imply specic interpersonal utility comparisons. The
latter cannot be avoided.
(1976: 421)
What about those who implement public policy? One of the most persistent external perceptions of
the public choice canon is bureaucrat bashing. Specically, Niskanen (1971) argued that those
who implement policythe elected and (especially) the career bureaucratswould use advan-
tages they hold from their positions (expertise and information) to extract the largest possible
budgets. Public choice theory fears the budget-maximizing bureaucrat.
In many ways, the problem was one of competition. Niskanen argues that competition would
allow the comparison of the relative prices of competing bureaus and shift power from bureaucrats
to politiciansthat under competition spending on services would fall and technical eciency
increase. Renements argued that Niskanen inaccurately characterized the interaction between
bureaucrats and legislators (e.g. Blais and Dion 1991). Migué, Bélanger, and Niskanen (1974)
note that bureaucrats may maximize other goals instead of the supply of public services. Conybeare
(1984) argues that Niskanen implicitly assumes perfect price discrimination (see also Bendor et al.
1985; Breton and Wintrobe 1975). Miller and Moe (1983) model the legislature, which changes
the Niskanen prediction. Empirical studies are mixed at best on the Niskanen proposal (Boyne
1998; Conybeare 1984; Higgins et al. 1987). Conybeare (1984) notes that even if multiple, com-
petitive bureaus are competing for funding, rather than producing equivalent goods (as in McGuire
et al. (1979)), there may be negative side eects such as high monitoring costs. What, then, is
the value of competition? Miller and Moe (1983) show that competition for the public supply
of a good is valuable when it reveals information about actual supply costs, and thus places
monitors in better decisional positions and enhances their power. The advantage of competition
is how it reveals information by allowing comparison.
Conclusion
These six questions have helped to shape the public choice theory canon. The answers that have
been given for these questionsthe positions taken, the theorems oeredare arguments about
the rules of the game that underlie the operation of democratic systems around the world. Public
choice is an important strand in the diverse theories developed by social scientists to study policy
processes if only because the canon has changed how economists see the state. Rather than as a
benevolent dictator or a dolt, economists mostly see the state as a collection of actors, each
working for their own ends, sometimes working within the rules of the game and sometimes
changing those rules. At a minimum, economics is a richer discipline because of public choice.
The policy sciences and political science have also moved forward, if only because public choice
provides a foil against which to argue when building new theories of the policy processes.
It is important to reiterate that public choice is not a monolith, and there is an argument to
be made that public choice itself has been eclipsed by other rigorous and insightful views of the
Whitford
84
state that also have come from within economics. One is the competing Chicago School of
political economy, in which work by Gary Becker, George Stigler, Sam Peltzman and others
has fundamentally reshaped our understanding of what is eligible for formalization in terms of
economic theory. Mitchell notes that the dierent approaches taken by the Virginia and Chicago
schools have led to qualitatively dierent inferences about politics (e.g. as in the case of the
literature on regulatory politics). He notes: Most Virginians believe that politics is rarely ecient
while Chicagoans, apparently, believe that political institutions routinely achieve ecient results.
The contending arguments are both powerful and subtle (Mitchell 2001).
The second new school is that of political economics, whose leaders are economists like
Alberto Alesina, Torsten Persson, and Guido Tabellini (Blankart and Koester 2006). The main
thrust of the movement is to join important schools of thought, several of which were made
more important specically because of the public choice movement. Political economics joins
together the work of public choice with that of Lucas rational expectations macroeconomics,
and the game theory that has become omnipresent in all of economics. Specically, political eco-
nomics is dierent from the naïve view of macroeconomics because it builds in roles for rational
politicians, voters, and parties.
The nal assessment of the public choice paradigm is not in its narrow application to the
policy processes but its overall contribution to the way social scientists study policy: enriching
political science, challenging the policy sciences, reshaping economics, and even giving politicians
and voters something to talk about.
Bibliography
Aronson, P.H. and P.C. Ordeshook. 1972. Spatial strategies for sequential elections, in R.G. Niemi and
H.F. Weiseberg (eds) Probability Models of Collective Decision-Making. Columbus, OH: Merrill.
Arrow, Kenneth Joseph. 1963. Social Choice and Individual Values 2nd edn. New York: Wiley.
Bendor, Jonathon, Serge Taylor and Roland van Gaalen. 1985. Bureaucratic expertise versus legislative
authority: A model of deception and monitoring in budgeting. American Political Science Review 79(4):
104160.
Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blais, André and Stéphane Dion. 1991. The Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrat. Pittsburgh, PA: University of
Pittsburgh Press.
Blankart, C.B. and G.B. Koester. 2006. Political economics versus public choice, Kyklos 59(2): 171200.
Boyne, George A. 1998. Competitive tendering in local government: A review of theory and evidence,
Public Administration 76(4): 695712.
Breton, Albert. 1974. The Economic Theory of Representative Government. Chicago: Aldine Publishing.
——and R. Wintrobe. 1975. The equilibrium size of a budget-maximizing bureau: A note on Niskanens
theory of bureaucracy, The Journal of Political Economy 83(1): 195207.
Buchanan, James M. 1965. An economic theory of clubs, Economica 32(125): 114.
——, and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy.
Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Conybeare, John A.C. 1984. Bureaucracy, monopoly and competition: A critical analysis of the budget-
maximizing model of bureaucracy, American Journal of Political Science 28(3): 479502.
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper.
Harsanyi, John C. 1953. Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking, Journal of
Political Economy 61(5): 4345.
Higgins, Richard S., William F. Shughart II and Robert D. Tollison. 1987. Dual enforcement of the
antitrust laws, in Robert J. Mackay, James Cliord
Miller and Bruce
Yandle (eds) Public Choice and
Regulation: A View from Inside the Federal Trade Commission. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press.
Hotelling, Harold. 1929. Stability in competition, The Economic Journal 39(153): 4157.
Lindahl, Erik. 1919. Just taxation a positive solution, Classics in the Theory of Public Finance (134): 16876.
McGuire, Thomas, Michael Coiner and Larry Spancake. 1979. Budget-maximizing agencies and eciency
in government, Public Choice 34(3): 33357.
The public choice perspective
85
McKelvey, Richard D. 1976. Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for
agenda control, Journal of Economic Theory 12(3): 47282.
Majone, Giandomenico. 1989. Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Mieszkowski, P. and G.R. Zodrow. 1989. Taxation and the Tiebout model: The dierential eects of
head taxes, taxes on land rents and property taxes, Journal of Economic Literature 27(3): 1098146.
Migué, Jean-Luc, Gérard Bélanger and William A. Niskanen. 1974. Toward a general theory of managerial
discretion, Public Choice 17(1): 2747.
Miller, Gary J. 2005. The political evolution of principal-agent models, Annual Review of Political Science 8:
20325.
——and Terry M. Moe. 1983. Bureaucrats, legislators, and the size of government, American Political
Science Review 77(2): 297322.
Milleron, J.C. 1972. Theory of value with public goods: a survey article, Journal of Economic Theory 5(3):
41977.
Mitchell, William C. 2001. The old and new public choice: Chicago versus Virginia, in William F.
Shughart II and Laura Razzolini (eds) The Elgar Companion to Public Choice, Northampton, MA: Edward
Elgar, 332.
Mueller, Dennis C. 1976. Public choice: A survey, Journal of Economic Literature 14(2): 395433.
—— 2003. Public Choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Niskanen, William A. 1971. Bureaucracy and Representative Government. Chicago: Aldine.
Olson, Mancur. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1991. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Ostrom,
E., J. Walker
and R. Gardner. 1992. Covenants with and without a sword: Self-governance is
possible, American Political Science Review 86(2): 40417.
Rae, Douglas W. 1969. Decision-rules and individual values in constitutional choice, The American Political
Science Review 63(1): 4056.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Riker, William H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Rowley, Charles Kershaw and Friedrich Schneider. 2004. The Encyclopedia of Public Choice, 2 vols. Boston:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Saari, Donald G. 2006. Which is better: The Condorcet or Borda winner?, Social Choice and Welfare 26(1):
10729.
Satterthwaite, Mark A. 1975. Strategy-proofness and Arrow s conditions: Existence and correspondence
theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions, Journal of Economic Theory 10(2): 187217.
Schoeld, Norman. 1978. Instability of simple dynamic games, The Review of Economic Studies 45(3): 57594.
Scotchmer, S. 2002. Local public goods and clubs, Handbook of Public Economics 4: 19972042.
Shughart, William F. 2008. Public Choice, in David R. Henderson (ed.) The Concise Encyclopedia of
Economics. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 42730.
——and Laura Razzolini. 2001. The Elgar Companion to Public Choice. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.
Taylor, M. 1969. Critique and comment: Proof of a theorem on majority rule, Behavioral Science 14(3):
22831.
Tiebout, C.M. 1956. A pure theory of local expenditures, The
Journal of Political Economy: 41624.
Tovey, Craig
A. 2010. The almost surely shrinking yolk, Mathematical Social Sciences 59(1): 7487.
Tullock, Gordon. 1967. Toward a Mathematics of Politics. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Whitford
86
7
Institutional analysis and
political economy
Michael D. McGinnis and Paul Dragos Aligica
Political economy
1
and the analysis of non-market decision settings
The foundational idea of the Ostroms institutionalism is simple but powerful in its implications:
analysis of the public sector should be no dierent in its basic assumptions from studies of the
market-oriented private sector. The focus of analysis is in both cases the individuals and their
actions in various institutional arrangements. Methods used to understand complex economic
industries involving large and small prot-seeking enterprises competing within more or less
ecient and competitive markets, should be expected to be equally functional for the study of
equally complex public structures. The large number of public enterprises operating in a modern
society (at the national level or at local, metropolitan levels) could be studied using tools transfer-
able from one domain to another. Although the standard framework needs special adjustments
in order to get adapted to a phenomenon that is in the end dierent from the market-based phe-
nomena, the analysis of public governance issues requires an approach that is fundamentally similar
to the analysis of private industries (Ostrom and Ostrom 1965, 1977; E. Ostrom 1972, 1983, 1996).
The key is that public enterprises should be seen as organizations that produce goods and
services for a variety of consumers and groups of consumers. Public goods and services have
dierent characteristics and require a variety of arrangements and processes to be delivered. As
in the case of private enterprises, these features determine the nature of the institutions, strate-
gies and policies needed. The functional problems of production, acquisition, distribution, and
consumption of public and common goods lead to the emergence of complex institutional
arrangements.
Once one starts to look at the public sector through the lens of competitive public economies,
the reality will never be the same again. For instance, the observation that most private enterprises
purchase many of the goods and services that they need from other enterprises, draws attention
to the notion that production (physical rendering) of public services may be considered sepa-
rately from the provision of such services (i.e. the decision how to produce goods or services, or
decisions concerning the quantity and quality of these products) and there remains the separate
question of deciding on billing and other nancial details). Issues of scale and eciency,
concerned mainly with production, can be analytically considered separately from questions of
what public goods and services should be made available to members of the group that will
87
collectively consume them, and from questions about how producers will be paid and their
products evaluated (Ostrom and Ostrom 1965; E. Ostrom et al. 1994).
Distinctions among production, provision, nancing, and evaluation were laid out quite
explicitly in a classic article on the organization of metropolitan governance in the United States
(Ostrom et al. 1961). Urban public economies are micro-universes that display, on a small scale,
governance problems and processes that are ubiquitous at larger scales. This perspective con-
siders local government ocials as service providers responsible for making taxing and spending
decisions, determining appropriate types of service and levels of supply, and arranging for and
monitoring production. As providers, these public ocials face several options in arranging for
the actual production of public goods, including creating its own production unit, contracting
for services with an external producer or creating a joint venture with other provision units in
order to have the services produced.
To sum up, the implication is that the organization of provision and the organization of
production have dierent principles of operation and should be institutionalized in dierent ways.
A local government may, on the one hand, be organizing service nancing through collective
consumption units and, on the other hand, be purchasing services from alternative public or private
suppliers. Institutional diversity is thus the natural pattern in the public sector, while centralization
and uniformity may be more of an exception.
The political economy institutionalism approach has thus more than just a methodological
value. One of its important consequences is that it introduces the notion of optimum scale of
performance. A crucial question in public administration and public policy is addressed frontally:
is there some special characteristic of governmental functions that makes large units necessary
to eciency? In the light of the above, one cannot avoid the answer that eciency depends
on the nature and type of service that a governmental agency is meant to produce and not on
some special characteristics of governmental functions associated to the scale of the activity. The
question of the validity of the notion that eciency is a function of large-scale centralization is
thus confronted. The thesis advanced is that the optimum scale of production is not the same
for all public goods and services and that some services may be produced more eciently on a
large scale while other services may be produced more eciently on a small scale (E. Ostrom
[1972] in McGinnis 1999b; Oakerson 1999; V. Ostrom et al. 1988). Implications questioning
the basic postulates of centralized governance in the modern public system are even today
perceived by many as counterintuitive and paradoxical.
It is clear why political economy institutionalism suggests that the existence of multiple
agencies interacting and overlapping should not be considered a priori and by denition dys-
functional. This overlapping and duplication is the result of the fact that dierent services
require a dierent scale for ecient provision and that the principles of division of labor,
cooperation and exchange function in the public sector, too. In traditional bureaucratic theory,
duplication of functions is assumed to be wasteful and ine cient. But in a market economy
multiple rms serve the same market. Overlapping service areas and duplicate facilities do not
lead to ineciency. Can we expect similar forces to operate in a public economy? The Ostroms
answer is positive. The public sector includes not only bureaucratic command structures con-
trolled by chief executives but also interorganizational arrangements with self-regulating
tendencies with eciency-inducing and error-correcting behavior (Ostrom and Ostrom 1965: 3).
The discussion leads sooner or later to the very notion of competition. In what measure and
how does the public policy process incorporate the competition process? There is no pre-
sumption that competition among public agencies is necessarily ecient
or inecient in all
settings,
but only that such competiton need not take the same forms as market competition
(V. Ostrom et al. 1961; Bish 1971).
McGinnis and Aligica
88
The bottom line is that the presence of more than a single producer of public goods within a
certain area enables citizens to make more eective choices about the mix of services they prefer
to receive while enabling citizens to vote with their feet or by enabling individuals residing
within an existing community to choose among alternative producers of public services. Fur-
thermore, multiple producers of some public goods may nullify each others actions and lead to
a reduction in the net output of public goods. In other words, political economy institutional-
ism considers the practical eect of competition among public agencies as an empirical question
depending upon the type of urban public good being considered and the specic circumstances
of the case (E. Ostrom [1972] in McGinnis 1999b: 148)
Toonen (1998) argues that the 1961 Ostrom, Tiebout and Warren article synthesized all of
the following components of New Public Management and related visions of network gov-
ernance: entrepreneurial leadership, contracts for service delivery, deregulation, devolution of
authority to market actors, the important contributions made by professional associations and
community groups, and an emphasis on evaluating the performance of public ocials and the
quality of the products they produce or procure. Each of these topics has attracted substantial
interest in recent years, and, to be fair, the authors did not systematically lay out any of these
implications in detail. In eect, these same ideas were later rediscovered and elaborated upon by
other scholars, who were in eect following a path initially laid out by these founders of the
Bloomington School of Institutional Analysis.
To sum up, the Bloomington School not only oers a specic set of theoretical lenses and a
new perception of the public and policy arena but also questions the assumption deeply ingrained
in the traditional view that large bureaucracies are more ecient in solving problems and in
providing public goods and services than the systems based on competition or bargaining. In
doing that, this approach challenges our perspective on the very nature of the policy process.
Complexity, scale and scope, levels and diversity, overlapping institutions and functional dif-
ferentiation invite us to rethink the public governance system. Sooner or later we are forced to
reconsider the criteria we are using in policy evaluation in all its aspects: policy theory, policy
implementation, and policy impact.
2
Polycentricity and monocentrism
Political economy institutionalism is an eort to change the paradigm. A new domain of insti-
tutional complexity and diversity needed to be charted and that requires an entirely new fra-
mework. The concept of polycentricity lies at the heart of this new paradigm. As initially
dened, the term polycentric connotes many centers of decision-making which are formally
independent of each other.
To the extent that they take each other into account in competitive relationships, enter into
various contractual and cooperative undertakings or have recourse to central mechanisms to
resolve conicts, the various political jurisdictions in a metropolitan area may function in a
coherent manner with consistent and predictable patterns of interacting behavior.
(Ostrom et al. 1961: 831)
Subsequently, Ostrom further claried his vision of polycentricity as constituting a highly
federalized system that required all of the following component parts: a rich structure of over-
lapping jurisdictions with substantial autonomy among jurisdictions, substantial degrees of demo-
cratic control within jurisdictions, and subject to an enforceable system of constitutional law
(V. Ostrom 1973: 229).
Institutional analysis and political economy
89
The alternative, and still much more inuential paradigm, is to presume that eective gov-
ernance requires a single ultimate authority exercising control through a unied command and
control structure. Conversely, in a polycentric order, the elements of a complex system are
allowed to make mutual adjustments to each other within a general system of rules where each
element acts with independence of other elements (V. Ostrom 1972). The conceptual spaces
dened by the two notions are interlinked. The possibility that a polycentric political system
can exist does not preclude the possibility that a monocentric political system can exist (ibid.).
Above and beyond the theoretical problems and debates, is a practical issue. The key ques-
tion is whether there is any prima facie ground for expecting less ecient performance from
polycentric arrangements than from a centralized system. As we have seen, before the work of
the Ostroms and their associates started to have an impact, the duplication of services (one of
the main features of polycentric systems) was assumed to be wasteful and to generate disorder.
To compare these two paradigms, an extensive empirical research agenda focused on governance
in municipal areas was initiated (Oakerson 1999; McGinnis 1999b). That empirical work started
to identify and chart the patterns of order looming underneath the apparent chaos intrinsically
associated to the experience of polycentricity as well as specied conditions for ecient per-
formance (V. Ostrom 1972). Polycentricity raises fundamental challenges to social and political
theory that have broader ramications that go beyond the issue of the governance of metropolitan
areas. An analysis of the class of phenomena displaying a multiplicity of decision centers shows
that there are many forms of organization that might seem analogous to a polycentric order.
However, not all of them had the attributes associated to polycentricity. For instance, a break-
down of order and rules may lead to situations where multiple decision centers coexist. Political
corruption leads to situations where various forms of bosses divide territories and jurisdictions.
Could that be called polycentric order? Therefore, it is important to specify the conditions that
could create a system of government organized in a polycentric manner. In this respect, ve fea-
tures are pivotal: the legitimate exercise of coercive capabilities; an overarching system of rules;
freedom to enter and exit; freedom to orderly change the rules; and incentives alignment.
3
A mere review of polycentricity reveals that the problem of whether the government of a
political system can be organized in a polycentric manner has a considerable history. As V. Ostrom
(1971, 1997) argued, Alexis de Tocquevilles classic study Democracy in America is an exploration
in polycentric governance. The challenge faced by the founding fathers of the American con-
stitution was in fact to design a polycentric order. The Federalist did not use the term poly-
centricity. However, Alexander Hamilton and James Madisons conception of the principles of
federalism and separation of powers within a system of limited constitutions meets the dening
conditions for polycentricity (V. Ostrom 1972, 1973, 1971). The federal system, argues V. Ostrom,
assumes a fragmentation of authority in many centers of decision-making that implies a separa-
tion of powers. In other words, designing the American constitution could be viewed as an
experiment in polycentricity. Federalism itself could be seen as one way to capture the meaning
and operationalize one aspect of this type of order.
Last but not least, it is important to highlight the normative dimensions of polycentric forms
of organization. Polycentricity seems to be a necessary condition for political objectives such as
liberty and justice. The dispersion of decision-making capabilities and the checks and bal-
ances dening polycentricity allows for substantial discretion or freedom to individuals and for
eective and regular constraint upon the actions of governmental ocials. As such, is an essential
characteristic of democratic societies. Last but not least, a polycentric arrangement has a built-in
system of self-correction. While opportunistic behavior and malfeasance are a problem for any
institutional arrangements, a political system that has multiple centers of power at diering
scales provides more opportunity for citizens and their ocials to innovate and to intervene so
McGinnis and Aligica
90
as to correct maldistributions of authority and outcomes. Thus, polycentric systems are more likely
than monocentric systems to provide incentives leading to self-organized, self-corrective institutional
change (E. Ostrom 1998b). To conclude, one of the strong theses put forward by students of
polycentrism is that the very nature and existence of democratic societies depends on the presence
of sizable elements of polycentricity in their governance systems (Aligica and Boettke, 2009: 2223).
Coproduction: consumer producers
The perspective opened up by the political economy and polycentricity theoretical lenses has
led to a series of important empirical and theoretical insights regarding the problem of public
policies and governance in the public sector. To illustrate this point, let us use as an example the
concept of coproduction.
Empirical research of Bloomington scholars identied a series of cases in which the collaboration
between those who supplied a service and those who used it was the key factor in determining
the eective delivery of the service. For instance, the health of a community depends not only
on the professional quality of health care personnel but also on the informed eorts of individuals,
while the quality of an educational product is largely determined by the eorts of the users
of educational services, namely the eorts students make. Similarly, the quality and supply of
neighborhood security depends on the joint eorts of citizens as well of the professional police
ocers. These are cases in which the users of services also function as coproducers, in the sense that
the production process cannot be totally separated from consumption. Without the informed and
motivated eorts of service users, the service may deteriorate into an indierent product with
insignicant value. Under co-production, the resources, motivations, and skills brought to bear
by the client or consumer are much more intimately connected with the level of achieved output
than in the case of goods production. Coproduction means more than the existence of at least two
producers (Ostrom and Ostrom [1977] in McGinnis 1999b: 93; Aligica and Boettke, 2009: 3233).
This phenomenon is far from marginal. It appears to be characteristic of much public service
production (Parks 1993; Parks and Oakerson 1989). Appreciation of the role of coproduction
in public service delivery requires a change of focus in our approach to public administration and
public policy. Instead of focusing exclusively on bureaucratic structures or public organizations, it
highlights the critical importance of consumer input. Many public policy puzzles may be solved
if the productive roles of consumers as coproducers of the services they receive is taken into
account (Kiser and Percy 1980; E. Ostrom 1996; Ostrom and Ostrom 1977; Whitaker 1980).
Once clearly dened, coproduction problems could be identied in many areas of the service
in public sectors. A typical example is the so-called service paradox.
When professional personnel presume to know what is good for people rather than providing
people with opportunities to express their own preferences, we should not be surprised to
nd that increasing professionalization of public services is accompanied by a serious erosion
in the quality of those services.
(Aligica and Boettke 2009: 33)
The better services are, as dened by professional criteria, and as supplied exclusively by highly
trained professionals, the less satised citizens are with those services. Satisfaction and eec-
tiveness is in the end a function of citizens functioning as essential co-producers (Ostrom and
Ostrom [1977] in McGinnis 1999b: 934).
While usually the attention in public services management and evaluation is primarily on the
production side, the strategies of consumption are as important as the strategies of production.
Institutional analysis and political economy
91
Coproduction requires that both production and consumption go hand in hand to yield
optimal results. One should try to take into account both the economies of consumption as
well as of production and provides for the co-ordination of the two (Ostrom and Ostrom
[1977] in McGinnis 1999b: 94).
Political economy institutionalism from the Bloomington School demonstrates that despite
the absence of the level of exibility found in fully competitive markets, the search for solutions
in the public arena is not blind. A notion like coproduction could be used as a diagnostic
tool and with it an entire battery of concepts and theories could be developed for institu-
tional design, policy analysis and assessment. The particular nature of each good and service
plus the technological and economic conditions of its production and consumption require a
complex institutional system in which public and private, markets and hierarchies combine to
generate an institutional architecture with diverse patterns of organization and diversely orga-
nized systems of governance. To cope with this challenge new methodological tools needed to
be developed.
The IAD framework
The Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD) Framework encapsulates the collective eorts
of the Bloomington School to understand the ways in which institutions operate and change
over time. The IAD framework assigns all relevant explanatory factors and variables to categories
and locates these categories within a foundational structure of logical relationships.
4
The IAD framework serves as a tool to simplify the analytical task confronting anyone trying
to understand policies and institutions in their full complexity. At the heart of the IAD frame-
work is the action situation, in which individuals (acting on their own or as agents of formal
organizations) observe information, select actions, engage in patterns of interaction, and evaluate
outcomes. As is typical in strategic interactions, potential outcomes are dierentially valued by
those actors with partial control over the determination of actual results. The IAD framework
highlights the social-cultural, institutional, and biophysical context within which strategic deci-
sions are made. Specically, the IAD framework helps to organize the task confronting a scholar
or policy analyst approaching a policy issue by directing their attention to rst, the rules-in-use,
rather than the rules on paper, second, the underlying biophysical nature of the good under con-
sideration, in terms of it being a private, public, or toll/club good or a common-pool resource
(CPR), as well as third, the most relevant attributes of the community, especially ambient levels
of trust and shared norms of reciprocity.
Systems typically look very dierent depending on the level of aggregation being used, and
the IAD framework explicitly distinguishes three levels of analysis in which dierent types of
choice processes take place: rst, operational level choices (regarding policy implementation);
second, collective level choices involving the determination of which strategies, norms and rules
are or should be available to actors fullling the specic roles dened by that group (as well as
specifying who is assigned to ll these roles); and third, constitutional level choices relating to
who is or should be empowered to participate in the making of collective and operational-level
decisions. The critical insight behind this framework is that the outcomes of interactions in
these dierent arenas of choice are explicitly connected to each other.
The actors in any action situation are presumed to be boundedly rational. They seek to
achieve goals for themselves and for the communities with which they identify but do so within
the context of ubiquitous social dilemmas and biophysical constraints, as well as cognitive limitations
and cultural predispositions. Within this broad framework, a range of theoretical perspectives
may be employed to develop and analyze models of specic situations.
McGinnis and Aligica
92
Rational choice theory, grounded in methodological individualism, provides the general
inspiration for the IAD framework, but dierent decision models are relevant for dierent
situations. For example, the same individual might follow Simons (1955) satiscing procedure
in one decision context while engaging in more extensive information search and evaluation in
other situations. There is no reason to presume that any one individual acts in exactly the same
way in all circumstances; still, there is merit in trying to locate the relevant range of decisional
procedures within the context of a common explanation.
In the IAD framework analysts must incorporate, in some manner, the actors self-understanding
of their roles and their conceptions of proper or acceptable behavior in particular contexts. By
incorporating factors not typically considered by rational choice theorists, the IAD framework
can encompass approaches to analysis that many of them would no longer recognize as rational
choice. Indeed, Ostrom (1998a) has called for a second-generation of rational choice theory
more rmly grounded in behavioral regularities, many of which have been discovered by critics
of the rational choice tradition.
The IAD framework is implicitly grounded in a dynamic view of policy processes. Social,
institutional, and biophysical factors are inputs to processes of individual decisions (with those
decisions presumed to be inuenced by their preexisting cognitive capabilities and cultural
presuppositions), and these decisions are then aggregated to constitute policy outputs that would
then interact with exogenous factors to produce observable outcomes, with actors evaluations
of these outcomes by these actors (or by other observers) feeding back into all of the previous
components of this never-ending process.
Institutional arrangements shape and constrain the behavior of individuals, but there is no
need to presume that individuals will always follow the rules. In the IAD framework consider-
able importance is attached to the means by which actors (at all levels) monitor each others
activities and sanction undesirable or inappropriate behavior. In empirical research it often turns
out that those systems which involve local participants in monitoring and sanctioning are more
likely to be sustainable than those in which those functions are instead fullled by agents of the
national government (E. Ostrom 1990).
The IAD framework bears a family relationship to game models (E. Ostrom 1986), but it is
essential to keep in mind the extent to which actors preferences as well as the choice options
available to them are determined by the institutional arrangements that dene their position or that
shape their perceptions and options. Concurrent games in other arenas of choice interact in subtle
ways with any ongoing process of interaction (McGinnis 2011b). The payos and menu of
choices available to participants in operational games have been dened by collective choice
processes. Games over collective deliberations are in turn shaped by the positions and interests
dened or manifested in the constitutional choice arena. In a strict sense, this may be no dierent
from a complete specication of a game model, but in practice this concern with simultaneous
consideration of multiple choice arenas inspires Workshop-aliated scholars toward a more
inductive mode of analysis (Mitchell 1988). Yet all this research remains inspired by a common
vision of the critical importance of polycentricity in the policy world, and how critical it is for
analysts to realize the complexities inherent in the systems they are studying.
Conclusions: public policy analysis
Irrespective of school of thought, knowledge base, or analytical sophistication, most forms of policy
analysis are by their very nature dealing with a single fundamental problem: collective action.
5
Slowly,
an interdisciplin ary theory uniting all the many factors that inuence collective action is emerging, and
members of the Bloomington School are playing critical roles in its emergence (E. Ostrom 2010a).
Institutional analysis and political economy
93
Adening feature of the political economy institutionalism advanced by the Ostroms and
their associates is that this general theory of collective action requires realization through very
specic and problem-oriented analyses. It refers to concrete, public aairs problems confronting
specic communities or groups. Its objectives are not abstract and theoretical but applied and
aimed at problem solving (V. Ostrom 1991: 21). Policy analysis is variable with problematical
situations and any diagnostic assessment must necessarily be conjectural. Without knowledge
well grounded in the problematic circumstances of a collective action policy analyses are likely to be
misspecied. That may seem commonsensical. However a common source of policy failure lies
in eorts to formulate and implement general solutions in total ignorance of the local conditions.
A diagnostic assessment is complexly linked to the institutional facts, that is to say knowledge
of the institutional environment is crucial (V. Ostrom 1991: 256).
6
We have examined a few ways in which the Bloomington School has analyzed links between
institutional diversity and the complexity of polycentric systems of governance. Conversely,
policy analysts committed to the monocentric alternative often reveal a surprising lack of
interest in real-world institutions. In other words, the way policy analysis was thought about for
most of the twentiethth century resulted in misguided eort to implement universal solutions,
typically centered in national level public ocials (V. Ostrom 1991: 2).
7
This logic and its implications are not accidental but a basic paradigmatic problem. As such, it is
prone to persist as long as policy analysts continue to conceptualize social order using just two
ideal typesmarkets and hierarchiesand believe that all societies could be described by reference
to them, thus ignoring the diverse nestings of institutional arrangements in time and place
specicities. But once the theoretical lenses of polycentricity are used, policy analysis is forced
to give more attention to institutional analysis driven by analytical methods and to problem-solving
using variable policy formulations based upon dierent presuppositions (V. Ostrom 1997: 104).
In his writing on public policy Vincent Ostrom tried to rescue the study of public policy
from the trap of intellectual triviality. Policy is not a purely technical exercise of adjusting means
to given ends xed in function of obvious problems. By their very nature, social scientists are
deeply involved in clarifying the meaning and place of values and norms in the development of
human institutions. An understanding of values, or a normative inquiry, is a prerequisite to
performing the tasks of policy design and evaluation. Moreover, if one wants to design or assess
decision rules, one needs criteria. Then the question is: what kind of criteria for those rules?
How we construct (or for that matter assess) those rules depends on the criteria used. The task
of the policy analyst is not only to use values as entry points or vehicles for analysis but to apply
them. These values are not given. In a word, the very notion of a policy problem is infused
by deeper philosophical or normative speculations related to human nature and the human
condition. The full dimensions and the complexity of the problems are fully revealed when nor-
mative concepts collide with natural conditions of human beings (V. Ostrom 1991: 25). The
world of policy analysis is in the end the world of implementationnamely the world of action
and decision, and therefore is the world of normative commitments.
Notes
1 As might be expected for scholars whose work extends over several decades, the terms the Ostroms
used to dene their approach to the study of political institutions has undergone several changes, and
these changes can generate some confusion. For example, in Ostrom and Ostrom (1971) they use the
term public choice to refer to their proposed new mode of analysis, but later developments in public
choice gave a much dierent meaning to that term. At the time, they were key participants in what
Vincent Ostrom famously labeled the no-name conference at Charlottesville, Virginia, organized by
James Buchanan in 1964 (V. Ostrom 1965). They have also used public economy as a generalization
McGinnis and Aligica
94
of market economy, intended to incorporate all relevant public, private, voluntary, and community-
based organizations active in a given area of public policy, and public service industry or public
enterprise to generalize the concept of a market sector to include non-explicitly commercial organi-
zations. The term behavioral approach (Ostrom and Ostrom 1965; E. Ostrom 1998a,b) has also been
used in dierent contexts. Ultimately, however, they settled on the phrase institutional analysis as the
most accurate label for their approach, but its lack of specicity makes that also a potentially confusing
term. For this reason, and others, we will use the term Bloomington School as a shorthand label for
the approach to research pioneered by Vincent and Elinor Ostrom.
2 That is to say it was doing more than merely developing a simple market model, derived from neoclassical
economic theory, and applying it to a non-market setting in the public choice tradition. Its goals are much
bolder: We thought an indication that quasi-market mechanisms were operable in a public service economy
would imply important new dimensions for a theory of public administration (V. Ostrom 1972). In other
words, they were restructuring scholars basic conceptualization of the public sector (Ostrom et al. 1961).
3 In a monocentric political system the prerogatives for determining and enforcing the rules are vested in a
single decision structure that has an ultimate monopoly over the legitimate exercise of coercive cap-
abilities. In a polycentric system many ocials and decision structures are assigned limited and relatively
autonomous prerogatives to determine, enforce and alter legal relationships (V. Ostrom [1972] in McGinnis
1999b: 5560). In a polycentric system no one has an ultimate monopoly over the legitimate use of
force. The rulers are constrained and limited under a rule of law. Ultimately, polycentric systems
are rule of law systems. Incentives alignment in the enforcement of general rules of conduct provides
the legal framework for a polycentric order: If individuals or units operating in a polycentric order
have incentives to take actions to enforce general rules of conduct, then polycentricity will become an
increasingly viable form of organization (V. Ostrom 1972). Another condition is freedom of entry and
exit in a particular system. The establishment of new decision centers under the existing rules should
not be blocked. The freedom of entry ensures the evolution and adaptation of the system. Finally,
another key condition is that spontaneity should be manifested in the reformulation and revision of the
basic rules that dene the framework of a specic polycentric order. The idea is that individuals should
be free not only to play the game or have the incentives to self-enforce the rules of the game but also
to change those rules in an orderly way. Understanding and learning from experience are in fact the
vectors of an ongoing process of knowledge integration in the institutional system and the prerequisites
of subsequent adaptations to the changing environment. (V. Ostrom [1972] in McGinnis 1999b).
4 The specic form of this framework has varied considerably over time; important stages in its devel-
opment can be seen at Kiser and Ostrom (1982), E. Ostrom (1990), Ostrom et al. (1994), McGinnis
(2000), E. Ostrom (1998a, 2005, 2007b, 2010b) and Poteete et al. (2010). The IAD framework is also
related to earlier work on public service industries and local public economies (Ostrom et al. 1961;
Ostrom and Ostrom 1977; E. Ostrom 1983; Ostrom et al. 1993; McGinnis 1999b; Oakerson 1999) as
well as more recent work on social-ecological systems (E. Ostrom 2007a, 2009). For a recent overview
of all of these related frameworks, see McGinnis (2011a).
5 Policy
analysis, writes Vincent Ostrom,
is based on the presumption that appropriate forms of collec-
tive choice and collective action will contribute to a more eective resolution of common problems
and an advancement in the aggregate well-being experienced by members of collectivities (V. Ostrom
in McGinnis 1999a: 394).
6 Due to the very specic and contextual nature of knowledge required for the assessment of a case, in
nite time and place exigencies, the need to get the local knowledge, and perceptions and ideas of
the actors involved is even more stringent. One has to derive criteria for choosing one alternative over
the other and to assess their consequences. In other words, the applied dimension presses the problem
of norms not only at an analytical level but also at the decision-making one.
7 Much of contemporary policy analysis appears to be largely institution-free except for abstract allusions
to the government, or the state (meaning nation-states).
Policy formulations presume a clean slate as though the failure to proclaim a General National
Policy implied the absence of an Energy Policy, an Urban Policy, a Housing Policy, an Edu-
cational Policy, or any other speciable policy. It is as though all political systems were uni-
centric, hierarchical in order, and run from the top down. The same modes of analysis and
policy prescriptions can presumably be used anywhere in the world.
(Ostrom, V. The Meaning of American Federalism: Constituting a Self-governing
Society. ICS Press, 1991: 2)
Institutional analysis and political economy
95
Bibliography
Aligica, P. and P. Boettke. 2009. Rethinking Institutional Analysis and Development: The Bloomington School.
London: Routledge.
Bish, R. 1971. The Public Economy of Metropolitan Areas. Chicago: Markham Press.
Kiser, L.L. and S. Percy. 1980. The concept of coproduction and its prospects for public service delivery,
Working Paper No. W80-6, Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis, Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University.
McGinnis, M.D. 1999a. Polycentric Governance and Development: Readings from the Workshop in Political Theory
and Policy Analysis. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
—— 1999b. Polycentricity and Local Public Economies: Readings from the Workshop in Political Theory and Policy
Analysis. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
—— 2000. Polycentric Games and Institutions: Readings from the Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis.
Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
—— (2011a). An Introduction to IAD and the Language of the Ostrom Workshop: A Simple Guide to a
Complex Framework, Policy Studies Journal 39 (1) (March 2011), 16377.
—— 2011b. Networks of adjacent action situations in polycentric governance, Policy Studies Journal 39(1):
4572.
Kiser, L. and E. Ostrom. The three worlds of action, in Strategies of Political Inquiry, ed. E. Ostrom,
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 179222.
Mitchell, W.C. 1988. Virginia, Rochester, and Bloomington: Twenty-ve years of public choice and
political science, Public Choice 56(2): 10119.
Oakerson, R.J. 1999. Governing Local Public Economies: Creating the Civic Metropolis. San Francisco: ICS Press.
——and R.B. Parks. 1988. Citizen voice and public entrepreneurship: The organizational dynamic of a
complex metropolitan county, Publius: The Journal of Federalism 18(4): 91112.
Ostrom, E. 1972. Metropolitan reform: Propositions derived from two traditions, Social Science Quarterly
53: 47493.
—— 1983. A public choice approach to metropolitan institutions: Structure, incentives, and performance,
Social Science Journal 20(3): 7996.
—— 1986. An
agenda for the
study of institutions, Public Choice 48: 325
—— 1990. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
—— 1996, Crossing the great divide: Coproduction, synergy, and development, World Development 24
(6): 107387.
—— 1998a. A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action, American Political
Science Review 92(1): 122.
—— 1998b. The comparative study of public economies, presented upon acceptance of the Frank
E. Seidman Distinguished Award in Political Economy, Memphis, TN, P.K. Seidman Foundation.
—— 2005. Understanding Institutional Diversity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Pres
—— 2007a. A diagnostic approach for going beyond panaceas, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
104(39): 151817.
—— 2007b. Institutional rational choice: an assessment of the institutional analysis and development
framework in P.A. Sabatier (ed.) Theories of the Policy Process, 2nd edn. Boulder, CO: Westview Press,
2164.
—— 2009. A general framework for analyzing sustainability of social-ecological systems, Science, vol. 325,
no. 5939: 41922.
—— 2010a. Analyzing collective action, Agricultural Economics 41(S1): 15566.
—— 2010b. Beyond markets and states: polycentric governance of Complex economic systems, American
Economic Review 100(3):
64172.
—— 2011. Background on the
institutional analysis and development framework, Policy Studies Journal 39
(1): 727.
——, Larry Schroeder and Susan Wynne. 1993. Institutional Incentives and Sustainable Development: Infrastructure
Policies in Perspective. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——, R. Gardner and J. Walker. 1994. Rules, Games, and Common-Pool Resources. Ann Arbor, MI: University
of Michigan Press.
Ostrom, V. 1964. Editorial comment: Developments in the no-name elds of public administration,
Public Administration Review 24(1): 623.
McGinnis and Aligica
96
—— 1971. The Political Theory of a Compound Republic: Designing the American Experiment, 2nd edn. Lincoln,
NE: University of Nebraska Press.
—— 1972. Polycentricity, Workshop Archives, Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University. Presented at Annual Meeting of the American Political Science
Association, September 59, Washington, DC. Reprinted in McGinnis 1999b. Polycentry and Public
Economies, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
—— 1973. The Intellectual Crisis in American Public Administration, 2nd edn. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of
Alabama Press.
—— 1991. Some ontological and epistemological puzzles in policy analysis, Working Paper No. W82-16,
Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
—— 1997. The Meaning of Democracy and the Vulnerability of Democracies: A Response to Tocquevilles Challenge.
Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
——, C.M. Tiebout and R. Warren. 1961. The organization of government in metropolitan areas: A
theoretical inquiry, American Political Science Review 55: 831 42.
—— 1990. American constitutionalism and self-governance, in M. Rozbicki (ed.) European and American
Constitutionalism in the Eighteenth Century. Vienna: US Regional Program Oce.
——, R. Bish and E. Ostrom. 1988. Local Government in the United States. San Francisco: ICS Press.
Ostrom, V. and E. Ostrom. 1965. A behavioral approach to the study of intergovernmental relations, The
Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 359: 13746.
—— 1971. Public choice: A dierent approach to the study of public administration, Public Administration
Review (31): 20316.
—— 1977. Public goods and public choices, in McGinnis 1999b. Polycentry and Public Economies, Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Parks, R.B. 1993. Comparative metropolitan organization: Service production and governance structures
in St. Louis (MO) and Allegheny County (PA), Publius 23(1): 1939.
——and
R.J. Oakerson. 1989. Metropolitan
organization and governance: A local public economy
approach, Urban Aairs Quarterly 25(1): 18 29.
Poteete, Amy, Marco Janssen and Elinor Ostrom. 2010. Working Together: Collective Action, the Commons,
and Multiple Methods in Practice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Simon, H.A. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice, Quarterly Journal of Economics 69(1): 99118.
Tiebout, C.M. 1956. A pure theory of local expenditures, Journal of Political Economy 64: 41635.
Toonen, Theo A.J. 1998. Networks, management and institutions: Public administration as normal science”’,
Public Administration 76: 22952.
Whitaker, G. 1980. Coproduction: Citizen participation in service delivery, Public Administration Review
40(3): 2406.
Institutional analysis and political economy
97
8
Postpositivism and the
policy process
Raul Perez Lejano
Our understanding of what policy-making is, and what policy analysts do, evolved beyond a
clear conception of policy-making as a linear, rational exercise to a more unsettled but prag-
matic view of it as a complex, plurivocal, indeterminate, and often controversial act. This marked
transition has been referred to as the argumentative (or discursive, linguistic, communicative)
turn in policy (Fischer and Forester 1993). As will be discussed, this opening up to a broader
landscape has both enlivened and fractured the policy discipline (to the extent that the word dis-
cipline is itself problematic). It has moved scholars and practitioners of policy to wonder, what
is our science? or perhaps, more appropriately, what is our folly?
Turning points in the practice of policy
The notion of policy-making and analysis as a rational process is traced to the rise of systems and
decision analysis, beginning with the Second World War. This era saw the use of mathematics
and the increasingly powerful growth in computer processing toward the systematic allocation
of resources, rst for military purposes but soon thereafter to large-scale social projects. The rst
policy think tanks, of which the RAND Corporation is perhaps emblematic, arose as seats of a
grand planning endeavor, in which numerical optimization could be translated into optimal
outcomes in the battleeld, in the emerging mega-cities and suburbs, in schools, hospitals, and
other sites of social activity. This heritage draws, rst and foremost, from the pioneering work of
von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) in conceptualizing a theory of games and decisions.
This powerful analytical lens begins and ends with the notion of individual rationality as self-
utility maximization, and of society as a collection of rational individuals. Translation of this
system of rational thought to actual application would not be long, e.g. Schellings treatment of
war and conict as multi-player games among rational actors (1980) or to Buchanan and Tul-
locks use of the same model to analyze political instituitons (1962). A central gure in the
translation of the rational model to the public realm of allocation of goods and services is Karl
Mannheim (1940), who provided an early vision of democratic social planning. In this modernist
vision, exemplied by Le Corbusiers utopian cities, society can be designed.
Where, then, did the turn away from the rational model occur? In part, we can trace some of
it to a turn to reection occasioned by a seeping disillusionment in these grand experiments in
98
rational policy-making. Several key examples will suce. But rst, we ask the reader to excuse
an inescapable US-centricity to this account. Much of the self-reection one nds in the
literature occurs in US academia and media. At the same time, we occasionally bring in
examples from other regions to guard against monocentricity and, at times, as a counterpoint to
some of these observations.
Disillusionment with the states grand social experiments began early. From the experience of
Lyndon Johnsons war on poverty, ending with ever-increasing disparities between rich and poor,
to the military rational planning of the Cold War, ending in national defeat to the North Vietna-
mese, United States ventures have failed in grand manner. In city planning, the rational design of
large-scale Corbusian housing complexes ends with the demolition of the grandiose Pruitt-Igoe
tenements in Chicago.
But this was not just the American experience. Indeed, one cannot look back on the great
leaps in agricultural productivity of post-feudal China without recalling, at the same time, the
social ills of the Cultural Revolution. Across the world, grand state-led social engineering, led
by institutions like the World Bank, resulted in large state agencies in developing nations that
failed to deliver goods and services eectively and failed to eliminate entrenched poverty
(Rapley 1996).
In fact, much of this was foretold many decades earlier, in Webers description of the
sweeping rationalization of society (Weber 1904). In this account, rationalization involved the
increasingly narrow reduction of social processes and institutions into means-end technocracies in
which easily calculable or accountable outputs would be optimized in rationally designed insti-
tutions. In this type of Zweckrationalität, bureaus would maximize bureaucratic imperatives to
the exclusion of deeper, perhaps more elusive social goals, e.g. energy departments would
maximize energy output to the exclusion of environmental quality; transportation agencies would
maximize road capacity to the detriment of walkable neighborhoods, etc. In his incisive critique
of the Tennessee Valley Authority, Selznick described how the state agency itself became cap-
tured by the very entities it regulated (the power companies) because their interests coincided
(1949). Skepticism over institutions grew ever deeper during the Watergate era, to be repeated
from administration to administration, from the Iran-Contra aair to Iraq. A good summary
account of the failures of the rational, modernist state is found in Scotts description of high
modernism (Scott, J. 1998).
In contrast to the rationalist goal of clearly dened objectives and alternatives, Rittel and
Webber describe pressing social issues as wicked problemsnamely those for which no right or
wrong exists, with ends for which there is no consensus in society, with alternatives and con-
sequences that cannot be determined by technical analysis, and no good way to even ascertain if
the problem has been solved or not (Rittel and Webber 1973). In such a milieu, the max-
imizing impulse gives way to the question, what is it exactly that we want to optimize? and the
consequentialist framework gives way to the question, how do we act when we just dont
know what will result?
Wicked problems are all around us. As this chapter is being written, society in the US in 2012 is
caught in an ideological divide. As scal conservatives forced the country into a near default in
pursuit of an ideological commitment to small government, low taxes, and defeating an
incumbent President, it became apparent how intractable the gulf was. The question quickly
became that of choosing between maximizing individual wealth or social equity, and society
itself was divided over the choice just as the liberals and conservatives in congress were. As to
predicting consequences of one action versus another, one side clearly believed that budget-cutting
would create growth, while the other believed that stimulus and near-term spending would
pump-prime the economy. What is right when one sides notion of rationality is a polar
Postpositivism and the policy process
99
opposite of the other? At this time, there is evolving yet another turn in policy thought being
precipitated by the Depression of 2008, and it is unclear how the policy disciplines will change
from this time forwardthat book is still being written.
Turning points in policy thought
At the same time as the grand experiment at social intervention was beginning to waver, a
revolution in the theoretical underpinnings of policy was evolving.
Part of the intellectual movement owes its trajectory to the linguistic turn in the social sci-
ences and humanities. The reference to language owes to the advancement in the eld of lin-
guistics, beginning with Saussures structural theory of meaning (1916). Saussure posited that the
meaning of words is not inherent in the words themselves but something that arises in the place
of the word in the constellation of other words forming the language system. Thus, the word
poor means what it means only in juxtaposition to words like destitute,”“rich,”“wealthy,
penniless, and all the other words that, by virtue of its position relative to each other, deter-
mine their respective meanings. Meaning is purely positional, which is why Saussures is said to
be a structural theory of meaning. Post-structuralism comes on the heels of Saussures theory by
positing further that not only is meaning relative and positional, it is not even xed this way.
Meaning is never determined and, instead, is always subject to the free play or polysemy of
language (Derrida 1978).
Parallel developments include Wittgensteins philosophical treatise on logic, in which, con-
trary to logicians who maintain that fundamental truths can be arrived at by beginning with
foundational facts and building logically outward, all truth claims are contingent. There is no
logical truth, only language games wherein truth is established only within a particular language
system, but never established categorically (Wittgenstein [1922]61). Truth is socially constructed,
subject to conventions established in social discourse, but always contextual, never categorical.
In the sociology of knowledge, much of the unraveling of the notion of absolute knowledge is
traced to Lyotard, who began by contrasting technical-scientic knowledge with narrative or folk
knowledge, then argued that both were language games, no one more privileged than the other
to any claim to truth (Lyotard 1979). Lyotards declamation against universality of knowledge
(what he called grand narratives) is thought to be the rst emphatic statement of a new, post-
modern age where there are no denitive truth claims, social norms, or teleological principles,
but only individual and particular voices in a discursive babble (or paralogy, in Lyotards words).
This turning away from modernity, with its pursuit of universal truths and its espousal of the
enlightenment of rationality and scientic inquiry, and a turning toward a never-ending ques-
tioning of purpose and meaning, had a profound eect on policy thought (and, as will be argued, a
later and less dramatic eect on practice). Berger and Luckmann wrote about institutions as
social constructs, subject to artice and ever-changing convention (1966). This easily lends to a
questioning of the institutional foundations of policythe meaning of the state, the legislature,
or the legal process. Others questioned even the primacy of science as a truthestablishing
endeavor, showing that the scientic process itself is very much a cultural practice as other cultural
practices such as taboo or courtship (Latour 1987; and see Douglas 1966 for an earlier statement
of modernity and culture).
The eect of these intellectual revolutions on thinking about policy, and the institutions in
which policy happens, has been deeply felt. Consider the linguistic turn and its turning away from
logocentricity, which is the notion that words point to objective truths which language accu-
rately represents. And consider the turn toward the idea that words themselves are not xed in
meaning but subject to play and debate. This extends immediately to the most physical object of
Lejano
100
policy, which are statements of policy, policy documents, and law. In this poststructural age,
even a statement like We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that
they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life,
Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness itself ceases to be self-evident. The words are enshrined
for all of history, but their meaning changes. Equality and liberty mean dierent things today than
when rst written in Jeersons time. And what they mean today is itself subject to debate. Does
equality mean extending the same bundle of rights and privileges to undocumented immigrants?
If not, then these persons are consituted as less than citizens, which is what the Declaration of
Independence meant by persons (which, in Jeersons time, referred to white, male landowners).
The telos of policy is also uncertain. What is the maximand of rational policy-making if we
cannot even come to agreement over what liberty, rights, and public good mean? There is no
transcending ethic that all can come to agreement over. In the context of the ideological debates in
the US Congress, some have tried to appeal to an overweening ethical principle Nation before
Party! but even this is questioned, as the nations good has been conated on all sides with the
partys. As Sarah Palin said:
Politics isnt just a game of competing interests and clashing parties. The people of America
expect us to seek public oce and to serve for the right reasons. And the right reason is to
challenge the status quo and to serve the common good.
(http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=94118910 (downloaded
December 10, 2011))
Everyone, even the political maverick, lays claim to the public good.
The deconstruction of institutions has also had a profound eect, beginning with the decentering
of the state (which parallels the decentering of the author as the font of meaning of the logos)
away from the presumption that the state represents the people and acts for the greatest good of
the greatest number (Mill 1863). Devolution away from the state has been most marked in the
government to governance literature in which focus turns to networks of policy actors acting
in often innovative ways (Koppenjan and Klijn 2004; Edelenbos et al. 2010; Schout et al. 2010).
It is perhaps no accident that a central gure in linguistics, Noam Chomsky, would emerge as one
of the foremost critics of the new order, characterizing the state as a conglomerate of military,
industrial, government, and big business interests (Chomsky and Herman 1988). But perhaps the
most trenchant critique would come from the French sociologist, Michel Foucault, who posited
all modern institutions to be modeled after the same basic mold of the penal institution, designed to
disipline the public and channel all human activity toward the furthering of the interests of the
powerful (1977). And as the policy-making institutions go, so does the very integrity of the policy
that emerges from them. Thus, in a skeptical age, anactionsuchastheTARP(TroubledAssetRelief
Program), the US Federal Reserves lending instrument that kept large nancial institutions from
bankruptcy in 2008, could be so casually described by political commentators in terms such as:
The bailout money is just going to line the pockets of the wealthy, instead of helping to
stabilize the economy or even the companies receiving the bailouts: Bailout money is being
used to subsidize companies run by horrible business men, allowing the bankers to receive
fat bonuses, to redecorate their oces, and to buy gold toilets and prostitutes.
(www.worldcrisisnewswatch.com/2011/05/tarp-bailout-scam-explained-government.html)
Thus, the postpositivist turn has come to mean not just a turning away from the notion that
the public good was measurable and subject to systematic analysis and optimization. In fact it
Postpositivism and the policy process
101
questioned the foundational meaning of policy itself, not only uncertainty over the correlation
between policy actions and the publics welfare, but that the very intent of policy could not be
presumed to be aligned with such collective good.
Policymaking in an interpretive world
To sum up the state of aairs thus far, if:
policy goals cannot be set denitively, in a manner achieving broad consensus over them;
policy situations cannot be described or analyzed in a positivist manner (i.e. their truth
determined by some denitive measures);
policy instruments and policy texts cannot be unambiguously determined with regard to
their meaning;
policy-making and implementing institutions cannot be assumed to have the capacity to
realize policy targets, nor assumed to be aligned with them in purpose
then what policy should be and how policy should be enacted cannot be determined in objective
manner and, instead, a matter of interpretation. This is not a trivial proposition, inasmuch as the
essence of community and political life, as Aristotle said in the Politics, is their establishment
with a view to some good. If we cannot agree on what good means for the community,
then how do we set policy and go about attaining its ends?
In an interpretive world, where meaning and good ends are subject to deliberation and debate,
policy-making is less about measuring and projecting the optimal trajectory for policy but the
crafting of a compelling and consensus-building story that captures the publics moral imagina-
tion and moves people and groups to action. In this account, we refer to a number of key
works in the postpositivist policy literatureat this point, a handful of useful summary treat-
ments can be found in Stone, Roe, Fischer and Forester, Fischer, Hajer, Kaplan, Schneider and
Ingram, Yanow, Schon and Rein, and Dryzek.
Making sense of the world, and policy situations encountered in it, requires seeking satisfac-
tory interpretations of these situations. For Ricoeur, people make sense of the world by crafting
coherent narratives about it (1981; also Bruner 1991). In Ricoeurs words, By means of the
[narratives] plot, goals, causes, and chance are brought together within the temporal unity of a
whole and complete action (1984: ix). So it is, then, that by reconstructing a persons underlying
narrative account, we can best reproduce their experience of a situation. To do this, Ricoeur
espouses a hermeneutic approach to narrative interpretation (1976, 1981).
Goman said something similar when he evoked the idea of frames, which were interpretive
constructs used to create coherent meaning in an otherwise complex and incomprehensible
situation (1974). Frames, as Goman introduced them, are interpretive schemes that selectively
highlight aspects of the issue and introduce a specic perspective that then allows one to capture
reality in a simpler manner (1974; also Schön and Rein 1994). But seldom found in this research is
the explicit recognition that, very often or perhaps generally, these mental models, cultural models,
and frames take on the appearance and essence of story. Bruner is one of the few to make this
explicit connection (1987). As others have expressed it: Given the amount of uncertainty about
the world, people create cause-and-eect stories to ll in the blanks. Framesalso known as
mental models, schemasare essentially such stories (Wesselink and Warner 2010). Stone talks
about how causal stories are used to craft and process policy ideas through the process (1997)
though, we might add, the causal story is just one of the genres one nds in the policy eld (i.e.
others include moral fables, epic myths, tales of chivalry, surrealist ction, etc.). And so, for
Lejano
102
example, along with the proposal for TARP was the narrative of how nancial institutions like
Goldman Sachs were too big to fail. In this interpretive model, it is on the strength of the
policy story that policies win or lose.
As a result, over several decades now, scholars have called for the systematic use of narrative
analysis in public administration and policy research (Roe 1989, 1994; Yanow 1992, 2007; Balfour
and Mesaros 1994; Sköldberg 1994; Schram and Neisser 1997; Hajer and Wagenaar 2003;
Ospina and Dodge 2005; Hampton 2009; Lejano and Leong 2012). This is joined by an already
considerable literature on narrative approaches to studying organizational process and design (e.g.
see Martin 1982; Boje 1991; Weick 1995; Boyce 1995; Czarniawska 1998; Patriotta 2003).
The move towards narrative approaches began with the interpretive turn in the social sciences
(Berger and Luckmann 1966; Rabinow and Sullivan 1979, 1987). In the 1970s and 1980s, scholars
like Fischer and Forester (1993) argued for an interpretive approach to public policy studies.
The then prevalent positivist-instrumentalist bent of the social sciences had failed in carrying out
its promise of giving a good account of what goes on in government and society at large (Dryzek
1982). The deductive approach of technical knowledge, with its search for objective measures
and universal principles, failed to account for the fact that social phenomena mean dierent things
to dierent people, and that such social constructions are highly contextual (ibid.: 310; also
Fischer and Forester 1993). The primacy of technical knowledge was questioned and, increasingly,
narrative knowledge began to be seen as equally valid (Lyotard 1979; Jameson 1984).
Among the rst to use narrative analysis to study public controversies was Emery Roe (1989,
1994). His point was that narratives are one of the richest vehicles for the multiple and complex
meanings that dierent stakeholders bring to a public issue. Martha Nussbaum says something
similar when she describes how complex normative positions are best expressed in narrative
form (1990). Deborah Stone speaks to the power of causal stories which public managers and
politicians craft, to construct reality in a way that best captures their interests and policy goals (1997).
Given this irreducible element of social construction, she argues, understanding deliberation in
the public realm requires an interpretive approach (Stone 1997). In our work, we look for
stories that are told by dierent publics, including citizens groups and media.
In this discussion, we understand a narrative to simply mean a story, composed of a coherent
sequence of events, involving a set of characters, which are actors with denite traits (e.g. see
Ryan 2007; Bal 2009). When we reconstruct a narrative underlying an issue, we are simply com-
posing a story, with events and characters, as if a narrator were recounting it to us directly. It is
possible that no one source (whether a respondent or a text) ever gives us a complete narrative
in toto, or that it gives us only one particular account of a larger narrative, and it is the analysts
role to construct a story that reects the dierent aspects of the issue in a coherent way. The
resulting, reconstructed narrative is akin to the fabula (or storyline) of a literary piecenamely it
presents the plot even when it cannot be found in any single narrators particular account (Bal
2009). Stories, then, are used to capture the imagination and support of decision-makers and
public to rally around a policy initiative and form a coalition in support of it. Sometimes, in
fact, the stories themselves organize these coalitions and networks of policy actorsliterally,
policy movements and networks are emplotments of characters and events into one coherent
narrative (Lejano et al. 2013). Most recently, Lejano and Leong (2012) develop a hermeneutic
approach for analyzing the multiple dimensions of public debate.
But this should not be thought of as mere political spin doctoring, as the stories one nds
in the policy realm can be taken at face value or critiqued, and can engender belief or incre-
dulity. So the question is: ow can we tell a good, from a bad, narrative interpretation of a public
issue? There are dierent ways, and Kaplan (1986) discusses some. In Kaplans terms, good
narratives should be empirically veriable, rich, and coherent. First, a narrative can be tested
Postpositivism and the policy process
103
against known empirical information, events, etc. Secondly, given two narratives that both meet
empirical tests, the one that is able to account for more facets of experience, empirical reality,
and peoples personal accounts, should be regarded as the better, richer one. Lastly, the test of
coherence suggests that we assess the strength by which dierent accounts, dierent facets of the
story, the sequence of events, etc. are connected by some logical (or other) scheme. For example,
the passage I saw a bird ying. I started weeping. is not as coherent as this one: I saw a bird
ying above me. The majesty and utter simplicity of this reality made me feel so alive, I could
not but begin to weep. There are other prescriptions for how one distinguishes a better story
from an inferior one, but in practice, this poses no problem for us in everyday life. To cite a trivial
example, everyone knows Rocky I was a far better story than Rocky V, without even needing
to explicitly describe the complex mode by which we come to such judgements.
The pragmatism test lies in the ability of the reconstructed narrative to explain the dierent
contingencies and particularities surrounding the issue. Does it help us better to understand the
motivations of the dierent actors and their actions? In the case study to be taken up herein, does it
help us to understand why opposition to the project was so strong and eective, and why
attempts by the agency at knowledge transfer did not suce to quell this opposition?
Why is there a need to nd meanings beyond the surface of what people say or write? First of
all, there may be processes or conditions, like ocean currents beneath a surface calm, that inuence
the proceedings even though these processes may be well removed from the matter at hand.
Tradition, power, culture, and other forces of structuration act like this. Second, there may be issues
that stakeholders, consciously or subconsciously, relegate to the background. Yanow notes that
in public decision-making, some issues are verbotennamely publicly unspeakable because there
is no explicit public consensus underlying them (1992: 400). This is also tied up with political
necessities such as maintaining public silences about contradictions (1992: 418).
Policy institutions and the postmodern condition
In the previous section, we took up the task of analyzing policy ends and determining policy
directions when truth and good could not be unambiguously stated. We then, now, ask the
closely related question of what is the policy enacting institution (an agency, a community, or an
individual) to do under such uncertainty? How do policy actors proceed to act in the public realm?
If, taking a cue from Lyotard, all policy discussions were simply nothing other than language
games, then policy-making must then be simply a competition over the best discourse. This can
devolve into the classic pluralist model of competition over policy agendas. In this game, the
better, more inuential, better resourced interest group wins the policy battle. But this process can
take dierent forms, in part determined by how policy institutions view the policy question.
Karl Poppers epistemological framework viewed the establishment of truth and good as
unachievable by any objective, scientic model but rather the contingent and defeasible setting of
truth claims. By defeasible, we mean a process whereby claims are constantly subject to testing
and conrmation or revision in the world of practical implementation (Popper 1994). This incre-
mentalist view of knowledge leads to a pluralist model such as that of Lindbloms mutual partisan
adjustment, wherein, through a tug of war of competing interests, society nds some reasonably
optimal trajectory that is cognizant of the diering interests and their strength of preference
(1965). In this model, process determines the right.
But process can determine what is right in other ways. Habermas believed in the possibility
of a kind of rationality that had a transcendent moment that allowed the diverse and conictual
set of policy actors to come to agreement over what is right (1984). In this model, what is true
and good is not available a priori but reached through a process of agonistic debate. It is still a
Lejano
104
tug of war, carried out through dialogue, but with a dierence: in this model, policy actors can
come to a mutually agreed resolution of what is right and good, through the force of better
argument. The key, in this communicative model of rationality, is the practice of the ideal speech
situation, where all have an ability to speak and be heard and communication is nondistorted.
This epistemological framework nds its application in dierent practical models for public delib-
eration and consensus-building (Bobrow and Dryzek 1987; Healey 1996; Innes and Booher
2009; Susskind et al. 1999). In these situations, consensus can be reached through compromise
across xed but divergent interests (Fisher et al. 1991), or through the construction of new
understandings of a situation that move policy actors to reconsider their positions or to realize a
higher goal that exceeds the provincial limits of individual preference (Schön and Rein 1994).
The social construction of policy pertains not just to the identication of solutions to pressing
social problems, but the active construction of the problems themselves. As Schneider and Ingram
depicted it, what the issue is, what the stakes are, who the stakeholders are, and what their roles
in the policy issue as constructed might bethat is, as targets, beneciaries, victims, or agents of
policy (1997). In this framework, the key step is reached well before problem-solving begins
but in the earlier phase of issue identication and stakeholder analysis. This view of policy lends
a constructionist interpretation to the issue-salience and policy windows model of the policy
process (see Kingdon 1984). Issues do not exist a priori to be solvedrather, they are constructed
in response to the priorities of agenda-setters. In some cases, policy solutions preexist issues and
can take the form of policy responses waiting for appropriate problems to be identied in order
for them to be employed (March and Simon 1958). From this point of view, military action (to
take one example) is seen not as a response to an emergent conict, but the other way around,
namely conicts are identied (or designed) as a response to an unmet demand for military action.
In this type of policy milieu, ideas (which are what social constructions are, after all) and the
rhetorical skill by which they are deployed become the focus of policy attention (Throgmorton
1991; Howlett and Rayner 2008).
Models of the policy process taken up in the rst section of this book still pertain. We are
well advised to not jettison the idea of a policy process template. In the context of the linguistic
turn, however, each of the stages in the policy cycle are now seen as forums for public delib-
eration, namely as part of an extended communicative process. As Laswell rst suggested, an initial
step still remains that of issue identication, but since meaning of policy can no longer be xed,
interpretations of issues (and their salience in the public mind) continues all throughout the
policy process. Moreover, in the postmodern era, these processes need not necessarily lead to
outcomes, at least not idealized ones, nor to a transition from one stage to another. Habermas
speech situation need not lead to decisions, as the focus is on the communicative process. In
Lyotards model of paralogy, consensus is never envisionedit is enough to simply have debate
and an airing of disparate views. In the postpositivist age, talk is action.
But this is just a short step away from a complete rethinking of the policy process.
Deconstructing the policy process
Classic models of the policy process, involving stages or cycles of issue identication, analysis, and
nally, implementation are actually translations of the rational model into institutional form.
The classic rational model of analysis involves just these stages, from identication of overall
goals or values, enumeration of policy alternatives, evaluation, decision, and enaction. The idealized
policy process is a hypostatization of the model of rationality.
But just as, not merely postructural theory, but the practice and follies of real-world policy has
forced us to reconsider the rational model, so is it possible to deconstruct the entire policy process.
Postpositivism and the policy process
105
In part, this deconstructionist turn is guided by the new institutionalism that emerged from the
elds of public administration and organization theory. In this postmodern view, institutions are
themselves social constructions (e.g. March and Olsen 1989) that themselves are crafted after well-
constructed narratives (Weick 1995). When institutions take on a repeatable form, it is not because
of some objective property of these institutions, but rather, because their social constructions
become norms or standards that diuse from polity to polity (DiMaggio and Powell 1991).
While the turn away from logocentricity involved an undoing of the idea that meaning is
xed in the words of policy, it also undoes the primacy of the author as the center of meaning.
From this point onward, policy will be, as Barthes put it, a writerly text (1975), where the
implementors and targets of policy are just as much authors as the writers of policy. This turns
the policy process inside out. For example, where and at what stage is policy designed? In a
deconstructed process, policy is not simply designed in a central location and diused outward;
rather, it undergoes transformation and redesign as new policy actors take on the institutional
norm and make use of it (Howlett and Rayner 2008). Consider a policy on conditional cash
transfers for the poor, wherein payments are made to recipients so long as the latter pledge to or
prove that they use the money for medical or educational purposes. Then consider a situation
wherein eld agents who implement the policy by making the actual transfers to recipients and
collect information, decide to allow a womens cooperative to pool their outlays and obtain credit
from a local bank. Are the eld agents not also participating in design of the policy, not as formally
laid out but as actualized in the eld?
As Pressman and Wildavsky showed, neat boundaries between the policy design and imple-
mentation become blurred in practice (1979). In practice, all such conceptualizations of the policy
process do blur in many dierent ways. For this reason, one can take a phenomenological
approach to analyzing policy processes. Instead of beginning, in positivist fashion, from the uni-
versal concept and applying it to actual processes deductively, one can instead begin and end
with the actual process in place, in actual context, as Husserl, the pioneer of phenomenological
thought, put it: to the thing itself (1900). That is, do not analyze the process according to a pre-
constructed template, whether it be one of stages or cycles of policy-making; rather, describe it
as it is, as experienced and observed in place. For example, Argyris and Schön wrote about how
actual programs might be characterized by theories-in-practice rather than theories underlying
their design (1974).
An example of phenomenological description is seen in Lejano (2008), wherein habitat con-
servation policy is described not according to its formal design, but in the informal, dynamically
evolving practices that made up the policy as experienced. In such a mode of description,
formal descriptors of policy processes (e.g. designers, implementors, organizational roles and rules,
bureaucratic structure) all blur into sometimes new categories requiring new modes of description.
For example, in the aforementioned study, instead of describing the program as a set of rules, the
author modeled it as a web of relationships, all cohering with each other in dynamic fashion.
Another mode of studying a deconstructed policy process is to study it in the same way as
one might study the social construction of a narrative that is shared with others. The formation
of such a narrative is congruent with the formation of the network of actors that share it.
Latour, Callon, Law, and others have sought to describe the process by which such actor-networks
are formed (Latour 2005; Callon 1986; Law 1992). Callon describes it as the translation of the
policy story into forms that can be assimilated by (or, perhaps more accurately, can emplot)
other actors. In this translation process, he posits four stages (1986):
Problematisation:dening a problem that requires joint action, and set of actors who are
potentially enmeshed in it.
Lejano
106
Interessement: the negotiation of actors involvement and roles in the initiative.
Enrollment: actors acceptance and acting out of these roles.
Mobilization: the expansion of the network to include communities of support.
It is not an accident that the above sequence also resembles the exposition of a storys plot
namely identication of the conict, description of the setting and cast of characters, and mobili-
zation of action on the characters part. The description of the network process is not far from
the act of emplotmentin fact, they are essentially one and the same.
The turn away from the positivist notion of determinate problem solutions and a functionalist
notion of the policy process leads to a turning toward, instead of the linear process of locating
solutions, the discursive process of issue construction and deliberation. The focus is not on the
location of the optimal solution, but on the gathering together of a critical coalition (or net-
work) that supports and champions a policy idea to completion. Callon and Latour took this
same road by focusing on the network formation process. Howlett and Ramesh (1998) discussed
how to delineate the characterized policy subsystems (which are almost the same as the net-
works described above) in terms of their openness to new policy ideas and disposition to policy
change. In this literature, the postpositivist focus is not so much on the narrative and its narra-
tion, but on the formation of coalitions and shifts in memberships and allegiances (Sabatier and
Jenkins-Smith 1993), which one reasons, leads to shifts in their shared narratives. By retaining
the classic notion of interest-based coalitions, these theories are able to combine frame, interests,
and knowledge base in one process theory.
There are other ways to modify the otherwise linear, rational process model. As Goman had
shone light onto social and organizational processes that occurred backstage (e.g. on the
street, at home, in the coee shop, smokey room, etc.) rather than the foreground of policy-making
(e.g. senate oor, parliament, executive boardroom, etc.), researchers began paying attention to
informal processes (e.g. Innes and Booher 2010), decentralized decision-making in the eld (e.g.
Lipsky 1980), or policy-making within complex networks (e.g. Kickert et al. 1997). The tran-
sition away from formal institutional processes nds its most ambitious form in a growing lit-
erature on practice (e.g. Bourdieu 1977; Giddens 1984). The modernist impulse would seek to
nd universal rules in the structures that govern individuals in society (as in dialectical materi-
alism or classic political institutional theory) or within the individual (as in rational choice or
behavioralist theories). In contrast, theorists of practice aim to represent meaning and action as
traversing the structure-agency divide. For example, Bourdieu discusses how individual decision-
making is an improvisation guided by sometimes rigid controls, often not transparent to the
individual and often immanent in the bodys own habitual movements (1990). In this frame-
work, enacting of reproductive health policy, as an example, is as much or more determined by
the everyday routines women and men follow subconsciously than formal rules and programs
the functioning of political institutions if steered by similar habitual patterns, such as talk and
dress and relationships between members of an organization. Such focus on practice, while by
now well established in the organizational literature, is just beginning to have an eect on
policy studies.
Furthermore, if policy-making proceeds through the construction of a policy narrative, then
perhaps it is also through narrative means by which the process is best described. This involves
soliciting stories from policy actors caught up in the process (as in Pentland 1999; also Lejano et al.
2012). Description of the process is captured by narrative. These stories can vary from place to
placeperhaps aligned with easily recognized templates (e.g. policy stages) in some respect, but
nely and richly dierent in the way it unfolds. Through a postpositivist lens, these ne dif-
ferences are as important as the general commonalities. Whereas the positivist lens emphasizes
Postpositivism and the policy process
107
deductive reasoning from universal principles (e.g. policy stages), postpositivism focuses on the
particulars of the phenomenon.
To sum up: why are processes not so easily circumscribed in a postpositivist frame of analysis?
Because policy no longer can be seen as an object that can be objectively determined, and
neither can we place exactly where policy is crafted and how. Policy meanings cannot be
pinned down and, so, where there used to be analysis, we have deliberation all throughout the
policy process, and where there used to be pure implementation, we now have redesign and
reinterpretation of policy. Authorship of policy is not xed and determinate, and where a policy
is authored is similarly deconstructed to include a new constellation of policy actors.
The problem of social construction
Contrary to a radical constructionist interpretation of policy, most of the scholars cited above do
not espouse simple constructionism (Fischer 2003). Policy stories are not simply ctions crafted
out of sheer artice. We discussed, earlier, certain tests of validity and pragmatic value that allow
us to discern whether one narrative is more credible than another. Just because we weaken the
notion of objective standards for truth does not mean an inability to tell better from worse policy
narratives. Social constructs have to be coherent, and the parts of their story have to be internally
logically consistent.
Just as importantly, policy stories have to, ultimately, be grounded in the real experiences of policy
actors. The last ten years have been a sobering experience for us all, but especially policy scholars.
Notwithstanding the concerted eort to build momentum for the war in Iraq, at some point, policy-
makers had to reconcile their policy narrative with the nagging fact that there were no weapons
of mass destruction (WMDs) in Iraq. Despite the degree to which the homeownership narrative
captured the public psyche, at some point in the last few years, the socially constructed value of
property had to reconcile with the limitations of earning power of the would-be property owners,
and bubbles began to burst. There is not an innite array of narratives that can capture the public
agenda, but only those that cohere with how people and policy-makers understand themselves and
the world around them. Such understandings are borne by learning over lifetimes of experience.
Whether bubbles or WMDs, what confronts the public today is the turning back of the pen-
dulum away from a hapless constructionism to a sober realization that policy narratives are not
ctions but rather attempts to represent reality. The failure of cherished institutions (market, state,
and community) have created a void in the way we idealize policy process.
1
What are needed
now are approaches that reconcile the desire for objective foundations for policy-making with
the inescapable intedeterminate nature of policy. Perhaps what we are beginning to see is a turn
toward a post-constructionist understanding of policy and its processes (Lejano 2006). Doubtless,
we perceive this in the recent focus on evidence-based policy-making (Pawson 2006; Bochel
and Duncan 2007; Khagram and Thomas 2010). But another part of it may be a reversion to pure
ideology. It seems that polities, the world over, are now caught in a divide between requiring
more and better-informed judgments from decision-makers or giving up on rational process alto-
gether and relying on exhortations from political extremists (and the latter occur in many forms
pastors, mullahs, talk show hosts, governors and former governors). In this ironic age, the new
freedoms of digital communication and social networks seem to go hand in hand with the
increasing demise of free and democratic public discourse.
2
The challenge for political life is to
discover a new middle ground where polities are free to imagine and craft new futures while
grounding deliberation on the realities of everyday life.
Policy studies have to nd such middle (or higher) ground, as well (Lejano 2006). As De
Leon writes concerning positivism and postpositivism: it would seem foolish to set the two
Lejano
108
concepts at odds, in a zero-sum game, as opposed to use them to inform and support one another
(1998, p.157). Perhaps as a necessity, policy scholars who take the route of postpositivism have
espoused a deep critique, and often wholesale rejection, of the positivist model. But this has
created a bifurcated literature, with neither side wary of the achievements of the other. Doctoral
students in the elds of policy and public administration are asked, early in their academic
careers, to choose one or other of these alternatives. To postpositivists, quantitative models seem to
merely scratch the surface of institutions, and to positivists, discursive approaches appear to be pure
artice. If the rst decade of this new century is any indication, measurement and discourse need
a new reconciliation.
As one recalls the turn that policy studies took after the crises of the 1960s and 1970s, one
wonders what corner we are turning now.
Notes
1 As an example, the ongoing nancial crisis gripping the European Union threatens institutional models
that envision new regional modes of collaborative policy-making. Asian models of state-sponsored
interventions in the market begin to reveal wicked trade-os between productivity and quality of life
and liberty. And as for the American model, we all know too well about its crises and ideological
standos.
2 As this chapter is being written, the authors own university in Irvine, California, is undergoing a crisis
over free speeche.g. students arrested for writing with chalk on pavement in protest against runaway
tuition fee increases.
Bibliography
Argyris, Chris and Donald Schön. 1974. Theory in Practice: Increasing Professional Eectiveness. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass.
Bal, Mieke. 2009. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, 3rd edn. Toronto: University of Toronto
Press.
Balfour, Danny L. and William Mesaros. 1994. Connecting the local narratives: Public administration as a
hermeneutic science, Public Administration Review 54: 55964.
Barthes, Roland. 1975. S/Z: An Essay. New York: Hill and Wang.
Berger, Peter and Thomas Luckmann. 1966. The Social Construction of Reality. New York: Doubleday.
Bobrow, Davis and John Dryzek. 1987. Policy Analysis by Design. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Bochel, H.M. and S. Duncan. 2007. Making Policy in Theory and Practice. Bristol: Policy Press.
Boje, David M. 1991. The storytelling organization: A study of story performance in an oce-supply
rm, Administrative Science Quarterly 36(1): 10626.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 1990. Structure, habitus, practice , in Pierre Boudieu (ed.) The Logic of Practice, Richard Nice (trans.).
Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.
Boyce, Mary E. 1995. Collective centring and collective sense-making in the stories and storytelling of
one organization, Organization Studies 16(1): 10737.
Bruner, Jerome. 1987. Life as narrative, Social Research: An International Quarterly 71(3): 691710.
—— 1991. The narrative construction of reality, Critical Inquiry 18(1): 121.
Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Callon, Michel. 1986. Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the scallops and the
shermen of St Brieuc Bay, in John Law (ed.) Power, Action and Belief: A New Sociology of Knowledge.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Chomsky, N. and E. Herman 1988. Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media. New
York: Pantheon Books.
Czarniawska,
B. 1998. A Narrative
Approach to Organization Studies. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Derrida, Jacques. 1978. Writing and Dierence (LÉcriture et la Diérence), A. Bass (trans.). Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Postpositivism and the policy process
109
de Leon, P. 1998. Models of policy discourse: Insights versus prediction, Policy Studies Journal 26(I):
147161.
de Saussure, Ferdinand. 1916. Cours de Linguistique Générale, C. Bally and A. Sechehaye (eds) with the
collaboration of A. Riedlinger. Lausanne and Paris: Payot; Course in General Linguistics, W. Baskin
(trans.), 1977. Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.
DiMaggio, Paul and Walter Powell. 1991. The iron cage revisited: Institutional Institutional isomorphism and
collective rationality in organization elds, in P. DiMaggio and W. Powell (eds) The New Institutionalism
in Organizational Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Douglas, M. 1966. Purity and Danger: An Analysis of Concepts of Pollution and Taboo, Routledge and Keegan
Paul, London.
Dryzek, J. 1982. Policy analysis as hermeneutic activity, Policy Science 14(4): 30929.
Edelenbos, J., N. van Schie and L. Gerrits. 2010. Organizing interfaces between government institutions
and interactive governance, Policy Sciences 43(1): 7394.
Fischer, Frank. 2003. Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative Practices. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
——and John Forester (eds). 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Fisher, R., W. Ury, and B. Patton. 1991. Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In. New
York: Penguin.
Forester, John. 1999. The Deliberative Practitioner. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, Alan Sheridan (trans.). New York:
Pantheon.
Giddens, Anthony. 1984. The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration. Berkley, CA:
University of California.
Goman, E. 1974. Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1984. Reason and the Rationalization of Society, vol. 1 of The Theory of Communicative
Action, Thomas McCarthy (trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.
Hajer, Maarten A. and Hendrik Wagenaar (eds). 2003. Deliberative Policy Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Hampton, Greg. 2009. Narrative policy analysis and the integration of public involvement in decision
making, Policy Sciences 42: 22742.
Healey, Patsy. 1996. The
communicative turn in
planning theory and its implications for spatial
strategy-making, Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 23(2): 21734.
Howlett, Michael and M. Ramesh 1998. Policy subsystem congurations and policy change: Operationalizing
the postpositivist analysis of the politics of the policy process, Policy Studies Journal 26(3): 46681.
——and Jeremy Rayner. 2008. Third generation policy diusion studies and the analysis of policy mixes:
Two steps forward and one step back?, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis: Research and Practice 10(4):
385402.
Hysing, E. 2009. From government to governance? A comparison of environmental governing in Swedish
forestry and transport, Governance 22 (4), 64772.
Husserl, Edmund. 1900. Logical Investigations (Logische Untersuchungen) vol. 1, J.N. Findlay (trans.). New
York: Routledge.
Innes, Judith E. and David E. Booher. 2010. Planning with Complexity: An Introduction to Collaborative
Rationality for Public Policy, New York, NY: Routledge.
Jameson, Frederic. 1994. Postmodernism, or the cultural logic of late capitalism, New Left Review 1: 146.
Khagram, S. and C.W. Thomas. 2010. Toward a platinum standard for evidence-based assessment by
2020, Public Administration Review 70(s1): S100S106.
Kaplan, Thomas. 1986. The narrative structure of policy analysis, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management
5(4): 76178.
Kickert, Walter J.M., Erik-Hans Klihn and Jopp F.M. Koppenjan. 1997. Managing Complex Networks:
Strategies for the Public Sector. London and Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Koppenjan, J. and Klijn, E.H. 2004. Managing Uncertainties in Networks: A Network Approach to Problem
Solving and Decision Making. London: Routledge.
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
——2005. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lejano
110
Law, John. 1992. Notes on the theory of the actor network: Ordering, strategy, and heterogeneity,
Available at: www.lancs.ac.uk/fass/sociology/papers/law-notes-on-ant.pdf
Lejano, Raul. 2008. The phenomenon of collective action: Modeling institutions as structures of care,
Public Administration Review May/June: 491504.
——and Ching Leong. 2012. A hermeneutic approach to explaining and understanding public con-
troversies, JPART Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory (http://jpart.oxfordjournals.org/
content/early/2012/04/04/jopart.mus001.abstract).
——, Helen Ingram and Mrill Ingram. 2013. The Power of Narrative in Networks: Relating Alternative Ecologies.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lipsky, Michael. 1980. Street-level Bureaucracy: Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Services. New York:
Russell Sage Foundation.
Lindblom, Charles. 1965. The Intelligence of Democracy: Decision Making Through Mutual Adjustment. New
York: Free Press.
Lyotard, Jean-François 1979. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press.
Mannheim, Karl. 1940. Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction. London: Routledge.
March, James and Herbert Simon. 1958. Organizations. New York: Wiley.
——and Johan Olsen. 1989. Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics. New York: Free Press.
Martin, J. 1982. Stories and scripts in organizational settings, in A.H. Hastorf and A.M. Isen (eds) Cognitive
and Social Psychology. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 255305.
Mill, John Stuart. 1863. Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son, & Bourn.
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1990. Loves Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Ospina, Sonia M. and Jennifer Dodge. 2005. Its about time: Catching method up to meaningthe usefulness
of narrative inquiry in public administration research, Public Administration Review 65(2): 14357.
Patriotta, Gerardo. 2003. Sensemaking on the shop oor: Narratives of knowledge in organizations,
Journal of Management Studies 40(2): 34976.
Pawson, R. 2006. Evidence-based Policy: A Realist Perspective. London: Sage.
Pentland, Brian. 1999. Building process theory with narrative: From description to explanation, Academy
of
Management Review 24(4): 71124.
Popper,
Karl. 1994. All Life is Problem Solving. New York: Routledge.
Powell, Walter and Paul DiMaggio. 1991. The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Pressman, J. and A. Wildavsky. 1979. Implementation: How Great Expectations in Washington are Dashed in
Oakland: Or, Why Its Amazing that Federal Programs Work at All, This Being a Saga of the Economic
Development Administration as Told by Two Sympathetic Observers Who Seek to Build Morals on a Foundation
of Ruined Hopes. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Rabinow, P. and W. Sullivan (eds). 1979 and 1987. Interpretive Social Science: A Reader. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Rapley, John. 1996. Understanding Development: Theory and Practice in the Third World. Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner.
Ricoeur, Paul. 1976. Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning. Texas: Christian University Press.
—— 1981. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and Interpretation, John B. Thompson
(ed. and trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
——. 1984. Time and Narrative, vol. 1, K. McLaughlin and D. Pellaver (trans.). Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
—— 1992. Oneself as Another, Kathleen Blamey (trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rittel, Horst and Melvin Webber. 1973. Dilemmas in a general theory of planning Policy Sciences, vol. 4.
Amsterdam: Elsevier Scientic, 15569. (Reprinted in N. Cross (ed.) 1984. Developments in Design
Methodology, Chichester: John Wiley & Sons 13544.
Roe, Emery M. 1989. Narrative analysis for the policy analyst: A case study of the 19801982 medy
controversy in California, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 8: 25173. doi:10.2307/3323382.
—— 1994. Narrative Policy Analysis: Theory and Practice. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Ryan, Marie-Laure. 2007. Toward a denition of narrative, in David Herman (ed.) The Cambridge
Companion to Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2235.
Sabatier, P.A. and H.C. Jenkins-Smith. 1993. Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Postpositivism and the policy process
111
Schelling, Thomas C. 1980. The Strategy of Conict, reprinted, illustrated and revised. edn. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Schneider, Anne and Helen Ingram. 1997. Policy Design for Democracy . Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas.
Schön, Donald and Martin Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies.
New York: Basic Books.
Schout, Adriaan, Andrew Jordan, and Michelle Twena. 2010. From old to new governance in the
EU: Explaining a diagnostic decit, West European Politics 33(1): 15470.
Schram, Sanford and Philip T. Neisser. 1997. Tales of the State: Narrative in Contemporary U.S. Politics and
Public Policy. Langham, MD: Rowman & Littleeld.
Scott, James C. 1998. Seeing like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Scott, W. Richard. 1998. Organizations: Rational, Natural, and Open Systems. Englewood Clis, NJ:
Prentice Hall.
—— 2001. Institutions and Organizations. 2nd edn. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Selznick, Philip. 1949. TVA and the Grass Roots: A Study in the Sociology of Formal Organization. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Sköldberg, Kaj. 1994. Tales of change: Public administration reform and narrative mode, Organization
Science 5: 21938.
Stone, Deborah. 1997. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision-Making. New York: Norton.
Susskind, Lawrence, Jennifer Thomas-Larmer and Sarah McKearnen. 1999. The Consensus Building Handbook:
A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Throgmorton. J.A. 1991. The rhetorics of policy analysis, Policy Sciences 24: 15379.
van Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern. 1944. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Charles Scribner [1904].
Weick, K.E. 1995. Sensemaking in Organizations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Wesselink, Anna and Jeroen Warner. 2010. Reframing Floods: Proposals and Politics, Nature and Culture 5(1):
114.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. [c. 1922]
1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: Suivi
De Investigations Philosophiques.
Paris: Librairie Gallimard.
Yanow, Dvora. 1992. Silences in public policy disclosure: Organizational and policy myths, Journal of
Public Administration Research and Theory 2: 399423.
—— 2001. Conducting Interpretive Policy Analysis. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
—— 2007. Interpretation in policy analysis: On methods and practice , Critical Policy Studies 1: 11022.
Lejano
112
Part III
Modelling the policy process
Frameworks for analysis
9
The institutional analysis and
development framework
Ruth Schuyler House and Eduardo Araral Jr.
As a relatively young discipline and an intrinsically complex science, public policy has yet to con-
geal into a clear-cut school of thought. Rather, its borders are diuse, both overlapping with
and comprising multiple pure disciplines of the social and natural sciences. Indeed, the com-
plexities of the open systems subject to study necessitate a multidisciplinary approach that pragma-
tically draws from the elds most germane to the particular issues at hand. Further, by drawing
from dierent approaches, scholars can develop constructively competitive views of a context in
order to come to a more enlightened understanding about the potential eects of public action.
Institutional scholars engagement with classical economics, political science, law, sociology,
psychology, natural science, and a host of other elds in the pursuit of understanding the policy
process has generated an incredibly rich and variant body of scholarship united by a common
focus on institutions and their roles (among other important factors) in shaping, constraining,
and enabling human behavior. By focusing on rule sets and the major physical and social constructs
characterizing a particular situation, institutional scholars seek to grapple with both macro-level
social structures and individual agency and also move beyond the market versus hierarchy division
to identify a more elemental set of components comprising any and all situations of human
interaction.
We believe that institutional analysis makes an important contribution to the study of public
policy for a number of reasons, in particular its established record of drawing from multiple
elds as discussed already. For one, institutional research over the past 25 years has advanced
Douglass Norths early challenge to progress economics from a static to dynamic theory of
human exchange (North 1990, p.107). Indeed, institutions have come to be commonly recog-
nized as a critical factor shaping political and economic behavior, but we have yet to fully
understand what types of institutions (if any) are requisite for the development and the
maintenance of functioning democracies, let alone how to manage and control processes of
institution building and institutional change. Moreover, institutional analysisand more
specically, the institutional analysis and development (IAD) framework developed largely by
Elinor Ostrom and her colleagues at the Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis at
Indiana Universitycomes as close as any approach to oering a framework that is generally
applicable to comparatively studying a wide variety of social situations. Finally, as entirely new
and sometimes blended structures of organization emerge in an increasingly complex, globalized
115
political economy, we need to utilize theoretical frameworks that are capable of encompassing
multitudinous patterns of human interaction.
Frameworks, theories, and models
Before delving into the IAD framework, we must clarify what a framework is, and how it
relates the many theories and modelseach with their own constructs and vocabulariesused
to understand public policy. Ostrom herself oers a clear explanation distinguishing between
theories, frameworks, and models (2007, p.25). Most broadly, a framework identies a set of
general variables and relationships that should be studied in order to understand a particular
phenomenon, but assigns no values to the variables and does not specify the direction of rela-
tionships between them. In essence, the framework is an organizing tool that allows the com-
parison of dierent theories, many of which may be compatible with a particular framework.
According to Ostrom, frameworks attempt to identify the universal elements that any theory
relevant to the same kind of phenomena would need to include (2005, p.826).
A theory species a more coherent set of assumptions about elements within the framework,
including their relationships with each other, their importance to answering particular kinds of
questions, and expectations about interactions and outcomes. For example, game theory, classical
economic theory, transaction cost theory, and a host of other theories have been extensively
used alongside the IAD framework.
Finally, a model is used to represent a specic situation and makes explicit assumptions about the
values of variables and the expected outcomes of a situation given a particular set of parameters (Ostrom
2007, p.26). Since there exist numerous ways in which a particular system of human organization or
governance might be studied and understood, the IAD framework becomes useful to engage in
comparative study across disciplines and draw nearer toward generalized understandings about the
creation, implementation, interaction, and outcomes of rules arrangement in dierent contexts.
Institutions
Before jumping into the application of the IAD framework, we must rst come to a common
understanding of its primary focus: institutions. What, then, are institutions, and why do they
constitute an important unit of analysis? Perhaps the most commonly cited denition of institu-
tions is Douglas Norths: institutions are the rules of the game of a society, or, more formally,
the humanly devised constraints that structure human interaction (1990), including formal laws
and regulations and informal constraints, such as conventions and social norms. Emphasizing
their functionality, Menard and Shirley dene institutions as the rules, norms, and constraints
that humans devise to reduce uncertainty and control their environment (2005). While scho-
lars of dierent strands of institutionalism dier in opinion about the human intentionality of
institutional forms, the rational choice or actor-centered institutionalists who most commonly
utilize the IAD framework see institutions as constructs intentionally devised by political or eco-
nomic actors to serve particular purposes. Ostrom describes rules as shared prescriptions (must,
must not, or may) that are mutually understood and enforced in particular situations in a pre-
dictable way by agents responsible for monitoring conduct and for imposing sanctions and
norms as shared prescriptions known and accepted by most of the participants themselves involving
intrinsic costs and benets rather than material sanctions or inducements (2005, p.824).
The varied use of multiple denitions of the term institution (for example, when used to
refer to physical buildings like hospitals or organizations like the UN as opposed to rule sets) is
one among many challenges of institutional research. Furthermore, institutions are invisible and are
House and Araral
116
thus very dicult to describe, dene, and measure. And quite often, the most inuential rules
governing a system of interaction are the informal norms and conventionsthe rules-in-use ”—
rather than the rules-in-form on formal record (Ostrom 2007, p.23). The eects of particular
rules are also dicult to study in isolation, as rules and norms consistently interact with the
constellation of other rules and exogenous factors that dene a particular situation.
Finally, rules exist at multiple levels, and rules at any one level are embedded in the next
higher tier. The nestedness of lower levels in higher tiers is important to understanding how
rule changes (and thereby institutional change) at one level are inuenced by rules and contextual
factors at other levels. Thus, institutional analysis becomes akin to untangling the relationships
between rules within and across levels. As Kiser and Ostrom point out, rules exist at the opera-
tional level that govern the every day activities and decisions of agents in an interactive situation.
Moving higher, there exists a set of collective choice level rules that constrain those at the opera-
tional level and determine how operational rules are set. And at the constitutional choice level, rules
that govern the process of rule-setting, including who may be involved and how, frame the
collective-choice and operational situations (Kiser and Ostrom 1982).
Oliver Williamson, the prominent transaction cost scholar, proposes a similar delineation of
institutional tiers, where human exchanges lie at the most immediate level. These transactions are
constrained by governance structures, which are in turn shaped by the institutional environment
set by property rights rules, the bureaucracy, legislative processes, etc. Finally, all of these rule struc-
tures are couched within rules at the level of embedded norms and traditions, which change
most slowly and are often studied via application of social theory (Williamson 1998). Despite
minor variations, the point is that most theorizing related to institutions incorporates the recurring
themes of nestedness, congurative relationships, and interrelatednesscharacteristics that make
institutional analysis complex and prescriptions for institutional reform often quite tentative.
The IAD framework
Given the complexity of studying institutions, along with the observed dierences in approa-
ches to understanding institutions, the Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD) framework
unies the multidisciplinary study of rules and norms in a common analytical framework com-
prising a number of key variables that dene a particular action situation. The framework is applic-
able to both snapshot analyses as well as process-oriented studies of institutional change, where
feedback becomes an important part of the analysis. Furthermore, the framework allows the
researcher to focus on particular components of an action situation, for example the external
physical variables, the actors characteristics, or the rules-in-use. Ultimately, the IAD framework
is intended to allow researchers to model the strategies players adopt within particular rule cong-
urations and to better understand how the mixture of participants, rules, strategies, community
attributes, and external variables, results in certain outcomes, and thereafter, how these outcomes
and participants responses to them pressure changes to the prevailing rule sets.
Like any good framework, the IAD framework maps out the broad variables applicable to
any institutional form (including markets, hierarchies, and collective action systems) that may be
studied by dierent theories and models. These broad variables, which Ostrom terms action arenas,
are nested subassemblies of a broader, interrelated social structure.
Action arenas are comprised of two lower-level subassemblies: the actors and the action situa-
tion (Ostrom 2007, p.28). The actors and action situation interact and are simultaneously aec-
ted by exogenous variables including physical conditions (e.g. the nature of a resource in a
common pool situation); community attributes (the social and cultural context); and the rules in
use, or institutional arrangements (ibid.; Ostrom et al. 1994).
Institutional analysis and development framework
117
The action arena
The action arena under study is the social space where individuals interact and is comprised of
the participants and their action situation (Ostrom 2005, p.829). Ostrom describes action situations
as collections of seven variables: rst, the participants; second, their positions; third, the set of
potential outcomes; fourth, information available; fth, the costs and benets associated with the
set of outcomes; sixth, the degree of control participants have over choices and strategies, and
seventh, relationships between actions and outcomes (Ostrom 2005, p.828). Also germane to
describing the situation is the frequency and duration of interactions and whether the situation
is recurrent or singular.
The actors, be they conceptualized as individuals, loose groups, or formal organizations, exhibit
dierent attributes aecting their behaviors. The researcher must investigate and make assumptions
about participants preferences, goals, values, beliefs, and decision-making strategies (Ostrom 2007,
p. 30). The actors may be characterized according to values of four variables: the resources they
control; the values they assign to various actions and outcomes; the way they use information; and
the processes they use for selecting strategies (Ostrom 2007, p. 28). It is also important to note that,
in the tradition of institutional economics, neoclassical economics, assumptions of pure rationality and
full information are discarded and replaced by a conceptualization of individual actors as boundedly
rational (Simon 1957) and typically lacking full information about the situation at hand.
External variables
A set of three important external contextual variables structure the arena: the rules-in-use, the
physical conditions of the good under study and the surrounding context, and the characteristics
of the community of participants (Kiser and Ostrom 2000).
Figure 9.1 A framework for institutional analysis
Source: Ostrom (1999: 42)
House and Araral
118
Rules-in-use
Returning to the notion of rules-in-use, a critical component of institutional analysis is discovering
how the nested, interlinked rules-in-use that aect potential payos and losses, demarcate the
set of allowable or feasible strategies, and inuence actors behaviors. These rules are subject to
the limits of human cognition, understanding, and language, and can only be discovered through
rigorous research of the understood dos and donts”—rules that may, indeed, be quite dierent
from or supersede the rules that exist on formal record (Ostrom 2005, p.832).
Which rules, then, are important to analyzing a particular action arena? Ostrom and Crawford
developed a typology of rules that should be specied in order to determine rst, their impact
on the action situation and actors, and second, the impact of one rule change upon another. In
cataloging the rules governing a particular situation and making note of their congurations,
scholars can thereafter better explain and predict the results of rule changes on the situation and
the likelihood of change itself. The set of important rules governing any situation includes
boundary rules that set who can participate and how easy is it for them to join or exit the arena;
position rules which assign positions of leadership, subservience, rank, etc.; authority rules which dene
what actions participants in dierent positions may or may not take; scope rules which restrict the
set of possible outcomes; aggregation rules which dene the degree of control an actor has at a
decision point; information rules which aect the availability of information for dierent participants;
and payo rules which assign the costs and benets linked to dierent actions. All of the many possible
congurations of these rule sets dene dierent institutions (Ostrom and Crawford 2005).
Beyond understanding the rules-in-use governing a situation, it is also important to understand
where the rules themselves originated, the history of their evolution, and the stability of their con-
guration. The stability of a rule sets conguration depends on multiple factors, including enfor-
cement capacity (Gibson et al. 2005; Ostrom 2005, p.833), the frequency of interactions, and the
degree to which rules are similarly understood and valued by participants (Ostrom 2005, p.833).
Attributes of the material context
Another critical factor that inuences the action arena is the state of the world in the arena at
handthe physical context, material conditions, and the type of good under study in the situation.
These conditions delimit what kinds of strategies and outcomes are at all possible and how particular
strategies relate to dierent outcomes (Ostrom 2005, p.837). Furthermore, regarding the good
under study, it becomes important for the researcher to ask critical questions about the nature of
the good, including the ability to exclude beneciaries and the subtractability of the ow
(ibid.)or the degree of rivalry, in neoclassical economic terms. These two attributes are used to
distinguish between public and private goods, common pool resources, and club goods, each of
which is associated with a set of assumptions and expectations related to their production and pro-
vision and the incentives of participants that utilize, control, trade, allocate, acquire, or produce
them. Additionally, it may be important to consider the size of the good, whether it can be stored
and transported, and how consistently it can be made available (Ostrom 2005, p.840).
Attributes of the community
The nal set of external variables that aect the action arena is the attributes of the larger commu-
nity, sometimes referred to as the culture (Ostrom 2005, p.841). According to Ostrom, the
attributes that are important to shaping behaviors in the action arena include the norms of behavior
generally accepted in the community, the level of common understanding potential participants
Institutional analysis and development framework
119
share about the structure of particular types of action arenas, the extent of homogeneity in the
preferences of those living in a community, and the distribution of resources among those aected
(Ostrom 2005, p.841). By specically accounting for the role of culture and shared conventions,
the IAD framework incorporates lines of enquiry more typical of sociological and anthropological
research into understanding policy situationsa shift responsive to long-standing critique of the
strict positivist tradition in policy science.
Linking arenas and studying institutional change
In addition to studying the eects of the aforementioned factors on a particular action situation,
it is also often important to uncover the linkages and relationships between factors in dierent
action arenas. More specically, the relationships between institutions at dierent levelsthe
operational, collective choice, and constitutionalare critical to processes of institutional change.
For the researcher, it is necessary to acknowledge that rules changes in one arena are constrained
by rules at a deeper level, and that changes in successively deeper levels are typically more costly
and dicult to make (Ostrom 2005, p.842). Because there are multiple sources of institutional
change with networked eects, sustained change in one component is dicult without con-
current change in others (Saleth and Dinar 2004). Further, change is dicult to coordinate and
depends not only on changing organization but also changing human behavior, the institutional
environment, and the institutions of governance at higher levels (Williamson 1998).
As for applying the framework to understand institutional change, exogenous variables are
assumed to be xed at the beginning of analysis, and resultant outcomes are thereafter judged
by participants according to criteria such as perceived eciency, equity, adaptability, account-
ability, and conformance to morality and general social norms. If outcomes are unproductive,
deemed unfair, or are otherwise displeasing to the actors in the arena, those actors will strategize
to change the rule structure. In this way, the IAD framework may be applied to research the
iterative, ongoing nature of policy-making.
Applications of the IAD framework
A key test of a frameworks utility is the extent to which it has been applied to a variety of
settings and research programs. The IAD framework meets this test as it is now extensively
used in teaching, research, and policy advice worldwide and is arguably one of the most utilized
frameworks in the US and Western Europe (Sabatier 2007) as well as in East, Southeast and
South Asia.
For instance, in teaching, dozens of graduate programs in public policy, political science,
economics, sociology, and ecology around the world use the IAD framework or elements of it
used in their curriculum. Examples include universities in Asia (Tsinghua University in China, the
National University of Singapore, Hong Kong University, Seoul National University, China
University of Political Science and Law, Asian Institute of Technology), Europe (Humboldt Uni-
versity, Stockholm School of Economics, Delft University Technology (Netherlands), Erasmus
University), North America (Indiana University, Arizona State University, University of Col-
orado, Rice University, University of California, Carleton University, UNAM (Mexico), Duke
University, University of Michigan, University of Nevada,) among others.
In terms of empirical and experimental research, the IAD framework has been extensively
used in a wide range of research programs. These include the commons research agenda such as
sheries (Basurto 2008; de Castro 2000), irrigation (Bruns 2009; Araral 2006); ground water
(Steed 2010; Wang 2006), forestry (Andersson 2003; Hayes 2007; Pacheco 2007; Persha 2008;
House and Araral
120
Jagger 2009; Marquez 2011); watersheds and river basins (Myint 2005; Heikilla et al. 2011); and
land use (Donnelly 2009).
The IAD framework has also been used not just for common pool natural resources but also
research on knowledge as commons (Hess and Ostrom 2006); infrastructure in developing
countries (Schroeder et al. 1993); property rights (Kauneckis 2005; Mwangi 2003); foreign aid
and bureaucratic incentives (Araral 2008); federalism and constitutional order (V. Ostrom 1991;
Jillson and Wilson 1994; Wang 2006; Oyerinde 2006); local public economies (Oakerson and
Parks 2011); public housing (Choe 1992); nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) and non-
prots (Bushouse 1999; Elliott-Teague 2007; Sabet 2005); global commons (McGinnis and
Ostrom 1996; Dolsak 2000; Allen 2005) as well as collective action problems and social
dilemmas (Dudley 1993; Ahn 2001; Coleman 2009; Araral 2009; van Laerhoven 2008).
Finally, in terms of policy advice, the IAD framework has been used in diverse policy settings such
as peace and nation-building in Liberia (Sawyer 2005), foreign aid (India, Kenya) (Gibson et al. 2005);
health care (United States), forestry policy in Bolivia (Andersson 2003), irrigation in the Philippines
(Araral 2006), among others.
Conclusion
The rich body of research used to develop the IAD framework alludes to the complexity of
institutional analysis and the problems associated with prescribing institutional reform with-
out a full study of the interrelations of the rules at work, particular social contexts, goods in
question, and underlying social norms. Nevertheless, the diverse community of institutional
scholars contributing to this line of enquiry has contributed to the growing sophistication of
institutional analysis. With luck, continued advancements in understanding the multiple rules at
play and the relationships between institutional arrangements and economic growth will allow
for more appropriate reform prescriptions, greater appreciation of the limitations of outside
intervention, and realistic expectations about changing institutional arrangements and growth
patterns.
While it is increasingly accepted that there exist no right institutions for any and all con-
texts, Ostroms and her colleagues studies of successful and failed institutions via application of
the IAD framework have allowed her to identify some general design principles including rst,
a clear denition of group boundaries; second, rules that are matched to local conditions; third,
active participation of individuals aected by rules; fourth, respect of community rule-making
rights by external authorities; fth, monitoring systems managed by community members; sixth,
established sanction systems; seventh, low-cost conict resolution mechanisms; and eighth nested
systems of governance in larger systems (Ostrom 1991). Further, increasing emphasis on the
importance of informal institutions should aord policy-makers a healthy dose of modesty when
designing and implementing institution-building programs, for as North warns, policy tools
are blunt instruments. We are often only able to signicantly change formal rules, while we
can exert very limited control over informal institutions (North 2008).
Finally, Robert Putnam reminds us of the ultimate goal of institutionsthat of achieving
purpose, not just agreement. Institutions shape politics by way of the rules and standard
operating procedures employed to reach political outcomes. And these institutions are inu-
enced by their particular historical and social contexts (Putnam et al. 1993). So then, under-
standing the collective goals that motivate institutional formation, how those institutions shape
social action and value systems, and again how those social goals lead to further institutional
change allow for a process-oriented, evolutionary understanding of economic growth and social
organization.
Institutional analysis and development framework
121
Bibliography
Ahn, T.K. 2001. Foundations for cooperation in social dilemmas PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University.
Allen, Linda. 2005. The politics of structural choice of the commission for environmental cooperation:
The theoretical foundations of the design of international environmental institutions, PhD dissertation,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Andersson, Krister P. 2002. Can decentralization save Bolivias forests? An institutional analysis of municipal
forest governance, unpublished dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
—— 2003. What motivates municipal governments? Uncovering the institutional incentives for municipal
governance of forest resources in Bolivia, Journal of Environment and Development 12(1): 527.
Araral, Eduardo K. 2006. Decentralization puzzles: A political economy analysis of irrigation reform in the
Philippines, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
—— 2008. The strategic games that donors and bureaucrats play: An institutional rational choice analysis,
JPART 19: 853871.
—— 2009. What explains collective action in the commons? Theory and evidence from the Phillipines,
World Development vol. 37, no. 3, 687697.
Basurto, Xavier. 2008. Biological and ecological mechanisms supporting marine self-governance: The Seri
Callo de Hacha shery in Mexico, Ecology and Society 13(2): 20.
Bruns, Bryan Rudolph. 2009. Solving Samaritans dilemmas in irrigation investment. Available at: www.
indiana.edu/~workshop/colloquia/ materials/papers/Bruns-Solving%20Sama ritans%20Dilemmas%20in%20Ir
rigation%20DRAFT090925.pdf
Bushouse, Brenda K. 1999. The mixed economy of child care: An institutional analysis of nonprot, for
prot, and public enterprises, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Choe, Jaesong. 1992. The organization of urban common-property institutions: The case of apartment
communities in Seoul, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Colfer, C.J.P. and R.G. Dudley. 1993. Shifting Cultivators of Indonesia: Marauders or Managers of the Forest.
Rice Production and Forest use among the Uma Jalan of East Kalimantan. Rome: Food and Agriculture
Organization
of the United
Nations.
Coleman, Eric. 2009. Essays on the eects of institutions and trust on collective action, PhD dissertation,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Croissant, Cynthia. 2005. Uses and landscape patterns: A study of relationships between human activities
and spatial patterns of land use and land cover on private parcels in Monroe County, Indiana, PhD
dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
De Castro, Fabio. 2000. Fishing accords: the political ecology of shing intensication in the Amazon,
PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Dolsak, Nives. 2000. Marketable permits: Managing local, regional, and global commons, PhD dissertation,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Donnelly, Shanon. 2009. Linking land use, land cover, and land ownership at the parcel scale in the
midwest United States, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Elliott-Teague, Ginger. 2007. NGOs in policymaking in Tanzania: The relationships of group characteristics,
political participation and policy outcomes, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Gibson, C.C., J.T. Williams and E. Ostrom. 2005. Local enforcement and better forests, World Development
33(2): 27384.
——, Krister Andersson, Elinor Ostrom and Sujai Shivakumar. 2005. The Samaritans Dilemma: The Political
Economy of Development Aid. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hayes, Tanya. 2007. Forest governance in a frontier: An analysis of the dynamic interplay between
property rights, land-use norms, and agricultural expansion in the Mosquitia forest corridor of Honduras
and Nicaragua, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Heikkila, Tanya, Edella Schlager and Mark W. Davis. 2011. The role of cross-scale institutional linkages
in common pool resource management: Assessing interstate river compact, Policy Studies Journal 39(1):
12145.
Hess, C. and E. Ostrom. 2006. Understanding Knowledge as a Commons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jagger, Pamela. 2009. Can forest sector devolution improve rural livelihoods? An analysis of forest income
and institutions in Western Uganda, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Jillson, Calvin C. and Rick K. Wilson. 1994. Congressional Dynamics: Structure, Coordination, and Choice in
the First American Congress, 17741789. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
House and Araral
122
Kauneckis, Derek. 2005. The co-production of property rights: Theory and evidence from a mixed-right
system in southern Mexico, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Kiser, L. and E. Ostrom. 1982. The three worlds of action: A metatheoretical synthesis of institutional
approaches, in E. Ostrom (ed.) Strategies of Political Inquiry. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 179222.
——and E. Ostrom. 2000. The three worlds of action: A metatheoretical synthesis of institutional
approaches, in Robert D. Putnam and Robert Leonardi (eds) Making Democracy Work. New York:
Greenwood Publishing Grou.
McGinnis, Michael and Elinor Ostrom. 1996. Design principles for local and global commons, in Oran
R. Young (ed.) The International Political Economy and International Institutions, Vol.2. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar.
Marquez, Lilian. 2011. The eect of institutions on Guatemalan forests: Conceptual, methodological and
practical implications, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Menard, C. and M.M. Shirley. 2005. Handbook of New Institutional Economics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Mwangi, Esther. 2003. Institutional change and politics: The transformation of property rights in Kenyas
Maasailand, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Myint, Tun. 2005. Strength of weak forces in multilayer environmental governance: Cases from the
Mekong and Rhine River basins, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
North, D.C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
—— 1996. Institutions, organizations and market competition, Economic History 9612005, EconWPA.
—— 2005. Institutions and the performance of economies over time, in C. Ménard and M. Shirley, (eds)
Handbook of New Institutional Economics. Dordrecht: Springer, 2130.
Oakerson, R. and Parks, R. 2011. The study of local public economies: Multi-organizational, multi-level
institutional analysis and development, Policy Studies Journal, vol. 39, 1(february): 147167.
Ostrom, E. 1991. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
—— 2005. Doing
institutional analysis digging
deeper than markets and hierarchies, Handbook of New
Institutional Economics, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 81948.
—— 2007. Institutional rational choice: An assessment of the institutional analysis and development fra-
mework,inTheories of the Policy Process, 2nd edition, edited by P.A. Sabatier, Boulder, CO: Westview
Press, 2134.
——, Larry Schroeder and Susan Wynne. 1993. Institutional Incentives and Sustainable Development: Infrastructure
Policies in Perspective. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——, R. Gardner and J. Walker. 1994. Rules, Games, and Common-pool Resources. Ann Arbor, MI: University
of Michigan Press.
——and S. Crawford. 2005. Classifying Rules. Understanding Institutional Diversity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 187215.
Ostrom, V. 1991. The Meaning of American Federalism: Constituting a Self-Governing Society, San Francisco,
CA: Institute for Contemporary Studies Press.
Oyerinde, Oyebade Kunle. 2006. The constitution of order among the Yoruba of Nigeria PhD dissertation,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Pacheco, Diego. 2007. An institutional analysis of decentralization and indigenous timber management
in common-property forests of Bolivias lowlands, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University.
Persha, Lauren. 2008. Decentralized forest management, anthropogenic disturbance patterns and forest
change in the Usambara Mountains, Tanzania, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Putnam, Robert D. and Robert Leonardi. 2002. Making Democracy Work. New York: Greenwood Publishing
Group.
Reiners, Derek. 2006. Institutional eects on decision-making and performance in public land agencies:
The case of wildre in the interior west of the United States, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University.
Sabatier, Paul A. (ed.). 2007. Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Sabet, Daniel M. 2005. Thickening civil society: nonpro t organizations and problems of water and
sanitation along Mexicos northern Border, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Saleth, R.M. and A. Dinar. 2004. The Institutional Economics of Water: A Cross-country Analysis of Institutions
and Performance. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Sawyer, A. 2005. Beyond Plunder: Toward Democratic Governance in Liberia .
Institutional analysis and development framework
123
Schoon, Michael. 2008. Building robustness to disturbance: Governance in Southern African Peace Parks,
submitted to the faculty of the University Graduate School in partial fulllment of the requirements for
the joint degree Doctor of Philosophy in the School of Public and Environmental Aairs and the
Department of Political Science, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Simon, H.A. 1957. Models of Man, Social and Rational: Mathematical Essays on Rational Human Behavior in a
Social Setting. New York: John Wiley.
Smith, Ronald S. 2006. Discerning dierences in social capital: the signicance of interpersonal network
and neighborhood association structure on citizen participation, PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University.
Steed B. 2010. Natural forces, human choices: an over time analysis of responses to ecological and human
induced disturbances in southern California water basin governance. PhD dissertation, Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University.
van Laerhoven, Frank. 2008. Local governance and the challenge of solving collective action dilemmas,
PhD dissertation, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Wang, Jianxun. 2006. Political economy of village governance in contemporary China, PhD dissertation,
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University.
Williamson, O.E. 1998. Transaction cost economics: How it works: where it is headed, The Economist
146(1): 2358.
House and Araral
124
10
The advocacy coalition framework
Coalitions, learning and policy change
Christopher M. Weible and Daniel Nohrstedt
Introduction
Policy process research is the study of public policy over time and the surrounding actors, con-
texts, and events. The formal academic study of policy processes began in the 1950s and 1960s,
led by the likes of Lerner and Lasswell (1951), Freeman (1955), Simon (1957), Lindblom (1959),
Dawson and Robinson (1963), Easton (1965), Ranney (1968), and Walker (1969). Policy pro-
cess research sprung, in part, from dissatisfaction with political scientists focus on governing
institutions (courts, legislatures, and executives), a theoretical desire to understand broader
political systems, optimism following successes of the social sciences during World War II, and a
practical desire to benet society.
Since the 1960s, a number of complementary research programs have emerged for describing
and explaining various aspects of policy processes (e.g. Sabatier 1999, 2007). Among these
research programs is the advocacy coalition framework (ACF) created by Paul Sabatier and
Hank Jenkins-Smith in the 1980s (Sabatier 1987, 1988; Jenkins-Smith 1990; Sabatier and Jenkins-
Smith 1993, 1999).
1
Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith established the ACF in response to several
perceived shortcomings in policy process research: a dissatisfaction with the policy cycle or stages
heuristic as a causal theory; a need to take more seriously the role of scientic and technical
information in policy processes; dissatisfaction with the top-down and bottom-up perspectives
of the implementation literature; a need to take a long-term time perspective to understand
policy processes; and a need to develop theories that assume more realistic human agents other
than the rational actor models found in microeconomics.
The ACF resulted as an amalgam inspired partly from previous studies of issue networks (Heclo
1978), implementation (Pressman and Wildavsky 1973; Mazmanian and Sabatier 1981; Hjern
and Porter 1981), learning (Heclo 1974; Weiss 1977), policy subsystems (Grith 1939; Freeman
1955), belief systems (Ajzen and Fishbein 1980; Putnam 1976; Peey and Hurwitz 1985; Hurwitz
and Peey 1987), scientic and technical information in policy debates (Mazur 1981; Jenkins-
Smith 1990), and a model of the individual based on bounded rationality and cognitive lters
(Simon 1957). The ACF serves as an analytical guide for answering questions principally about
advocacy coalitions, policy-oriented learning, and policy change.
125
The framework
Following Laudan (1977: 70120) and Ostrom (2005: 279), frameworks serve as a platform for
groups of scholars to work together toward common understandings and explanations of phe-
nomena. Frameworks provide assumptions, specify the scope of inquiry, and establish conceptual
categories with basic de nitions and general relations. Frameworks support the development
and testing of theory that, in turn, narrow the scope of inquiry, oer testable hypotheses, and
postulate causal relationships among concepts. This section introduces the ACF as an actual
framework by describing its assumptions, scope, and the basic concepts and the general relations
among them. The next sections describe the major theoretical emphases supported by the ACF.
Assumptions
Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith based the ACF on several foundational assumptions (1993: 1720):
The policy subsystem is the primary unit of analysis for understanding policy processes. Policy sub-
systems are dened by a substantive topic and territorial domain along with a set of people actively
involved in shaping subsystem aairs. Subsystems are simultaneously semi-autonomous while also
nested and interdependent (Sabatier 1998; Nohrstedt and Weible 2010). For example, a water policy
subsystem at local level will likely be nested in a regional policy subsystem which is nested
within a national policy subsystem. This same water policy subsystem at a local level overlaps to
various extents with other subsystems (e.g. a local-level transportation policy subsystem). To
attract the attention and involvement of actors, policy subsystems usually entail some degree of
authority or potential for authority to alter behavior and shape subsystem outcomes.
The set of relevant subsystem actors include any person attempting to inuence subsystem aairs. As
policy process research developed in the 1950s and 1960s, the emphasis was on symbiotic rela-
tions between legislative committees, interest groups, and the government agencies (what has
been referred to as the iron triangle). The ACF broadens the set of subsystem actors essen-
tially to include any person attempting to inuence subsystem aairs, including government
ocials, members of the private sector and nonprots, scientists and consultants, and members
of the media.
Individuals are boundedly rational with limited ability to process stimuli, motivated by belief systems,
and prone to experience the devil shift. The actors involved in policy subsystems are boundedly
rational, meaning they are goal-oriented but hampered by their cognitive abilities to process
stimuli (Simon 1985). To overcome these limitations, actors simplify the world through hierarchical
belief systems consisting of normative deep core beliefs, subsystem specic policy core beliefs, and
narrow secondary beliefs (Putnam 1976; Peey and Hurwitz 1985; see Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith
1999: 133). These belief systems are used as heuristics to lter and interpret stimuli (Lord et al.
1979; Munro et al. 1997; Munro et al. 2002). Furthermore, the ACF borrows from prospect theory
to assume that actors remember losses more than gains (Quattrone and Tversky 1988). The
result is what the ACF calls the devil shift, which is the tendency for individuals to exaggerate
both the power and maliciousness of their opponents (Sabatier et al. 1987).
Subsystems are simplied by aggregating actors into one or more coalitions. Given the large number
and diversity of actors involved in subsystem aairs, there is a need to simplify while not overly dis-
torting reality. The ACF directs researchers toward aggregating actors into one or more coalitions.
These coalitions are dened by their shared policy core beliefs and coordination patterns.
Policies and programs incorporate implicit theories and assumptions reecting the translated beliefs of one
or more coalitions. Subsystems consist of boundedly rational actors working together in coalitions
toward shaping policy outputs and outcomes. Given the importance of beliefs systems, the ACF
Weible and Nohrstedt
126
assumes that policy outputs are merely the translations of beliefs of the winning coalition or
coalitions (Pressman and Wildavsky 1973).
Scientic and technical information is important for understanding subsystem aairs. Most subsystems
involve issues that are usually dicult to describe and explain in terms of problem seriousness,
causes, and potential impacts of proposals. Scientic and technical information, thus, becomes
an important resource for coalition members for a variety of uses from argumentation with
opponents to the mobilization of supporters.
Researchers should adopt a longterm time perspective (e.g, of 10 years or more) to understand policy
processes and change. Policy process research is largely the study of public policy over time. The ACF
recommends that researchers examine their phenomenon as a point in the ongoing develop-
ment of the policy subsystem. Part of the rationale for taking a long-term perspective is to allow
for ample time to evaluate the outcomes of any policy decision, to assess political reactions, and
to study learning within and between coalitions.
Scope
A framework should provide a scope of inquiry for guiding scholars toward a shared research
agenda. The traditional foci of the ACF are descriptions and explanations of advocacy coalitions,
learning within and among coalition allies and opponents, and policy change. These emphases
should be viewed as general categories for both research inquiry and theory development.
Certainly other areas of research are permitted and have been conducted (e.g. Montpetit 2011;
Shanahan et al. 2011).
General conceptual categories and relations
A framework provides a common vocabulary including the major conceptual categories and
general relations among them. Figure 10.1 shows the ACF ow diagram (adapted from Sabatier
and Weible 2007) featuring a policy subsystem with coalitions, their resources and beliefs, and
the policy outputs and outcomes. Policy subsystems are embedded in a broader political system
with relatively stable parameters and external events, where the latter is more prone to change
than the former.
For researchers wanting to apply the ACF, it is important to consider the following basic
concepts: (1) public policy topic that denes the subsystem; (2) actors who are involved in
subsystem aairs; (3) institutions (e.g. rules) that structure overall subsystem interactions and the
behaviors within particular venues; (4) relative stable parameters and external events; (5) inter-
dependencies with other subsystems; and, nally, (6) time to permit observations of coalition
behavior, learning, and policy change.
The next step is to articulate the theoretical emphases within the ACF. Theories serve dierent
functions than frameworks in a research program. Theories narrow the scope of inquiry, link con-
cepts usually in the form of expectations, propositions, or observable implications, and establish
rationales (causal mechanisms) that explain how concepts interrelate. There are three major theoretical
emphases of the ACF.
First theoretical emphasis: advocacy coalitions
The rst area of theoretical emphasis focuses on advocacy coalitions. Advocacy coalitions are
dened as groups of actors sharing policy core beliefs and coordinating their behavior in a non-
trivial manner. Advocacy coalitions emerge and persist because actors vary in their belief systems
The advocacy coalition framework
127
(e.g. normative values regarding a particular policy topic) and seek to form alliances to translate
their beliefs into actual policies before actors with dierent belief systems can do the same.
The ACF oers three reasons that permit subsystem actors to overcome threats to collective
action in mobilizing coalition activity (Zafonte and Sabatier 1998; Sabatier and Weible 2007: 197).
First, similar beliefs among coalition allies reduce transaction costs of coordination. Second, the
level of coordination varies with some actors engaging in weak coordination (modifying their
behavior to achieve shared goals or information exchange) and others in strong coordination (jointly
developing and executing action plans) (Fenger and Klok 2001). Third, in high conict situations,
the devil shift occurs when actors exacerbate the power and maliciousness of opponents. When
under the devil shift, coalition members will overestimate the threats from shared opponents and
the imposed costs of inaction.
Empirical research across subsystems and political systems have conrmed that policy subsystems
are regularly composed of one to ve advocacy coalitions ghting over resources, access to
venues, and inuence on the formation of public policy (Weible et al. 2009). Occasionally, these
coalitions interact competitively showing intervals, sometimes spanning decades, of one-upmanship.
In other situations a single, dominant coalition will largely control a subsystem for extended
periods of time over a largely nonexistent, inactive, or disorganized opposition. Key descriptive
questions regarding coalition formation and development include:
What is the structure of the networks and belief systems of advocacy coalition members?
How stable is coalition membership over time?
What is the role of dierent organizations within coalitions?
Figure 10.1 Flow diagram of the advocacy coalition framework
Source: Adapted from Sabatier and Weible (2007)
Weible and Nohrstedt
128
How much consensus is there among coalition members?
What are the patterns of coordination among subsystem actors?
What strategies and resources do coalitions use to achieve their policy goals?
Within the scope of the emphasis on coalitions are also a set of explanatory questions addressing
the formation of coalitions and the interaction and behavior of coalition members:
Why do coalitions form?
How do coalition members overcome threats to collective action?
Why do coalition allies negotiate with opponents?
These questions are usually pursued in the form of testing and developing hypotheses. The most
important hypotheses aiming at the composition and development of advocacy coalition include:
Hyphothesis 1 On major controversies within a policy subsystem when policy core beliefs
are in dispute, the lineup of allies and opponents tends to be rather stable
over periods of a decade or so.
Hypothesis 2 Actors within an advocacy coalition will show substantial consensus on issues
pertaining to the policy core beliefs, although less so on secondary aspects.
Hypothesis 3 An actor (or coalition) will give up secondary aspects of his or her (its) belief
system before acknowledging weaknesses in the policy core beliefs.
Hypothesis 4 Within a coalition, administrative agencies will usually advocate more moderate
positions than their interest group allies.
Hypothesis 5 Elites of purposive groups are more constrained in their expression of beliefs
and policy positions than elites from material groups.
(Sabatier and Weible 2007: 220)
Hypotheses 15 specify some of the fundamental components of the ACF, including the
hierarchy and stability of belief systems and the distinction between dierent types of organi-
zations. Important contributions in the study of coordination networks and belief stability and
change within coalitions can be found in Jenkins-Smith et al. (1991), Zafonte and Sabatier (1998),
Weible and Sabatier (2005), Weible (2005), Ingold (2011), Henry et al. (2010), Henry (2011), Matti
and Sandström (2011), and Pierce (2011). Previous empirical research provides mixed results
regarding these hypotheses by showing patterns of both stability and defection of coalition
members over time (Jenkins-Smith and St. Clair 1993; Jenkins-Smith et al. 1991; Sabatier and
Brasher 1993; Zafonte and Sabatier 2004; Andersson 1999; Munro 1993).
While coalition resources have been a regular feature within the ACF since its inception
(Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith, 1993: 29), Sabatier and Weible (2007: 201-4) and Weible (2007)
placed more emphasis on the area by oering a typology of coalition resources: (1) formal legal
authority to make policy decisions; (2) public opinion; (3) information; (4) mobilizable troops;
(5) nancial resources; and (6) skillful leadership. The access and use of these resources is theoretically
argued to be important for forming and maintaining coalitions and for policy change. However,
the empirical investigation of coalition resources has only recently been examined by scholars
(Nohrstedt 2011; Ingold 2011; Albright, 2011).
The formation and stability of advocacy coalitions over time and their political behavior is
conditioned by subsystem institutions and events outside the control of subsystem actors. The
most important institutional factors that constrain subsystem actors are rst, the openness of the
political system and second, norms of consensus, which aect the level of inclusiveness of
The advocacy coalition framework
129
coalitions, exchange of information across coalition boundaries, and access to policy venues
(Sabatier and Weible 2007). Institutions shape the level of coordination within a coalition, pri-
marily by setting legal impediments that constrain formation of formal alliances paving the way
for weaker forms of coordination as a viable political strategy (Zafonte and Sabatier 1998;
Fenger and Klok 2001; Nohrstedt 2010). Events are likely to aect coalition behavior, parti-
cularly by providing opportunities for exploitation of new resources (including mobilization of
new coalition members) and strategy in terms of venue exploitation.
Second theoretical emphasis: policy-oriented learning
Learning has been a central focus of the ACF since its inception (Sabatier 1988). Policy-oriented
learning is dened as enduring alterations of thought or behavioral intentions that result from
experience and which are concerned with the attainment or revision of the precepts of the
belief system of individuals or of collectives (Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith 1993: 4256). To
study policy-oriented learning is to study changes in belief system components of coalition
members over time. Policy-oriented learning may entail better understanding of political goals,
the causal relationship among key factors in the subsystem, and eective strategic behaviors,
especially as used in analytic debates.
Important descriptive questions that guide inquiry into learning are the following:
What belief system components are changing through learning?
To what extent is one coalition learning more than another coalition?
Explanatory questions deal with issues of when, why, and how actors learn within and between
coalitions and include:
What contexts and events foster learning by coalition members?
How does learning diuse among allies within a coalition?
What contexts and events foster learning by brokers?
To what extent, if at all, does a broker facilitate learning between coalitions?
Why does learning occur, if at all, between some members of opposing coalitions and not
others?
On the whole, the intent of the ACFs focus on policy-oriented learning is to understand and
explain what constitutes learning and why learning occurs within coalitions and between coa-
litions. Four general factors are important for explaining policy-oriented learning. The rst
involves the attributes of professional forums (see Jenkins-Smith 1990). Professional forums are
venues of discussion involving subsystem actors. Forums are structured by dierent sets of
institutional arrangements. Some forums are structured by open participation rules (open forum)
and others by closed participation rules (closed forum). Professional forums are based on common
analytical training and norms and are postulated to increase the likelihood for learning between
coalitions (ibid.).
The second variable conditioning learning is the level of conict between coalitions (Jenkins-
Smith 1990; Weible 2008). The expectation is that there is an inverted quadratic relationship
between conict and cross-coalition learning. On one extreme at low levels of conict, there is
little cross-coalition learning as the opposing coalitions place their attention on other, more
pressing issues. On the other extreme at high levels of conict, there is also little cross-coalition
learning as opposing coalitions are motivated to defend their positions and refute claims by their
Weible and Nohrstedt
130
opponents. The conditions most conducive for cross-coalition learning would then be inter-
mediate levels of conict where there is enough of a threat to attract the attention of rivals but
not too much of a threat to entrench opponents in rigid policy positions.
The third variable is attributes of the stimuli or data prompting learning. The stimuli can
come from many dierent sources including scientic and technical information, actors, and
events. One important attribute of stimuli relates to the level of analytical tractability of the
phenomenon (Jenkins-Smith 1990: 979). Subsystems with highly intractable issues are marked
by uncertainty and high levels of disagreement about the scientic and technical aspects of the
issue (e.g. about the quality of the data or theories used). In general, highly intractable issues are
expected to be associated with lower levels of cross-coalition learning.
The fourth variable that conditions learning involves attributes of individuals, including belief
systems, resources, and network contacts. Are actors with extreme beliefs less likely to learn
from their opponents than actors with moderate beliefs? Are some actors more or less supported
by their analytical training in learning than others? Are actors with network contactseither
within their coalitions or with opposing coalitionsmore likely to learn?
Central to the arguments about cross-coalition learning is a certain type of individual: the
policy brokers. Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith (1993: 27) dene brokers as a category of actors
whose dominant concerns are keeping with the level of political conict within acceptable
limits and reaching some reasonable solution to the problem. Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith argue
that identifying brokers is an empirical question and is not dependent upon organizational
aliation. These broker may learn, possibly prior to the coalitions, and then facilitate cross-coalition
learning later in the process (Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith 1993: 21819).
Given the research questions and categories above, the theoretical emphasis on policy-oriented
learning within the ACF is built into ve hypotheses:
Hypothesis 1 Policy-oriented learning across belief systems is most likely when there is an
intermediate level of informed conict between the two coalitions. This
requires that: (a) each have the technical resources to engage in such a debate;
and that (b) the conict be between secondary aspects of one belief system and
core elements of the other or, alternatively, between important secondary
aspects of the two belief systems.
Hypothesis 2 Policy-oriented learning across belief systems is most likely when there exists
a forum which is: (a) prestigious enough to force professionals from dierent
coalitions to participate; and (b) dominated by professional norms.
Hypothesis 3 Problems for which accepted quantitative data and theory exist are more
conducive to policy-oriented learning across belief systems than those in which
data and theory are generally qualitative, quite subjective, or altogether lacking.
Hypothesis 4 Problems involving natural systems are more conducive to policy-oriented
learning across belief systems than those involving purely social or political
systems because in the former many of the critical variables are not themselves
active strategists and because controlled experimentation is more feasible.
Hypothesis 5 Even when the accumulation of technical information does not change the
views of the opposing coalition, it can have important impacts on policy at
least in the short run by altering the views of policy brokers.
A review of ACF applications in Weible et al. (2009) indicates that, of the ve learning
hypotheses, the rst two have been tested the most and the last two the least. From this review,
they found evidence suggesting that learning within coalitions reinforces beliefs and mixed
The advocacy coalition framework
131
results about the likelihood of cross-coalition learning. For example, Larsen et al. (2006) nd
that cross-coalition learning occurs at the secondary level of belief systems (as expected) but also
at the policy-core level (not expected). Similar mixed results can be found with the measure-
ment and ndings involving professional forums. If there is any area within the ACF needing
more attention at both the theoretical and operational levels, it is policy-oriented learning.
Third theoretical emphasis: policy change
The third theoretical emphasis in the ACF involves policy change. The ACF assumes that policies
are translations of beliefs and can be conceptualized and measured hierarchically like belief sys-
tems. Policy components that span, and are salient to, a policy subsystem represent the policy
core aspects of the subsystem. Policy components that deal with only a part of a subsystem or
technical components of a policy represent secondary aspects of the subsystem. A change in policy
core aspects indicates a major change in the direction of the subsystem and is dened as major
policy change. A change in secondary aspects indicates a minor change in the subsystem and is
dened as minor policy change (Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith 1999: 1478).
The descriptive questions in the study of policy change include:
To what extent does major and minor policy change occur within the subsystem over time?
What is the content of minor and/or major policy change?
Explanatory questions on the topic of policy change are several:
Why do some events and contexts lead to minor and major policy change?
What are the mechanisms linking internal and external events to minor and major policy
change?
How do negotiated agreements lead to policy change?
When does policy-oriented learning lead to policy change?
As reected in these questions, the ACF species four pathways to policy change (Sabatier and
Weible 2007). The rst two paths involve events either external or internal to the policy sub-
system. External events occur outside the territorial boundaries of the subsystem and/or the
topical policy boundaries of the subsystem and are, hence, largely outside the control of sub-
system actors. Internal events occur inside the territorial and/or the topical area of the policy
subsystem and are more likely aected by subsystem actors. The two types of events dier in their
eect on coalition behavior and policy change. Most importantly, attribution of blame or suc-
cess is higher after internal subsystem events are compared to after external subsystem events (see
Nohrstedt and Weible 2010).
Policy-oriented learning is the third path and is said to lead to policy change through altering
the beliefs of coalition members. Policies may change after a dominant coalition learns or after
learning occurs between adversarial coalitions.
The fourth path is said to occur through negotiated agreements. Sabatier and Weible (2007:
2056) describe nine prescriptions fostering negotiation between coalitions and then policy
change. These nine prescriptions include: a hurting stalemate, broad representation, leadership,
consensus, funding, commitment by actors, importance of empirical issues, trust, and lack of alter-
native venues. From this list, the most important for instigating negotiations between coalitions
is a hurting stalemate. A hurting stalemate occurs when both coalitions view the status quo as
unacceptable and do not have access to alternative venues for achieving their objectives.
Weible and Nohrstedt
132
The original version of the ACF oered two hypotheses involving major policy change:
Hypothesis 1 Signicant perturbations external to the subsystem are a necessary, but not sucient,
cause of change in the policy core attributes of a governmental program.
Hypothesis 2 The policy core attributes of a governmental program in a specic jurisdiction
will not be signicantly revised as long as the subsystem advocacy coalition
that instituted the program remains in power within that jurisdictionexcept
when the change is imposed by a hierarchically superior jurisdiction.
These two hypotheses for policy change have existed since the original version (Sabatier
1987, 1988). After the introduction of the other paths to policy change in 2007, new hypotheses
were not added to encompass this expansion in logic. To better reect the theoretical arguments
c. 2007, a revised Hypothesis 1 would read as follows:
Hypothesis 1 Signicant perturbations external to the subsystem, a signicant perturbation
internal to the subsystem, policy-oriented learning, negotiated agreement, or
some combination thereof are necessary, but not sucient, cause of change in
the policy core attributes of a governmental program.
The underlying logic of the ACF suggests that none of the four paths are necessary and su-
cient to produce policy change. Thus, one underdeveloped area within the ACF is the expla-
nation that traces any path or combination of paths from its occurrence to policy change or
stasis. This research should center on one or more exploitive coalitions that seek to capitalize on
the opportunity aorded by one of the paths. But how a coalition will exploit an opportunity is
largely unknown from a theoretical perspective, with notable explorations into the topic taken
by Smith (2000), Ameringer (2002), Albright (2011), Ingold (2011), and Nohrstedt (2005, 2008,
2010, 2011). Developing knowledge in understanding the links from one or more of the four
paths to policy change will most likely involve the analysis of how resources are redistributed
between coalitions within the subsystem. It is likely, for example, that external events or internal
events or even learning might alter the distribution of resources or how those resources are used
leading to a more empowered coalition. Another theoretical area open for inquiry is the inter-
dependencies of the four paths or multiple occurrences within the same path. For example,
when do multiple external or internal events lead to learning and possibly negotiated agree-
ments among adversarial coalitions? Similarly, when do a number of events occurring over time
accumulate into sucient momentum for a coalition to capitalize to produce major policy change
(Smith 2000)? Finally, the role and behavior of dominant coalition actors in processes leading to
policy change must be claried (Nohrstedt 2010: 23). Under what conditions do dominant
coalition members promote stability and defend the status quo and when do they seek change?
What approaches to policy change (reformist or conservative) do dominant coalitions take fol-
lowing external and internal events and why? By denition, dominant coalition members
control key political resourcesprimarily formal legal authorityand thereby policy programs
(Nohrstedt 2011). Therefore, understanding the motivations of dominant coalition actors is an
important avenue for future research.
Conclusions
The ACF has continued for a quarter of a century and has made progress in understanding and
explaining policy processes across the globe. The theoretical emphasis in the ACF reects the
The advocacy coalition framework
133
specialization among people applying the framework as well as natural partitions of the hypotheses.
Clearly, the hypotheses are overlapping. Whereas a theoretical emphasis on the structure and
stability of networks and beliefs might be the dependent variable for one study about coalitions,
changes in coalition structure and stability might be the independent variable for another study
about policy change (Weible et al. 2011). Researchers should not view the theoretical emphases
as sharply distinct but rather as signifying helpful partitions that permit specialized inquiry into
questions about coalitions, learning, and policy change.
Among the next steps in applying the ACF is to continue to develop the theoretical descriptions
and explanations within each of these areas of emphases as well as to develop other unexplored
areas within the framework. It is quite possible, for example, that there is another theoretical
emphasis centered on the role of scientic and technical information and scientists in policy
subsystems (Jenkins-Smith 1990; Weible 2008; Montpetit 2011). Policy narratives are another
area that oers opportunities for theoretical growth based in part on the ACF (Shanahan et al.
2011). Scholars can also develop better theoretical understanding about how specic concepts
or categories of concepts interrelate within the framework; for example, the role of political
opportunity structures (Sabatier 1998; Kübler 2001). Most importantly, the ACF is increasingly
serving as a framework for guiding researchers from around the world in conducting compara-
tive public policy analysis. As such, what is needed is a clearer articulation of how subsystems
operate in dierent political systems and political cultures. One likely approach for international
comparisons is, rst, to focus on political system dierences (e.g. the continuum from corporatism
to pluralism) and, second, to compare and contrast subsystem institutions (e.g. subsystem specic
rules and norms) and their eects on coalition formation, policy learning and change.
Given the continued and growing momentum of the ACF research program, this eort must
ask the question: to what end? The immediate objective of the ACF is a better understanding
and explanation of policy processes. Such knowledge serves academia in research and teaching.
Another tradition in public policy is the service to society outside the networks of academics. In
this context, extant approaches for this aspiration can be found in various forms of engaged scho-
larship (Van de Ven 2008), advocacy, and direct service. For scholars applying the ACF and
seeking practical benets, one question should be how the framework can be used for theoretically-
guided research toward academic ends and as a tool in providing advice to subsystem actors
toward better societal outcomes.
Note
1 See Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith (1993) for a thorough description of the frameworks underpinnings.
Additionally, readers interested in gaining a deeper understanding of the ACF are encouraged to read
Sabatier (1987, 1988, 1998), Jenkins-Smith (1990), Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith (1999), Sabatier and
Weible (2007), Weible et al. (2009), and Weible et al. (2011).
Bibliography
Ajzen, Icek and Martin Fishbein. 1980. Understanding Attitudes and Predicting Social Behavior. Englewood
Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Albright, Elizabeth A. 2011. Policy change and learning in response to extreme ood events in Hungary:
An advocacy coalition approach, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 484511.
Ameringer, Carl F. 2002. Federal antitrust policy and physician discontent: Dening moments in the
struggle for congressional relief, Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 27(4): 54374.
Andersson, Magnus. 1999. Change and Continuity in Polands Environmental Policy. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Dawson, Richard and James Robinson. 1963. Interplay competition, economic variables, and welfare
policies in the American states, Journal of Politics 25 (May): 26589.
Weible and Nohrstedt
134
Easton, David. 1965. A Framework for Political Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fenger, Menno and Pieter-Jan Klok. 2001. Interdependency, beliefs, and coalition behavior: A contribution
to the advocacy coalition framework, Policy Sciences 34: 15770.
Freeman, J. Leiper. 1955. The Political Process. New York: Random House.
Grith, Ernest. 1939. The Impasse of Democracy. New York: Harrison Hilton Books.
Heclo, Hugh. 1974. Social Policy in Britain and Sweden. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
—— 1978. Issue networks and the executive establishment, in Anthony King (ed.) The New American
Political System. Washington, DC: AEI.
Henry, Adam. 2011. Power, ideology, and policy network cohesion in regional planning, Policy Studies
Journal 39(3): 36183.
——, Mark Lubell and Michael McCoy. 2010. Belief systems and social capital as drivers of policy network
structure: The case of California regional planning, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
21(3); 41944.
Herron, Kerry G. and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith. 2006. Critical Masses and Critical Choices: Evolving Public
Opinion on Nuclear Weapons, Terrorism, and Security. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Hirschi, Christian and Thomas Widmer. 2010. Policy change and policy stasis: Comparing Swiss foreign
policy toward South Africa (196894) and Iraq (199091) , Policy Studies Journal 38(3): 53763.
Hjern, Benny and David Porter. 1981. Implementation structures: A new unit of administrative analysis,
Organizational Studies 2: 21127.
Hurwitz, Jon and Mark Peey. 1987. How are foreign policy attitudes structured? A hierarchical model,
American Political Science Review 81: 1099120.
Ingold, Karin. 2011. Network structures within policy processes: Coalitions, power and brokerage in
Swiss climate policy, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 43459.
Jenkins-Smith,
Hank. 1990. Democratic Politics
and Policy Analysis. Pacic Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.
——and Gilbert St. Clair. 1993. The politics of oshore energy: Empirically testing the advocacy coali-
tion framework, in Paul Sabatier and Hank Jenkins-Smith (eds) Policy Change and Learning. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press, 14975.
——, Gilbert St. Clair and Brian Woods. 1991. Explaining change in policy subsystems: Analysis of coalition
stability and defection over time, American Journal of Political Science 35 (November): 85172.
Kübler, Daniel. 2001. Understanding policy change with the advocacy coalition framework: An application
to Swiss drug policy, Journal of European Public Policy 8(4): 62341.
Larsen, Jakob Bjerg, Karsten Vrangbaek and Janine M. Traulsen. 2006. Advocacy coalitions and pharmacy
policy in Denmark, Social Science and Medicine 63(1): 21224.
Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientic Growth. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Lerner, Daniel and Harold D. Lasswell (eds). 1951. The Policy Sciences. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Lindblom, Charles E. 1959. The science of muddling through, Public Administrative Review 59: 7888.
Lord, Charles, Lee Ross and Mark Lepper. 1979. Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The eects
of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37:
2098109.
Matti, Simon and Annica Sandström. 2011. The rationale determining advocacy coalitions: Examining
coordination networks and corresponding beliefs, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 385410.
Mazmanian, Daniel and Paul Sabatier. 1981. Implementation and Public Policy. Lanham, MD: University
Press of America.
Mazur, Allan. 1981. The Dynamics of Technical Controversy. Washington DC: Communications Press.
Montpetit, Eric. 2011. Scientic
credibility, disagreement, and error costs in 17 biotechnology policy
subsystems, Policy Studies Journal 39(3):
51333.
Munro, John. 1993. California water politics: Explaining change in a cognitively polarized subsystem,in
Paul Sabatier and Hank Jenkins-Smith (eds) Policy Change and Learning. Boulder, CO: Westview Press,
10528.
Munro, Georey D. and Peter H. Ditto. 1997. Biased assimilation, attitude polarization, and aect in
reactions to stereotype-relevant scientic information, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 23(6):
63653.
——, Peter H. Ditto, Lisa K. Lockhart, Angela Fagerlin, Mitchell Gready and Elizabeth Peterson. 2002.
Biased assimilation of sociopolitical arguments: Evaluating the 1996 US Presidential debate, Basic and
Applied Social Psychology 24(1): 1526.
The advocacy coalition framework
135
Nohrstedt, Daniel. 2005. External shocks and policy change: Three Mile Island and Swedish nuclear
energy policy, Journal of European Public Policy 12(6): 104159.
—— 2008. The politics of crisis policymaking: Chernobyl and Swedish nuclear energy policy, Policy
Studies Journal 36(2): 25778.
—— 2010. Do advocacy coalitions matter? Crisis and change in Swedish nuclear energy policy, Journal of
Public Administration Research and Theory 20: 30933.
—— 2011. Shifting resources and venues producing policy change in contested subsystems: A case study
of Swedish signals intelligence policy, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 46184.
——and Christopher M. Weible. 2010. The logic of policy change after crisis: Proximity and subsystem
interaction, Risks, Hazards, and Crisis in Public Policy 1(2): 132.
Ostrom, Elinor. 2005. Understanding Institutional Diversity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Peey, Mark and Jon Hurwitz. 1985. A hierarchical model of attitude constraint, American Journal of
Political Science 29: 87190.
Pierce, Jonathan J. 2011. Coalition stability and belief change: Advocacy coalitions in US foreign policy
and the creation of Israel, 192244, Policy Studies Journal 41134.
Pressman, Jerey and Aaron Wildavsky. 1973. Implementation. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Putnam, Robert. 1976. The Comparative Study of Political Elites. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Quattrone, George A. and Amos Tversky. 1988. Contrasting rational and psychological analysis of political
choice, American Political Science Review 82: 71936.
Ranney,
Austin. 1968. Political Science
and Public Policy. New York: Markham.
Sabatier, Paul, A. 1987. Knowledge, policy-oriented learning, and policy change: An advocacy coalition
framework, Knowledge: Creation, Diusion, Utilization 8(4): 64992.
—— 1988. An advocacy coalition model of policy change and the role of policy-oriented learning
therein, Policy Sciences 21 (autumn): 12968.
—— 1991. Toward better theories of the policy process, PS: Political Science and Politics 24(2): 14756.
—— 1998. The advocacy coalition framework: revisions and relevance for Europe, Journal of European
Public Policy 5 (March): 98130.
—— 1999. The need for better theories,inTheories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 317.
—— 2007. Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——and Anne M. Brasher. 1993. From vague consensus to clearly dierentiated coalitions: environmental
policy at Lake Tahoe, 19641985, in Paul Sabatier and Hank Jenkins-Smith (eds) Policy Change and
Learning. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 177208.
——and Hank C. Jenkins-Smith. 1993. Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition Approach.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——and Hank Jenkins-Smith. 1999. The advocacy coalition framework: An assessment, in Paul Sabatier
(ed.) Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 11768.
——and Christopher M. Weible. 2007. The advocacy coalition framework: Innovations and clarications,
in
Paul Sabatier (ed.)Theories
of the Policy Process, 2nd edn. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 189222.
——and Matthew Zafonte. 2001. Policy knowledge, advocacy organizations, in Neil J. Smelser and Paul
B. Baltes (eds) International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences 17. Oxford: Pergamon Press,
1156368.
——, Susan Hunter and Susan McLaughlin. 1987. The devil shift: Perceptions and misperceptions of
opponents, Western Political Quarterly 40: 5173.
Schlager, Edella. 1995. Policy making and collective action: Dening coalitions within the advocacy
coalition framework, Policy Sciences 28: 24370.
Shanahan, Elizabeth, Michael D. Jones and Mark K. McBeth. 2011. Policy narratives and policy processes,
Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 53561.
Simon, Herbert A. 1957. Models of Man: Social and Rational. New York: John Wiley.
—— 1985. Human nature in politics: The dialogue of psychology with political science, American Political
Science Review 79 (June): 293304.
Smith, Adrian. 2000. Policy networks and advocacy coalitions: Explaining policy change and stability in
UK industrial pollution policy? Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy 18: 95114.
Van de Ven, Andrew H. 2008. Engaged Scholarship: A Guide for Organizational and Social Research. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Walker, Jack, L. 1969. The diusion and innovation among the American states, The American Political
Science Review 63(3): 88099.
Weible and Nohrstedt
136
Weible, C.M. 2005. Beliefs and perceived inuence in a natural resource conict: an advocacy coalition
approach to policy networks, Political Research Quarterly 58(3): 461 75.
—— 2007. An advocacy coalition framework approach to stakeholder analysis: understanding the political
context of California marine protected area policy, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 17:
95117.
—— 2008. Expert-based information and policy subsystems: A Review and synthesis, Policy Studies
Journal 36(4): 61535.
——and Paul A. Sabatier. 2005. Comparing policy networks: Marine protected areas in California, Policy
Studies Journal 33(2): 181204.
——, Paul A. Sabatier and Kelly McQueen. 2009. Themes and variations: Taking stock of the advocacy
coalition framework, Policy Studies Journal 37(1): 12140.
——, Paul A. Sabatier, Hank C. Jenkins-Smith, Daniel Nohrstedt and Adam Douglas Henry. 2011. A
quarter century of the advocacy coalition framework: An introduction to the special issue, Policy Studies
Journal 39(3): 34960.
Weiss, Carol. 1977. Research for policys sake: The enlightenment function of social research, Policy
Analysis 3 (autumn): 53145.
Zafonte, Matthew and Paul A. Sabatier. 1998. Shared beliefs and imposed interdependencies as determinants
of ally networks in overlapping subsystems, Journal of Theoretical Politics 10 (4): 473505.
——and Paul A. Sabatier. 2004. Short-term versus long-term coalitions in the policy process: Automotive
pollution control, 196389, The
Policy Studies Journal 32(1): 75107.
The advocacy coalition framework
137
11
The punctuated equilibrium
theory of agenda-setting
and policy change
Graeme Boushey
Introduction
On March 23, 2010, President Barack Obama signed into law the Patient Protection and
Aordable Care Act (PPACA), marking a major shift in the organization and structure of health
care in the United States. The statute outlined a series of dramatic reforms to the provision,
funding and regulation of public and private health insurance, controversially requiring that all
Americans carry qualifying health coverage, directing state governments to regulate new health
insurance exchanges, expanding the coverage of poor and uninsured children, and designating a
comparative eectiveness research institute to track the eectiveness of preventative and clinical
public health (Kaiser Family Foundation 2010).
1
Although there is currently considerable uncer-
tainty regarding the future implementation of the health care reforms, the passage of the act is
nonetheless remarkable in the size and scope of policy change. The PPACA has triggered sig-
nicant policy-making attention across the legal, executive, and legislative branches of both the
state and federal governments. If the statute survives the current legal challenges, the PPACA
will radically alter the US health care system.
The sweeping policy reform highlights a familiar puzzle to students of the punctuated equi-
librium theory (PET) in public policy-making. Public policy change is typically characterized by
tremendous stability, as broad policy change usually faces considerable political and institutional
barriers. Yet policy change can occur through sweeping positive feedback cycles as radical new
innovations are adopted in a relatively short time frame.
2
Most changes in US health policy have
occurred through incremental adjustment, as Congress approved modest reforms to national and
state programs. However, at key moments national policy-making attention has focused squarely
on the problem of underinsurance, leading to sweeping policy reforms such as the Medicare and
Medicaid programs, the expansion of the Medicare prescription drug benet, and most recently
the passage of the PPACA. Viewed over time, public policy-making is characterized by punctuated
dynamics.
As a policy process model, punctuated equilibrium theory documents how shifts in macro poli-
tical attention result in both negative and positive feedback cycles in policy-making. Negative feedback
cycles emerge as a result of the delegation of routine policy-making to policy subgovernments, as
138
a core group of institutional actors make marginal adjustments to policy in response to a dominant
policy image. Positive feedback cycles result when mass political attention focuses system-wide
attention on a new dimension of a policy problem. When this occurs, policy change occurs
rapidly as new political actors and new jurisdictions become involved in policy-making.
These distinct patterns of incremental and non-incremental policy change result from the dis-
proportionate allocation of issue attention in public policy-making (Baumgartner and Jones 2009;
Jones and Baumgartner 2005). Governments have limited agenda space but face thousands of
competing policy problems annually (Baumgartner and Jones 2009; Jones and Baumgartner
2005). Because mass political attention is rarely focused on a single issue, policy-making is
generally delegated to policy subgovernments, where actors within political institutions work to
manage an overwhelming supply of information demanding political action. When system-wide
political attention is focused on a single issue, the pressures reinforcing equilibrium in a policy
subsystem are ruptured, leading to broad political change.
To understand forces leading to both policy stability and rapid change in a single political
system, punctuated equilibrium theory approaches the study of public policy longitudinally by
exploring how focusing events, institutional venues, policy ideas and policy entrepreneurs interact
to produce policy change. The allocation of government attention is unpredictable, yet PET
identies systematic processes that lead to the dynamic processes of policy change over time
through the study of comparative issue dynamics across institutional and historical contexts.
This chapter provides an overview of the theory and methods of the punctuated equilibrium
theory of public policy. The chapter begins with a review of the decision-making model under-
lying punctuated equilibrium theory, explaining how pressures facing individual and institu-
tional decision-making precipitate punctuated dynamics in agenda setting. The chapter then focuses
on PET as a policy process model, reviewing how focusing events, policy ideas, institutional
venues and interest groups interact to produce both stability and sudden policy change over time.
The chapter concludes with a review of recent methodological advances in comparative policy
dynamics, highlighting major empirical and methodological ndings as PET has evolved as a
general model of policy-making across historical and institutional contexts. With these factors
working together, the review points to a number of new opportunities for evaluating the causes
of punctuated dynamics in public policy-making.
Negative feedback cycles and policy incrementalism
3
Models of political decision-making begin with an important observation about the demands of
information processing in public policy-making. Political actors are constrained by a scarcity of
time, resources and political attention. Because political decision-makers must address a multi-
tude of dierent issues on a daily basisnegotiating budget appropriations, designing regulatory
policy, sitting in hearings and attending to caseworkdecision-makers cannot dedicate the time
and resources needed to engage in a comprehensive solution search for each and every policy
problem (Lindblom 1959; Hayes 1992).
The challenges presented by the sheer volume of issues demanding political attention are
compounded by the complexity of emerging public policy problems (Workman et al. 2009).
Policy problems are multidimensional, and policy-makers are challenged by considerable uncer-
tainty regarding the appropriate solutions and potential outcomes of new policy interventions.
For example, policy-makers faced with growing concern over about air pollution must consider
dicult trade-os between protecting population health, protecting the environment, and pro-
viding for the continued competitiveness of industry. The development of appropriate regula-
tions are further complicated when the costs and expected outcomes of regulatory intervention
Punctuated equilibrium theory
139
are unknown. Policy-makers face considerable challenges when problems are complex, solutions
are costly, and outcomes are uncertain.
To compensate, policy-makers engage in incremental decision-making, limiting solution
searchers to a small set of local alternatives and making small adjustments to existing policy regimes
(Lindblom 1959; Wildavsky 1964). This implies a conservative approach to policy-making, as
risk-averse policy-makers make gradual changes to existing policies through successive limited
comparison rather than risking large-scale policy failure (Lindblom 1959; Robinson 2006). For
example, when faced with the considerable uncertainty of the consequences of new air quality
regulations, policymakers may prefer to make minor adjustments to the existing policysuch as
adopting slightly more stringent energy eciency standards for cars or manufacturersrather
than advocating for a large-scale change such as a cap and trade system for greenhouse gas emissions.
This approach has the advantage of reducing the uncertainty regarding the cost and ecacy of
policy change. In this regard, incremental decision-making can resemble path dependency
theory, as policy and solutions become locked in over time (Robinson and Meier 2006).
Institutions and negative feedback cycles
The tendency toward incremental decision-making is reinforced by policy-making institutions,
which help decision-makers organize information, set agenda priorities, develop solutions, and
choose among alternatives. In political institutions, policy-making is generally delegated to policy
subsystems, specialized policy-making jurisdictions charged with the development of public
policy within a specic issue area.
The delegation of policy-making to subgovernments helps to overcome the challenges pre-
sented by oversupply of information by facilitating parallel processing where dierent subgovern-
ments address multiple, diverse issues simultaneously (Workman et al. 2009: 79). In the United
States, policy-making in Congress is channeled through the committee system, a series of specia-
lized subgovernments charged with policy development across specic issue areas. The committee
system reduces the problem of information oversupply by committees acting as gatekeepers,
selectively ltering information for the larger legislative body.
The organization of policy-making institutions reinforces the bias toward incremental policy-
making by imposing strict decision costs on policy-making that pressure against sudden policy
change (Workman et al. 2009). Deliberative bodies may have supermajority requirements to
enact certain forms of legislation, or require multiple legislative bodies to approve policy prior
to enactment. Broad policy change is therefore generally dicult to achieve, as it requires the
coordination and cooperation of multiple veto players with distinct preferences across policy-
making institutions (Tsebelis 2002). Actors face considerably less opposition at the subgovernment
level, where policy-making occurs through marginal, consensual adjustment to prior policy regimes.
Negative feedback in public policy-making is maintained by the stability of participants
engaged in policy subsystems. When policy subsystems are dominated by a speci c interest in
the policy process, policy-making is dictated by a policy monopoly, a narrow coalition of elected
ocials, bureaucrats and interest group representatives controlling the legislative agenda at the
subgovernment level (Baumgartner and Jones 2009; True et al. 2007).
4
As beneciaries from the
status quo, these policy monopolies have little incentive to undertake radical reforms in policy-
making. Instead, policy monopolies oset outside calls for reform and policy change by making
minor or supercial adjustments to policy, allowing the subsystem to appear responsive without
radically adjusting public policy.
For example, faced with the challenge of conserving natural resources and energy in the United
States, the Senate Committee on Energy and Natural Resources has historically recommended
Boushey
140
increasing the fuel eciency of automobiles and heavy trucks, and consistently working to reduce
the nations energy dependence by regulating the fuel consumption of passenger vehicles. By
making minor adjustments to vehicle fuel eciency, policy-makers incrementally move toward
the overall goal of energy conservation while simultaneously reducing the uncertainty of new
policy for industry, consumers and government. Such incremental adjustments prevail at a sub-
system level where constraints on attention and information demand that policy-makers routinely
focus on limited alternatives in developing new solutions.
Finally, negative feedback cycles dominate in policy subsystems because of the relative stabi-
lity of the policy image the collective understanding and ideas regarding the problems and issues
at stake (Baumgartner and Jones 2009; Walgrave and Varone 2008). Although policy problems
are complex and multidimensional, decision-makers operating within a policy monopoly tend
to focus only on specic dimensions of a public policy problem. Within a policy monopoly there is
little disagreement over the nature of the policy problem. Without change in the monopoly
dynamic, policy solutions become routine over time, and policy though subsystem-level responses
to well-dened policy problems become repetitive. For much of recent history, energy and
natural resources have largely been understood as a problem of conservation and eciency.
Government has focused largely on regulating the individual consumption of oil through speed
limits, fuel eciency standards, and highway and infrastructure investment. These solutions all
respond to a common and widely shared understanding of the challenges of energy conservation.
The tremendous policy stability that typically explains policy-making results from the constraints
that individuals working within complex political institutions face as they address complex
policy problems. Policy-makers rarely have the time, resources or incentive to engage in craft-
ing radical new solutions to each and every policy problem. Even if an actor pushes for a radical
new program, they usually face institutional barriers that reroute toward gradual and consensual
policy adjustment.
Disproportionate information processing and positive feedback cycles
Policy change generally occurs gradually, but at other times issues explode onto the policy agenda,
leading to sweeping changes in public policy that cannot be explained neatly by conservative
incremental policy-making theory. These periods of policy disequilibrium result when a focus-
ing event directs system-wide attention onto a new salient dimension of a public policy issue,
elevating it to the forefront of the institutional and mass political agendas (Baumgartner and
Jones 2009; Jones and Baumgartner 2005; Kingdon 1984; Shattschneider 1975). When elevated
issue attention expands the scope of con ict to new jurisdictions, the policy monopolies that
sustained the prior equilibrium are destroyed as new participants introduce legislation responding
to the shift in governments understanding of the policy problem (Baumgartner and Jones 2009).
Sudden periods of agenda instability and policy disequilibrium are the result of positive feedback
cycles in public policy-making, as new pressures for policy change destabilize long-standing policy
regimes (Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
In recent years, punctuated equilibrium theory has extended the theory of bounded ration-
ality to model how individual and organizational choice can explain both incremental adjustment
and sudden shifts in policy regimes. Punctuated policy dynamics are the result of dispropor-
tionate information processing in public policy processes (Jones 2001; Jones and Baumgartner
2004, 2005; Workman et al. 2009). Decision-making is limited less by the supply of available
information and more by the scarcity of attention (Jones 1994: 87). The key insight is that
patterns of policy change result from the selective allocation of attention in decision-making.
Individuals pressed with the demands of making decisions across a multitude of issues reduce
Punctuated equilibrium theory
141
information costs through incremental decision-making; however, when a subset of issues
receives substantial political attention, it leads to more extensive problem representation and
solution search than is typical (Jones 2001). These attention shifts occur as individuals lter new
information, focusing attention squarely on decisions that elevate a sense of urgency, fear or
anxiety. While individuals may intend to make proportional, rational decisions that are appro-
priate for the problems they face, emotional cues often lead them to under-respond to some
pressures, and over-respond to others. Neither individuals nor institutions respond to information
and policy relevant signals equally (ibid.).
The bias toward incremental responses to routine problems contributes to disproportionate
information processing in decision-making. Because most problems are addressed through incre-
mental adjustment, people routinely fail to incorporate new policy-relevant information when
making daily decisions. When attention is squarely focused on an emerging policy problem, indi-
viduals then over-respond to new information as a wide range of new policy relevant infor-
mation is suddenly incorporated into choice (Jones and Baumgartner 2004). In this regard, the
status quo bias of incrementalism begets large shifts in attention exactly because it reinforces a
disjointed pattern of neglect and sudden response to information (Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
Individual preferences also shift suddenly in response to changes in the context of new policy-
relevant information. Although policy problems are multidimensional, decision-makers tend to
focus narrowly on a limited set of dimensions highlighted in the most immediate problem at
hand. As research in framing eects has demonstrated, preferences for policy can shift radically
depending on the specic contextual cues (Iyengar 1996; Jones 2001). Preferences may therefore
shift dramatically when policy-makers react to information that highlights a new and previously
overlooked component of a policy problem.
In focusing on the disproportionate allocation of individual attention, punctuated equilibrium
theory demonstrates that incrementalism is not the only mechanism of preference formation
and choice implied by bounded rationality. Shifts in individual attention can lead to dispropor-
tionate responses to new information. Rather than following a single path of incremental choice,
individuals instead often shift attention and preferences suddenly.
Positive feedback cycles and institutional choice
As with the pressures leading to negative feedback cycles, the processes leading to positive feedback
result from the interaction of individuals and institutions in public policy-making. Although the
organization of policy-making in the United States generally imposes a conservative pressure
against rapid policy change, policy entrepreneurs and interest group activists across national and
sub-national jurisdictions constantly pressure for new policy reform or innovation. When a new
idea or initiative takes hold and becomes legitimized across political venues, sudden shifts in
policy follow.
Punctuated equilibrium theory contends that the formalized process of agenda-setting and
political decision-making in political institutions amplies disproportionate information proces-
sing (Jones and Baumgartner 2004, 2005). Most policy issues are handled as routine develop-
ments and are delegated to policy subgovernments (Baumgartner and Jones 2009; True et al.
2006; Baumgartner and Jones 2002). However, at any given moment a small subset of issues
receives system-wide political attention. When this occurs, widespread participation of actors across
venues and the incorporation of new information can trigger rapid and extensive policy change
(Baumgartner and Jones 2009; True et al. 2007; Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
Studies of punctuated dynamics begin by identifying the factors leading to the shift in macro-
political attention preceding radical policy reforms. Elevated issue attention caused by a focusing
Boushey
142
event that galvanizes mass public and political attention can open a window of opportunity,
creating conditions for rapid and non-incremental policy change (Baumgartner and Jones 2009;
Birkland 1997; Kingdon 1984). Exogenous shocks work to suddenly galvanize mass political
attention on an issue area, revealing a critical policy problem that demands political interven-
tion. The tsunami leading to the Fukushima nuclear reactor meltdown in 2011 focused inter-
national political attention of the safety of nuclear power, leading governments to suspend new
projects or adopt more restrictive regulatory regimes for monitoring safety.
Exogenous shocks are not the only mechanism that can lead to shifts in public policy images
over time. Baumgartner and Jones (2009) observe that changes in policy indicators, as well as
changes in the tone of media coverage, can both redirect public and political perceptions of policy
problems. Furthermore, policy entrepreneurs play a key role in inuencing perceptions of a
policy problem. Strategic issue denition and redenition (Baumgartner et al. 2008; Baumgartner
and Jones 1993; Jones and Baumgartner 2005) and policy targeting (Boushey 2010; Donovan
2001; Schneider and Ingram 1993) can draw public attention to new dimensions of a problem,
leading to swings in public opinion and support for new policy ideas. It is not simply that
focusing events elevate government attention, but perhaps more importantly that these events
redirect mass political understandings of the underlying policy problem.
These pressures have a common impact on political decision-making, especially when a new
policy idea expands the scope of conict and brings new voices into a policy arena (Shattschneider
1975). As this occurs, the policy monopoly that had sustained policy equilibrium at the sub-
government level is destroyed. In its place, government generates new legislation, regulations,
and institutions to respond to the emerging policy problem, as new stakeholders across political
jurisdictions and venues are mobilized to engage in previously neglected policy arenas. Policy
punctuations represent the output of these periods of instability, as government reorganizes to
eectively respond to the new policy image.
Finally, although the allocation of political attention universally follows the rules of dispropor-
tionate information processing, dierent institutions impose decision costs that lead to stick slip
dynamics in public policy-making, as pressures for policy change contend with institutional rules
that impose friction or gridlock on the policy process (Baumgartner et al. 2009). Here, institu-
tional decision rules shape long-term patterns of policy equilibrium. As pressure for change accu-
mulates, more responsive institutions will see smaller but more frequent reversals in policy-making,
updating policy more rapidly in response to shifting preferences. Institutions with higher deci-
sion costs will be generally resistant to large-scale policy change. In these intuitions, positive
feedback cycles of sudden policy change will occur more rarely, but be larger in size and scope.
This dynamic is illustrated in Jones and Baumgartners (2005) comparison of the historical dis-
tributions of policy change across US policy-making institutions. Where institutional decision-
costs are lower (for example executive orders), punctuated dynamics are less pronounced. Where
institutional costs are highest (for example in budgeting) the distribution of policy change suggested
rare but more extreme policy change.
These observations underpin what Jones and Baumgartner (2005) refer to as the general punc-
tuation hypothesis, as cognitive and individual constraints interact to produce punctuated dynamics
in political decision-making. Because cognitive limitations leading to punctuated dynamics are
universal, punctuated dynamics will emerge across policy-making contexts, and policy-makers
will respond disproportionately to information. However, punctuated dynamics are also con-
tingent on the degrees of friction imposed by institutional rules, leading to a greater likelihood
of punctuations in some institutions of government than others (ibid.: 20).
The dynamics of punctuated equilibrium have been documented across issue areas and
institutional contexts. For example, researchers have documented punctuated dynamics across
Punctuated equilibrium theory
143
US policy-making institutions (Baumgartner and Jones 2005; Jones et al. 2003) as well as state
(Breunig and Koski 2009) and local government budgeting (Jordan 2003). The patterns of policy
stasis and change have been documented in policy areas as distinct as gun control (True and
Utter 2002), crime control (Schneider 2006), environmental regulation (Repetto 2006), tobacco
control (Wood 2006), education nance (Robinson 2006) and international infectious disease
policy (Shiman et al. 2002). Perhaps more impressively, research in recent years has expanded
beyond the study of American politics to evaluate the general punctuation hypotheses in other
institutional contexts. Scholars have documented punctuated dynamics across Western democracies
(Baumgartner et al. 2009; Jones et al. 2009; Baumgartner et al. 2008). This growing body of
work suggests that that punctuated dynamics emerge from pressures of political decision-making
that are generalizeable across eras and institutional contexts (Baumgartner and Jones 2009).
5
Policy entrepreneurs, venue shopping, issue framing and policy change
Punctuated equilibrium theory suggests that interest groups and policy entrepreneurs play a pro-
minent role in developing and introducing new ideas in the political system. Punctuated dynamics
are shaped by the mobilization of competing interest groups and activists in public policy-
making. Organized interests that assume privileged positions in policy monopolies help to
reinforce the status quo, providing expert testimony and support for maintaining a stable policy
regime at the subsystem level. Conversely, the strategic choices of marginalized interest groups
are pivotal for understanding how new ideas enter the political system.
The eect of the participation of interest groups is therefore critical for understanding how
policy images evolve over time. While policy monopolies maintain policy stability, marginalized
or outsider interest groups do not simply acquiesce to the bias of policy monopolies across sub-
governments. Instead, these organizations work to shape policy change at all levels of government.
This section briey discusses how the strategies adopted by outsider or marginalized interests
lead to periods of policy change. In so doing, it highlights one major mechanism leading to
policy change across political systems. Most organized eorts fail to disrupt the status quo, but
when an interest group succeeds, its activities can lead to sweeping changes across institutions.
The rst major implication of punctuated equilibrium theory is that interest groups are not
complacent when they are excluded from policy-making at the subgovernment level. Interest
groups shut out of one policy venue often strategically look for agenda access elsewhere. Organized
interest groups engage in venue shopping, strategically moving across jurisdictions to secure legislative
change (Boushey 2010; Baumgartner and Jones 2009; Cashore and Howlett 2006; Pralle 2003).
In federal systems, interest groups may pressure for reforms across municipal and state governments,
adopt litigation strategies to secure change through the courts, or employ state and local ballot
initiative campaigns to introduce legislation directly before the voters as part of the initiative
system. The logic is that institutions and policy-making jurisdictions are not equally receptive to
new appeals for policy reform. For example, Cashore and Howlett (2006) discovered dierences in
jurisdictional susceptibility to widespread policy reform in federal and state forestry policy, indicating
that various institutions respond dierently to nearly identical pressures for policy change.
More broadly, research in state-level policy innovation and diusion has documented con-
siderable variation in the responsiveness of state governments to calls for policy change.
Researchers have developed a robust understanding of how dierences in the ideology, resources
and professionalism of state and provincial governments shape their responsiveness to new reform
initiatives over time (Boushey 2010; Karch 2007; Berry and Berry 1999). Boushey (2010)
observes that venue shopping in federalism can lead to punctuated patterns of policy diusion
across subnational governments in federalism. The ability of interest groups to secure policy
Boushey
144
change at select venues can result in gradual policy adoptions across jurisdictions as they succeed
in pushing reforms through at state and municipal governments over time. However, in rare
instances venue-shopping strategies can trigger positive feedback cycles as an issue becomes the
focus of broader system-wide policy-making attention (ibid.).
Organized interests not only experiment with the selection of venues but also actively engage
in the framing and reframing of legislative ideas in the hope of expanding public support for
policy change (Baumgartner et al. 2008; Smith 2007). Activists seeking to shape public respon-
siveness to their policy programs experiment with framing legislation in response to changes in
the political environment, looking to attribute new meaning or justication for their preferred
policy proposals (Baumgartner and Jones 1993).
Interest groups adopt one of two strategies when attempting to frame a policy problem. One
is simply to attach a new justication for an existing policy proposal. For example, interest
groups justify policy reforms in the context of the major salient issues of the day, such as
pushing for tax reform legislation as a solution to a major nancial crisis or advocating for a ban
on factory farming in the wake of food safety concerns. Such framing and coupling strategies
are employed to redirect public attention to a di erent dimension of a policy problem that is
more favorable to the policy agenda of a given interest group.
The second form of strategic interest group framing happens with policy targeting. In this
case, interest groups narrow or expand the conict surrounding a proposal by narrowing or
expanding the scope and application of the policy proposal. (Schattschneider 1975). Marijuana
reform activists have pushed for the legalization of medical marijuana, rather than the immediate
end of marijuana prohibition (Boushey 2010). Targeting policies in this manner does not simply
oer new justication for the policy proposal; it alters the scope of the policy itself.
Of course, eorts to redene or reframe a policy debate generally fail to generate broad support
for a new policy reform. Even when a new way of describing a policy problem succeeds,
opposing interest groups often succeed in diminishing the impact of an emerging frame with a
counterargument. However, when issue framing or venue-shopping strategies successfully unite
broad and distinct social interests around a cause, rapid policy change may follow. This points to
an important feature of the broader policy-making processes leading to punctuated dynamics in
public policy-making: although the formal organization of policy-making institutions works to
slow pressures for sudden policy change, the multiple access points and proliferation of interest
groups also encourages the proliferation of policy ideas.
The role that interest groups play in shifting national political attention through issue framing
and venue-shopping strategies have been well-documented in case studies of interest group
mobilization. For example, the passage of the Eighteenth Amendment prohibiting alcohol in
the United States emerged from a century of political pressure, as prohibitionists pushed for local,
state, and national alcohol reform, constantly shifting the justication for prohibition (Boushey
2010; Aaron and Musto 1981). The Tobacco Master Settlement agreement was secured through
judicial venue shopping, as 46 states joined in a giant lawsuit against the tobacco industry to
recover state Medicaid expenditures incurred covering smoking-related illness (Baumgartner and
Jones 2009; Wood 2006). Finally, the longer-term decline in public support for the death
penalty in practice occurred as the death penalty abolitionists succeeded in shifting the focus of
the debate towards the very real possibility that governments were executing the innocent. The
movement to stay the death penalty also followed a venue-shopping strategy, as activists have
pressured for moratoriums on capital punishment in receptive states, legitimizing the policy
reform gradually (Baumgartner et al. 2008).
Although these cases highlight strategies of groups operating within federalism, there is no
reason to believe that this strategic choice is limited to this institutional context. Venue shopping
Punctuated equilibrium theory
145
can occur within single institutions, as actors petition distinct subgovernments to place an issue
on the agenda. For example, activists concerned with the dangers of genetically modied foods
may bypass the Department of Agriculture and instead petition the Food and Drug Administration
to regulate new crops. The essential insight is that organized interests and policy entrepreneurs
play a key role in developing and introducing ideas into the system. Policy entrepreneurs
selectively direct issue attention toward new dimensions of a problem in the hopes of securing a
change of policy over time. Furthermore, they labor to introduce these policies into the poli-
tical system, probing for receptive venues and petitioning for widespread policy adoption. In
these two ways, interest groups play a pivotal role in precipitating punctuated dynamics in
public policy.
Empirical approaches in punctuated equilibrium
The complex processes contributing to negative and positive feedback processes over time make
it dicult to evaluate punctuated equilibrium theory. Positive feedback cycles result from sto-
chastic processes, and it is nearly impossible to anticipate when or how exogenous shocks will
galvanize macropolitical attention over time (Jones and Baumgartner 2005). Sudden shifts in
systemic issue attention can be triggered by factors as distinct as an unexpected environmental
crisis, a coordinated social movement, changes in media coverage regarding a new problem, or a
long-term shift in policy indicators leading to heightened political concern about a new pro-
blem. These unpredictable punctuations are the result of complex interactions between available
policy solutions, participants, and receptive venues at a critical moment. Studies of agenda-setting
assert that shifts in policy-making occur when factors converge to open a window of opportunity
for policy change, but these approaches have oered no universal method for understanding
when such shifts in policy attention will occur.
Preliminary research in punctuated equilibrium theory focused on explaining how complex
interactions precipitate negative and positive feedback cycles in public policy-making, drawing
heavily on longitudinal case studies to illustrate how exogenous shocks, changes in the policy
image, the receptivity of institutional venues, and the participation of interest groups interact
over time to produce policy change within a specic case (Baumgartner and Jones 2009). These
studies of comparative issue dynamics conrmed the patterns of attention allocation leading to
widespread policy change (with the exception of Givel 2006).
6
These studies provided a robust
understanding of the process leading to negative and positive feedback cycles across institutions
and issue areas, and have further permitted researchers to isolate how shifts in the policy image
(Baumgartner and Jones 2009; Baumgartner et al. 2009), the participation of interest groups and
policy entrepreneurs (Boushey 2010), venue shopping (Pralle 2003) and the decision rules of distinct
institutional venues (Baumgartner et al. 2009) contributed to punctuated dynamics in public
policy-making.
To test the broader implications of punctuated equilibrium theory, researchers have shifted
their focus to aggregate patterns of policy outputs across issues and institutions over time, exploring
longitudinal changes in budgetary outlays, law-making, executive orders, public opinion, media
attention and other agenda-setting processes. Over the last decade, researchers working to
understand the evolution of issue attention in government have gathered impressive collections
of data that captures government attention over time. In the United States, Bryan Jones, Frank
Baumgartner, and John Wilkerson have organized the Policy Agendas Project, an invaluable
resource regarding trends in the federal budget, congressional hearings, important problem public
opinion data, media coverage, executive orders and other indicators of national policy-making atten-
tion from 1946 onward.
7
The success of this initial project inspired the Comparative Agendas
Boushey
146
Project, a collaborative endeavor documenting parallel indicators of longitudinal policy atten-
tion across 14 Western democracies.
8
These resources have classied policy attention by major and
subtopic codes, allowing researchers to evaluate both aggregate patterns of policy change while also
tracking the rise and fall of specic issues and policy problems across governments over time.
Punctuated equilibrium theorists have relied on these resources to evaluate how cognitive
constraints and institutional rules shape policy outputs over time. This research focused initially
on the general punctuation hypothesis, exploring whether policy change over time could be
best explained through incrementalism or disproportionate information processing. More recently,
this research has branched out to model how institutions shape information processing.
Because of the overwhelming complexity and unpredictability of policy change in political
systems, punctuated equilibrium theory has employed stochastic process models to evaluate
punctuated dynamics in public policy-making (Breunig and Jones 2011; Breunig and Koski
2009; Baumgartner et al. 2009; Robinson and Caver 2006; Jones and Baumgartner 2005; Jordan
2003; True et al. 1999; Padgett 1980). To evaluate the general punctuated hypothesis, punctuated
equilibrium has examined the underlying probability density distributions of policy inputs and
outputs data, beginning with research on public budgeting (True et al. 1999) and expanding out
to shifts in policy-making in other institutional contexts such as elections, bill introductions and
question periods, legislative hearings, shifts, and media coverage of events over time (Baumgartner
et al. 2009; Jones and Baumgartner 2005; Jones et al. 2003). This research has followed Padgetts
(1980) seminal application of stochastic process models in public budgeting, which demon-
strated that aggregate distributions of policy change over time could be used to distinguish
between incremental and non-incremental patterns of change.
This approach is justied by the theoretical distributions associated with incremental decision-
making and disproportionate information processing. Incrementalism implies a normal distribu-
tion, as policy change occurs through a gradual adjustment with larger shifts in policy occurring
equally around the mean (Breunig and Jones 2011; Baumgartner and Jones 2005; True et al.
1999; Padgett 1980). Punctuated equilibrium theory implies leptokurtic distributions, described
by fat tails (indicative of internal reprioritizations and external policy punctuations), and sharp
central peaks (indicative of internal inattentiveness and external temporal stability) (Breunig
and Jones 2011; Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
Figure 11.1 illustrates policy change distributions associated with incremental and dispropor-
tionate information processing. The incremental histogram on the left follows a normal distribu-
tion of budgetary change over time. Here, annual changes in budgets are clustered around the
mean, and larger changes are evenly distributed, with extremely large punctuation representing
extremely rare events. In the punctuations histogram budgetary change is typically very small, as
evidenced by the central cluster of data around the mean. Moderate policy adjustment occurs
less frequently and major policy change more frequently than anticipated by incremental model.
This is consistent with a process of volatile policy change that occurs through long periods of
neglect and sudden moments of extreme change.
Researchers have supplemented these ocular checks of punctuated dynamics with several
statistical measures of the distribution of policy change data.
9
Most commonly, researchers have
estimated the L-Kurtosis (LK) or peakedness of a given distribution. A normal distribution can
be described as mesokurtic, and is smooth and symmetrical around the mean. Leptokurtic distribu-
tions are indicated by sharp central peaks and fat tails. LK provides a simple method for distin-
guishing between mesokurtic and leptokurtic distributions, returning values in intervals between
0 and 1, with higher values indicating non-normality.
10
The incremental histogram in Figure 11.1
produces an LK score of 0.12, indicative of a normal distribution. The punctuated curve on the
right produces a value of 0.17, indicative of an exponential or power law distribution.
Punctuated equilibrium theory
147
Applied to the study of policy change over time, stochastic process models therefore provide
a relatively simple method for distinguishing between policy-making driven by strict increment-
alism and policy-making driven by punctuated equilibrium. Policy change distributions that are
normally distributed indicate a process of incremental decision-making. Policy change distribu-
tions producing sharp central peaks and fat shoulders imply decision-making processes consistent
with punctuated dynamics in policy-making (Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
Punctuated equilibrium theory has made use of stochastic process models to assess patterns of
decision-making across institutional and historical contexts. These studies have provided robust
support for the general punctuation hypothesis, as virtually all patterns of policy change over
time produce punctuated dynamics consistent with disproportionate information processing.
Distributions of policy change data consistent with punctuated equilibrium theory have been
identied in studies of public budging in federal budgeting ( Jones and Baumgartner 2005), state
budgeting (Breunig and Koski 2006), and local government budgeting ( Jordan 2003). A com-
parison of national budgeting across the United States, France, Germany, Great Britain, Denmark
and Canada conrmed that budget change across nations produces punctuated dynamics ( Jones
et al. 2009). This growing body of research suggests that incrementalism is one process of
decision-making embedded in a larger model of disproportionate information processing.
More recently studies of punctuated equilibrium have employed stochastic process models to
understand how dierent institutions shape punctuated dynamics in policy-making. Here,
researchers have compared the shape and kurtosis of change data to understand how the institu-
tional context shapes punctuated dynamics in policy-making. Some institutions impose consider-
able friction against policy change while others are more responsive. This research has qualied
PETs earlier understanding of disproportionate information processing, illustrating that varia-
tion in the decision rules and transaction costs imposed across institutions shapes the frequency
and magnitude of policy punctuations. Baumgartner and his coauthors (2009) compare the
kurtosis values associated with policy change distributions across multiple policy-making insti-
tutions in the United States, Denmark and Belgium, nding that institutions that impose larger
barriers to policy change are also more susceptible to large policy punctuations. Although all
policy-making departs from normal incremental decision-making process, there is considerable
variation in the slip stick dynamics imposed by dierent forms of institutions. Government activ-
ities such as elections produce smaller L-kurtosis values than more rigid policy output processes,
Figure 11.1 Incremental and punctuated policy change distributions
Source: Breunig, Christian and Chris Koski. 2009. Punctuated Budgets and Governors Institutional
Powers, American Politics Research 37(6): 111638.
Boushey
148
such as lawmaking and budgeting (Baumgartner et al. 2009). Breunig and Koski (2009) conrm
these dynamics in their study in US state-level gubernatorial powers. The executives ability to
shape state budgets and veto undesirable legislation contributed to larger punctuations than
states with weaker executive oces.
Conclusion
The renewed focus on stochastic process models points to one of the most promising areas for
future research in punctuated equilibrium. The initial research testing the general punctuation
hypothesis has demonstrated that policy-making cannot uniformly be explained as resulting
from an incremental decision-making process. However, research has only recently started to
identify distributions commonly associated with disproportionate information processing in policy-
making (Breunig and Jones 2011). Future research will allow us to dierentiate between incre-
mental decision-making, sudden punctuations in response to exogenous shocks, and policy change
triggered by changes in factors endogenous to a given political system. PET researchers have
already begun to test how closely policy change distributions associated with dierent policy
processes match specic outcome distributions such as the power law or exponential distribu-
tions that result from distinct decision-making processes (Jones et al. 2009). Identifying the dis-
tributions attached to specic mechanisms of policy change beyond incrementalism will help us
understand the processes leading to policy change over time. Boushey (2010) integrated research
from agenda-setting and epidemiology to distinguish between incremental and punctuated
patterns of policy diusion in the United States. This research suggested that innovations that
encourage positive feedback cycles in policy-making could produce steep S-shaped distributions
representative of internal contagion, leading to rapid diusion across states, or stark R-shaped
exponential distributions in response to exogenous factors.
The data resources prepared in the Policy and Comparative Agendas projects will also lead to
new discovery in the eld. These resources provide leverage not only for testing how dierent
institutions shape punctuated dynamics in policy-making, but also for testing how the interac-
tion of policy-makers and policy ideas across systems shapes patterns of policy change over time.
The time series measures of attention across countries will eventually provide researchers with a
powerful resource for understanding how the serial allocation of political attention across countries
shapes patterns of agenda-setting and policy adoption over space and time. For example, research
focusing on the policy responses of domestic and international political systems to exogenous
shocks will help us to understand how dierent institutions respond to common exogenous shocks.
Current research shows how aggregate patterns of policy change generally unfold across dier-
ent institutional contexts. Future research will identify how dierent institutions interact with
common exogenous signals in policy-making.
Over the last two decades, researchers have expanded on the initial model of punctuated
equilibrium theory presented in Agendas and Instability in American Politics. On the one hand, PET
has added a much richer account of the decision-making model leading to incremental adjust-
ment and sudden positive feedback cycles. This has grounded punctuated equilibrium theory,
illustrating how disproportionate information processing leads to shifts in attention and policy
preferences in individuals and the institutions they populate. At the same time, PET theory has
expanded on the macropolitical implications of punctuated equilibrium theory, moving from a
study of policy change in the United States to a more general model of agenda-setting and
policy-making within organizations. The assumptions of PET theory have been evaluated in case
studies across issue areas and at the aggregate level across institutions. The broad interest in the
theory has generated a strong consensus regarding how policy change occurs over time, and
Punctuated equilibrium theory
149
points to a promising research agenda as new scholars identify how the allocation of policy
attention in organizations and institutions leads to profound shifts in public policy.
Notes
1 This section highlights only the subset of the major health reforms in the PPACA. An interested reader
may wish to refer to the Kaiser Family Foundations (2010) Summary of the new health reform law
for a succinct 13-page summary of the key provisions of the PPACA.
2 To conceptualize the pressures leading to incremental and sudden policy change within a single poli-
tical system over time, Baumgartner and Jones (1993) borrowed from evolutionary biology and
paleontology, drawing on Eldredge and Goulds punctuated equilibrium theory of speciation (1972).
For a comparison of the PET framework in biology and public policy, see Robinson (2006). For a
critique of the metaphor, see Givel (2010).
3 Punctuated equilibrium theory borrows heavily from prior research in bounded rationality in policy-
making to explain pressures leading to policy stability and change. For more extensive reviews of
bounded rationality or incrementalism in policy-making, refer to Jones and Hayes chapters in this
volume.
4 The stability of participants at the subgovernment level has been well-documented in the study of
American politics. Researchers have alternately labeled this organization of elected ocials, interest
group activists and bureaucrats as iron triangles, policy subsystems, or issue networks.
5 For far more expansive lists of the many contributions of punctuated equilibrium theory, refer to the
publications page at the Comparative Agendas Project web page (www.comparativea gendas.org/pub lications)
or the Policy Agendas publication web page (www.policyagendas.org/biblio).
6 Givel (2006) contends that punctuated equilibrium theory fails to explain the stability of tobacco policy
in the face of widespread pressure for policy reform. Baumgartner and Jones (2009) revisit the case of
tobacco reform in the second edition of Agendas and Instability in American Politics. They argue that the
pro-industry tobacco policy monopoly has been thoroughly destroyed at the federal level, and that radical
reforms to tobacco control and regulation have occurred at the state and local levels of government.
7 These data are available at the policy agendas website at: www.policyagendas.org.
8 More detailed information on the Comparative Agendas Project can be accessed at: www.CAP.org.
9 Researchers have employed other simple tests evaluate the normality of a given probability density
function. Tests such as the Shapiro-Wilk, Anderson Darling or the KolmogorovSmirnov test indicate
whether a given distribution is consistent with a normal (incremental) decision-making process.
10 Prior research in punctuated equilibrium employed standard measures of kurtosis (K) to estimate the
shape of the distribution. For K, normal distributions have kurtosis values of 3, with larger values
indicating leptokurtic distributions. Breunig and Jones (2011) suggest L-Kurtosis as an alternative, as
this measure results in more stable estimates of the overall shape of the distribution.
Bibliography
Aaron, Paul and David Musto. 1981. Temperance and prohibition in America: A historical overview,in
Mark Moore and Dean Gerstein (eds) Alcohol and Public Policy: Beyond the Shadow of Prohibition.
Washington, DC: National Academy Press, 12581.
Baumgartner, Frank and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
——and Bryan D. Jones. 2002. Positive and negative feedback in politics,inPolicy Dynamics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press
——and Bryan Jones. 2009. Agendas and Instability in American Politics, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
——, Suzanna De Boef and Amber Boydstun. 2008. The Decline of the Death Penalty and the Discovery of
Innocence. New York: Cambridge University Press.
——, Christoer Green-Pedersen and Bryan D. Jones (eds). 2008. Comparative Studies of Policy Agendas.
New York: Routledge.
——, Christian Breunig, Christoer Green-Pedersen, Bryan D. Jones, Peter B. Mortensen, Michiel
Nuytemans and Stefaan Walgrave. 2009. Punctuated equilibrium in comparative perspective, American
Journal of Political Science 53(3): 60320.
Boushey
150
Berry, Frances S. and William D. Berry. 1999. Innovation and diusion models in policy research, in Paul
A. Sabatier (ed.) Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 169200.
Birkland, Thomas A. 1997. After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy, and Focusing Events. Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press.
Boushey, Graeme. 2010. Policy Diusion Dynamics in America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Breunig, Christian and Chris Koski. 2006. Punctuated equilibria and budgets in the American states,
Policy Studies Journal 34(3): 36379.
——and Chris Koski. 2009. Punctuated budgets and governors institutional powers, American Politics
Research 37(6): 111638.
——and Bryan Jones. 2011. Stochastic process methods with an application to budegetary data, Political
Analysis 19(1): 10317.
Cashore, Benjamin and Michael Howlett. 2006. Behavioral thresholds and institutional rigidities as expla-
nations of punctuated equilibrium processes in Pacic Northwest Forest Policy Dynamics, in Robert
Repetto (ed.) Punctuated Equilibrium in US Environmental Policy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
pp. 13761.
Donovan, Mark. 2001. Taking Aim: Target Populations and the Wars on Aids and Drugs. Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press.
Eldredge, Niles and Stephen Gould. 1972. Punctuated equilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism,in
T. Schopf (ed.) Paleiobiology, San Francisco: Freeman, Cooper, 82115.
Givel, Michael. 2006. Punctuated equilibrium in limbo: The tobacco lobby and US state policy making
from 1990 to 2003, Policy Studies Journal 43(3): 40518.
—— 2010. The evolution of the theoretical foundations of punctuated equilibrium theory in public
policy, Review of Policy Research 27(2): 18798.
Hayes,
Michael. 1992. Incrementalism and
Public Policy. New York: Longman.
Holyoke, Thomas. 2003. Choosing battlegrounds: Interest group lobbying across multiple venues, Political
Research Quarterly 56: 32536.
Iyengar, Shanto. 1996. Framing responsibility for political issues, Annals of the American Academy of Political
and Social Science 546(1): 5970.
Jones, Bryan D. 1994. Reconceiving Decision-Making in Democratic Politics: Attention, Choice, and Public Policy.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—— 2001. Politics and the Architecture of Choice: Bounded Rationality and Governance. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
——and Frank Baumgartner. 2004. Representation and agenda setting, Policy Studies Journal 32: 125.
——and Frank Baumgartner. 2005. The Politics of Attention: How Government Prioritizes Problems. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
——, Tracy Sulkin and Heather Larsen. 2003. Punctuations in American political institutions, American
Political Science Review 97(1): 15169.
——, Frank R. Baumgartner, Christian Breunig, Christopher Wlezien, Stuart Soroka, Martial Foucault,
Abel François, Christoer Green-Pedersen, Peter John, Chris Koski, Peter B. Mortensen, Frédéric
Varone and Stefaan Walgrave. 2009. A general empirical law of public budgets: A comparative analysis,
American Journal of Political Science 53(4): 85573.
Jordan, Meagan. 2003. Punctuations and agendas: A new look at local government budget expenditures,
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 22: 34560.
Kaiser Family Foundation. 2010. Summary of new health reform law, Focus on Health Reform. Available
at: www.k.org/healthreform/upload/8061.pdf (accessed 23 November 2011).
Karch, Andrew 2007. Emerging issues and future directions in state policy diusion research, State Politics
and Policy Quarterly 7(1):
5480.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agendas,
Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Lindblom, Charles. 1959. The science of muddling through, Public Administration Review 19: 7988.
Padgett, John F. 1980. Bounded rationality in budgetary research, American Political Science Review 74:
35472.
Pralle, Sarah. 2003. Venue shopping, political strategy, and policy change: A case study of Canadian forest
advocacy, Journal of Public Policy 23: 23360.
Repetto, Robert (ed.). 2006. Punctuated Equilibrium and the Dynamics of US Environmental Policy. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Robinson, Scott. E. 2006. Punctuated equilibrium models in organizational decision making, in Goktug
Morcol (ed.) Handbook on Human Decision Making. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, 133 49.
Punctuated equilibrium theory
151
—— and Flounsay R. Caver. 2006. Punctuated equilibrium and Congressional policymaking, Political
Research Quarterly 59(1): 1616.
—— and Kenneth J. Meier. 2006. Path dependence and organizational behavior: Bureaucracy and
internal standards, American Review of Public Administration, 36(3): 24160.
Schattschneider, Elmer E. 1975. The Semi-sovereign People. Hinsdale, IL: Dryden Press.
Schneider, Anne Larason. 2006. Patterns of change in the use of imprisonment in the American states: An
integration of path dependence, punctuated equilibrium and policy design approaches, Political Research
Quarterly 59(3): 45770.
—— and Helen Ingram. 1993. The social construction of target populations: Implications for politics and
policy, American Political Science Review 87(2): 33447.
Shiman, Jeremy, Tanya Beer and Yonghong Wu. 2002. The emergence of global disease control priorities,
Health Policy and Planning 17(3): 22534.
Smith, Mark A. 2007. The Right Talk: How Conservatives Transformed the Great Society into the Economic
Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
True, James and Glenn Utter. 2002. Saying yes, no, and load me up to guns in America, The
American Review of Public Administration 32(2): 21641.
——, Bryan Jones and Frank Baumgartner. 1999. Punctuated-equilibrium theory: Explaining stability and
change in American policymaking, in Paul Sabatier (ed.) Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, 15588.
——, Bryan Jones and Frank Baumgartner. 2007. Punctuated equilibrium theory: explaining stability and
change
in American policymaking,
in Paul Sabatier (ed.) Theories of the Policy Process, 2nd edn. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press, 15588.
Tsebelis, George. 2002. Veto Players: How Political Institutions Work. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Walgrave, Stefaan and Frédéric Varone. 2008. Punctuated equilibrium, and agenda setting: Bringing parties
back in. Policy change after the Dutroux crisis in Belgium, Governance: An International Journal of Policy
and Administration 21(3): 36595.
Wildavsky, A. 1964. The Politics of the Budgetary Process. Toronto: Little, Brown.
Wood, Robert. 2006. Tobaccos tipping point: the master settlement agreement as a focusing event,
Policy Studies Journal 34(3): 41936.
Workman, Samuel, Bryan D. Jones and Ashley E. Jochim. 2009. Information processing and policy
dynamics, Policy Studies Journal 37(1): 7592.
Boushey
152
12
Policy network models
Chen-Yu Wu and David Knoke
Dening policy networks
The overarching goal of policy network analysis is to understand how relationships between
actors involved in policy-making determine the outcomes of collective policy decisions (Compston
2009; Knoke 2011). To this end, policy network analysis consists of two distinct components.
First, one has to identify the important actors involved in the policy-making process. Although
policies are proposed, debated, and passed by legislators and other governmental entities, extra-
governmental actors such as non-governmental organizations (NGOs), interest groups, or even
inuential individuals can be involved in inuencing policies. Second, one has to describe the
type of social interactions that occur between actors during the policy-making process. Both
components are vital to enabling the researcher to explain or predict policy outcomes.
In short, policy network analysis provides scholars with an analytical framework to describe the
social network dimensions of policy-making. However, policy network analysis can also be
used to answer the fundamental research questions of social network analysis, namely: how
these networks form, how and why they persist over time, and also how they change.
Social network theory
Social network analysis consists of theories and methods for examining structural relations among
social actors and for explaining the consequences of those connections. Network theories can
apply to structures and processes occurring either in small, closed social systems (such as arti-
cially constructed experimental groups, or natural settings such as classrooms and work teams) or
in larger, open systems (such as communities, markets, and international relations). Network the-
ories and data analyses may apply to the egocentric, interpersonal, subgroup, or complete network
levels of analysis, as well as to cross-level and time-dependent eects. At the micro-level, net-
work analysts examine how people form, change, or drop ties such as friendship, giving assis-
tance and advice, exchanging information, and quarreling. Interpersonal interactions aggregate
into meso-level social structures that aect collective actions and performance outcomes of small
groups such as gangs, teams, and crews. Macro-level systems of cities, economies, nations, and
transnational relations may be studied using conceptual and methodological techniques
153
developed through decades of social network theory and research. The interdisciplinary eld
originated in anthropology, small group, social psychology, and sociology in the mid-twentieth
century, and really took o around 1970 as theoretical interest in structural analysis converged with
increasingly sophisticated computer software for analyzing network data based on matrix algebra
methods. The exponential growth of social research and proliferation of academic specialties intro-
duced social network analysis to increasing numbers of basic, substantive, and applied disciplines,
including political sociology, political science, and public administration.
As a minimum a social network consists of a set of actors (people, groups, organizations, nations)
and one or more relations that connect some of them (e.g., communication, trust, purchase,
attack). A boundary- or scope-condition species which actors are included within a particular
network; for example, by formal membership as in a social club; by residence as in a neigh-
borhood; or by informal criteria such as attendance at ea markets. Network theories typically
make three core assumptions about the mutual inuences among actors: (1) the social structure
of any complex system consists of the stable patterns of repeated interactions connecting actors
to one another; (2) these social relations are the primary explanatory units of analysis, rather
than the attributes and characteristics of the individual actors; and (3) the perceptions, attitudes,
and actions of actors are shaped by the multiple structural networks within which they are
embedded, and in turn their behaviors can change these networks structures (Knoke 2001: 634).
Political networks are a subset of social networks in which the primary relations among actors
involve inequalities in power. Asymmetrical power rarely depends on overt coercive force and
more often relies on taken-for-grant beliefs about the possession of authority to issue commands
and to expect compliance with orders (Max Webers legitimate power). Political power is
inherently relational: one or more actors seek resources and other advantages despite resistance
by others. Hence, social network theory is well-suited to investigate the diverse structures and
consequences of power, from the bedroom to the boardroom to the battleeld. Political net-
works can be observed at micro-levels, where friends and kin try to persuade one another to
vote and participate in electoral campaigns. At the most macro-level, political networks in the
international system are evident in shifting patterns of military alliances and interstate aggression
(e.g. Maoz 2010). This chapter concentrates on meso-level political networks comprised mainly
of formal organizations engaged in collective eorts to inuence public policy decisions within
nation-states.
To explain public policymaking at various governmental levels, network theorists draw
attention to the policy network as an appropriate unit of analysis. In local governments, important
political actors are typically powerful individuals (e.g. mayor, council members). But, at national
levels, inuential actors are more often formal organizations such as political parties, legislative
committees, executive agencies, ministries, and interest organizations including labor unions,
business associations, and public interest groups. Kenis and Schneider (1991: 41) argued, Policy
networks should be conceived as specic structural arrangements in policymaking. They
dened a policy network as set of public and private corporate actors linked by communication
ties for exchanging information, expertise, trust, and other political resources:
A policy network is described by its actors, their linkages and its boundary. It includes a
relatively stable set of mainly public and private corporate actors. The linkages between the
actors serve as channels for communication and for the exchange of information, expertise,
trust and other policy resources. The boundary of a given policy network is not in the rst
place determined by formal institutions but results from a process of mutual recognition
dependent on functional relevance and structural embeddedness.
(ibid.)
Wu and Knoke
154
A closely related concept, the policy domain, is socially constructed by political actors who mutually
recognize that their preferences on policy events must be taken into consideration by other
domain participants (Laumann and Knoke 1987: 10). A policy domain is dened as any political
subsystem
identied by specifying a substantively dened criterion of mutual relevance or common
orientation among a set of consequential actors concerned with formulating, advocating, and
selecting courses of action (i.e., policy options) that are intended to resolve the delimited
substantive problems in question.
(Knoke and Laumann 1982: 256)
Some policy domain examples are education, agriculture, national defense, welfare (Laumann
and Knoke 1987: 10), health, energy, and transportation (Burstein 1991: 328). The policy network
and the policy domain concepts are interrelated, with a policy domain delineating a bounded
system within which its organizational participants are interconnected by one or more policy
networks.
Five basic types of interorganizational relations exhibiting distinctive policy network struc-
tures, include: resource exchange; information transmission; power relations; boundary pene-
tration; and sentimental attachments (Knoke 2001: 65). Resource exchanges in policy networks,
such as money or personnel, are usually voluntary transfers, although occasional government
mandates impose interorganizational connections. Information exchanges range from technical
and scientic data to policy advice and advocacy. Power relations include both formal and informal
inequalities in authority and dominance, with public sector entities usually controlling more
power than private sector organizations to impose their interests on a domain. Boundary penetra-
tion refers to two or more actors coordinating their actions for a common goal, such as lobbying as
discussed below. Sentimental attachments are subjective and emotional aliation expressing
solidarity and political support as exemplied by labor unions and social movement organiza-
tions. The ve basic types of interorganizational relations can be operationalized by a multitude
of empirical indicators and jointly analyzed to reveal network structures connecting policy
domain organizations in complex patterns.
An interorganizational perspective on policy domains and policy networks comprised the
theoretical and methodological basis for the organizational state model of policymaking that
Edward Laumann, David Knoke, and Franz Pappi constructed for investigating the US national
energy and health domains (Laumann and Knoke 1987), and comparative network analysis of
the US, German, and Japanese labor domains (Knoke et al. 1996). See Knoke (1998) for a
detailed overview of these and related projects. The organizational state model views national
policy-making processes as dynamic inuence actions among formal organizations, with elite
persons acting as agents of these organizational principals. Within every policy domain, the set
of core organizational players are drawn from both the public and private sectors. Some key
organizations may have intense interests in numerous policy issues and participate in eorts to
aect the policy outcomes of dozens of legislative, executive, and judicial decisions. Other organi-
zations focus more narrowly on a single issue and mobilize only rarely to pursue their interests.
Given the diversity of organizational interests, limited resources, and complexity of inuence
dynamics, no organization or small subset has the capacity to control, let alone dominate, a policy
domains policy-making processes. Instead, most policy ghts consist of multiorganizational
coalitions brought temporarily together to work collectively on shaping policy proposals and
advocating a specic preferred policy solution to those authorities capable of rendering a bind-
ing decision on a particular policy event (e.g. a regulatory ruling, legislative act, court decision).
Policy network models
155
A policy domains communication and resource exchange networks enable interested organi-
zations to identify collaborators and opponents that can be mobilized on competing sides of a
policy event. Frequently, some members of an action setorganizations that all hold the same
outcome preference on the event, are connected in a communication network, and coordinate
their policy to inuence actionspool their political resources and launch coordinated cam-
paigns to pressure governmental decision-makers into choosing the policy outcome favored by
the coalition members.
Some organizations work solo but chances of a favorable outcome are usually greater when
coalitions create an ecient division of labor that maximizes their strengths and expertise.
Broad-based membership organizations such as labor unions mobilize mass constituencies to
man phone banks and email legislators. Organizations with well-funded sta assemble research
evidence to present during testimony at public legislative and regulatory hearings. Political con-
sultants produce persuasive head-counts at closed-door meetings with elected ocials. And deep-
pocketed political action committees always have an open door to make their cases to cash-starved
politicians. Lobbying proceeds neither by political bribery nor by striking overt quid pro quo
deals, but by making a more persuasive case in an appropriate decision-making arena (Brown
1998). Lobbyists succeed by providing policy-makers with useful information and data, sub-
stantive arguments, proposed policy language, and astute political arguments for supporting one
side of a policy ght over the alternatives.
After a binding policy decision is made, the coalitions disband as new policy events attract
dierent combinations of organized interest groups. Viewed over time, the policy network
structures of policy domain appear continually in ux. Yet, despite much instability at the micro-
level, relatively durable macro-level cleavages may emerge and persist. Examples of such enduring
cleavages are the business-vs.-labor, rural-vs.-urban, and religious-vs.-secular divisions occurring
in many nations. Many national policy domains contain fairly stable policy networks whose
boundaries and components persist over substantial time (Burstein 1991). However, as social
constructions, created through interactions among organizations and given meaning by culture
(1991: 345), policy domains are susceptible to reconceptualization and evolutionary transforma-
tions. Scant theory seeks to explain the historical origins of new policy domains or the trans-
formation of existing domains. An exception is Knokes (2004) schematic model of six elements
(focusing events, technological innovations, political entrepreneurs, issue framing, policy networks,
and institutionalization), which he oered as a provisional framework to initiate empirical research
on the sociopolitical construction of national policy domains (2004: 94). So far, no takers.
History and development of policy network analyses
According to Knoke (2011), the term policy network was rst used by Katzenstein (1976) in
his article comparing the foreign economic policies of France and the United States. Although
Katzenstein did not explicitly dene policy networks, he emphasized that policy networks form
a crucial link between state and society. Additionally, he proposed a simple continuum for
describing types of policy networks. One ideal type (to use the Weberian term) is the state-
centered policy network, which is dened by political power and dominance; the other ideal
type is the society-centered policy network, which in contrast is dened by economic power.
In practice, Katzenstein stated that all policy networks in advanced industrial states would fall
somewhere between the two extremes.
Since the publication of Katzensteins article, the volume of work on policy networks has
grown immensely. These works encompass policy-making on all levels, from the local level (e.g.
Laumann and Pappi 1976) to comparative (e.g. Marsh 1998), regional (e.g. Adshead 2002), and
Wu and Knoke
156
transnational analyses (e.g. McGann and Sabatini 2011; Witte et al. 2000). As the eld of policy
network analysis expanded, three distinct schools of thought emerged. In the following sub-
sections, we will briey discuss the US, British, and German perspectives on policy network
analysis.
United States. The American approach to policy network analysis is rooted in Laumann and
Pappis 1973 study, New Directions in the Study of Community Elites. In the study, as well as
subsequent replications (e.g. Galaskiewicz 1979; Laumann et al. 1978), researchers employed the
network analysis of power structures and found that actors in central network positions were
more engaged in local civic life, and as a result, enjoyed a better chance of inuencing public
policy debates in their favor.
Laumann and Knoke extended this framework to national policy domains and the formal orga-
nizations within them in The Organizational State (1987), and found that the networks among
these organizations enabled organizations with opposing interests to pool their resources and
mobilize them in pursuit of commonly-desired policy outcomes. Furthermore, the authors found
that, at the national level, it is often the case that dierent organizations simultaneously have
common and opposing policy interests.
In another study, Knoke et al. (1996) found that, like policy-making at the local level, actors
in centrally located network positions could more easily inuence policy decisions. In their
comparative study of US, German, and Japanese policy domains, they make the distinction between
communication networks (characterized by exchanges of information) and support networks
(characterized by resource exchanges), and found that occupying a central position in commu-
nication networks provided organizations with more political inuence in the US and Germany,
while the opposite was true for Japan (1996: 120). These ndings suggest that the processes
involved in policy-making are not necessarily universal, but rather culturally determined.
Germany. The German approach to policy network analysis, like the American approach, is
rooted both in the previously discussed study by Laumann and Pappi (1973), and also in
Lehmbruchs (1984, 1989) studies of corporatist politics the Federal Republic of Germany (FRG).
Compared to other more centralized states, such as the United Kingdom, the FRGs relative
noncentralized policy networks necessitated exchanges of resources among many organizations
involved in policy-making (Lehmbruch termed this corporatist concertation). In this policy
environment, Lehmbruch (1984) found that these interorganizational policy networks serve as
an important structural and institutional constraint moderating the outcomes of collective policy
decisions. Equally importantly, Lehmbruch (1989) concluded that the formal organizations involved
in the policy-making process can inuence the structure and dynamics of policy networks.
Great Britain. Unlike the American and German approaches, which analyze policy networks
using theories of power structures, British scholars analytical framework involves highlighting
the contrasts between dierent networks pluralist and corporatist characteristics (e.g. Rhodes
1985, 1990). Additionally, unlike American and German scholars, British policy network analysis
places more emphasis on more uid and unpredictable policy communities rather than entren-
ched governmental and subgovernmental units (Richardson 2000; Rhodes 1990). As such,
British scholars produced a wide range of literature on self-organizing groups involved in the
policy-making processes for policy domains such as agriculture, employment, and informational
technology.
Within the British school of thought, one of its more inuential works is Marsh and Rhodes
(1992) book, Policy Networks in British Government, which provided an analytical approach empha-
sizing the importance of structural relations between governmental entities, interest groups, and
informal actors, as opposed to interpersonal relations among individual actors. Equally impor-
tantly, their approach established a unidirectional direct link between policy networks and
Policy network models
157
policy outcomes. Critics of this approach, notably Dowding (1995, 2001), have argued that it
has two glaring weaknesses: rst, it lacks a theoretical basis; and second, it does not provide any
basis for explaining network transformation (which is, as previously mentioned, an important
objective for policy network scholars). In response, various authors (e.g. Marsh and Smith 2000;
Kisby 2007) have oered explanations and models addressing these criticisms.
Key ideas in modern policy network analysis
One of the features that all of these views of policy network analysis share, to some extent, is
the idea of resource dependency (Benson 1982; Rhodes 1985). In other words, in the realm of
policy-making, every actor desires resources that other actors control. As a result, every actor is
prepared to exchange or give up some resources in order to obtain resources which they do not
have (Compston 2009: 7). These exchanges are not unregulated or arbitrary; rather, actors employ
specic strategies which conform to mutually accepted rules of the game (Rhodes 1985: 45).
These rules can either be formally codied (e.g. laws regulating campaign contributions from
interest groups) or informal (e.g. hiring former government ocials to serve as consultants and
advisers to interest groups).
A common example in modern-day democracies is the exchange of resources between law-
makers and interest groups. As previously mentioned, legislators and other government ocials
are the only people who can legally introduce, debate, and ultimately pass policy in the halls of
government. Such political authority is a key resource that all other actors lack, and therefore
seek access to. These actors, however, control other resources coveted by these legislators.
Namely, interest groupsand the members they representhold both the votes that legislators
need to win elections and the funds legislators require to wage successful campaigns. Hence,
actors like interest groups can inuence or pressure legislators to push for legislation advocating
for their preferred policy outcomes.
This example highlights two key characteristics in every policy network. First is the assumption
that policy actors are rational, and that actors agree to participate in these resource exchanges if
they stand to benet from them. To illustrate, an ocial with a largely conservative electorate is
unlikely to heed the demands of a liberal/progressive interest group, nor accept its donations,
since the ocial does not need the votes of the minority to secure re-election, nor does the
ocial wish to alienate his or her base constituency. This characteristic can also explain why
legislators are much less likely to compromise with colleagues with opposing views when their
political parties hold a majority in government.
The second characteristic is that all policy exchanges stem from power imbalancespolitical,
economic, or ideologicaland that all policy exchanges result in power imbalances, although
not necessarily the same ones as before the exchange. In theory, if the playing eld was level for all
actors, there would be no need to exchange resources. Another way to approach this characteristic
is to understand that all resource exchanges result in losers as well as winners (Compston 2009).
In democracies, it is rarely the case that an individual legislator is subjected to the lobbying
eorts of a single nongovernmental actor; it is more likely that individual legislators are simul-
taneously considering the requests of multiple competing actors. Hence, after every exchange,
there will be some actors which are more well-o as a result, and others who are less so.
Policy network theory and empirical research
Like every analytical framework, policy network theory has strengths and weaknesses. For instance,
early critics of policy network theory charged that policy network research largely failed to
Wu and Knoke
158
develop testable theories of both policy development and outcomes (Knoke 2011). Addition-
ally, as mentioned previously, other criticsnotably Dowding (1995)claim that the discourse
of policy network theory is not only merely descriptive, but more importantly that the precise
denitions of many concepts in policy network research have not been agreed upon universally
by the scholars conducting this research. More recent work (e.g. Mikkelson 2006) has high-
lighted some confusion among scholars about whether policy networks should be treated as
dependent or independent variables. In other words, is policy network theory a better frame-
work for understanding why and how these networks form, or is it a better tool for predicting
the outcomes and consequences of this type of collective action?
Despite these criticisms, policy network theory continues to be an extremely valuable ana-
lytical tool for understanding both social network theory in general, but also the policy-making
process. A large volume of recent work was produced by European scholars, probably due to
both the creation of new nation-states following the fall of the Soviet Union in 1991, and also
the increased prominence of the European Union in European political and civic life (Knoke
2011). The increased volume of policy network research has also seen scholars expand their
foci, including: from government to strategies of governance; from centrally focused policy-
making to multilayered policy-making (McGann and Sabatini 2011; von Winter 2001); from
top-down hierarchies to grassroots inuences (von Winter 2004); and from policy formation
and outcomes to policy implementation (e.g. Greenaway et al. 2007).
Although policy network research in the United States has not kept pace with Europe,
American scholars have made some signicant contributions. For instance, some scholars
uncovered new insights into policy theory and social network theory in general through the
re-examination of older studies, while others chose to focus on and expand research on policy
domains (Knoke 2011). These new studies remain very much rooted in the American per-
spective of power structures. For instance, Carpenter et al. (2003) found that as actors needs for
policy-related information increases, they are much more likely to invest their eorts and
resources in building stronger communication links to their allies, rather than reaching out to
their opponents. The downside of this approach, however, is that by engaging in such cliquish
behavior, network actors expose themselves to an increased risk of network failure due to their
inability to obtain complete information (2003: 433).
American scholars continue to be active in research into the social construction (and recon-
struction) of policy domains. Policy domain researchparticularly research into changes in
policy domains is a signicant component of policy network theory, as it provides researchers
with a link between culture and policy-making (Knoke 2004). In other words, changes in
policy domains potentially transforms shared cultural meanings, taken-for-granted assumptions,
normative understandings, classicatory schemas, and tacit knowledge (2004: 3). Its implica-
tions for policy network theory are fairly clear: new domains necessitate new policy-making
strategies to comply with new legal regulations and bureaucratic practices, as well as other
unanticipated changes.
Analyses of policy networks in non-Western states remain rare (Knoke 2011). This dearth is
most likely due to various factors, such as the lack of cultural or political traditions of civic
participation or, more basically, the inability to participate in civic life under certain forms of
government. Additionally, the few studies that have been conducted tended to be descriptive,
rather than theoretically grounded empirical research. As a result, there is a huge potential for
growth for policy network literature on non-Western countries, as well as cross-national and
comparative studies.
Another impetus for the growth of policy network analysis is the increased scholarly interest
in globalization. According to McGann and Sabatini (2011), since globalization is commonly
Policy network models
159
characterized by the global movement of capital and services, policy networks are ideal for the
study of globalization due to the ability to identify and incorporate actors across social, political,
governmental, and geographical boundaries. Additionally, two factors which occurred almost
hand-in-hand with globalization also encouraged the proliferation of policy network research:
namely, increased political and economic liberalization across the globe, and technological advances
particularly in information exchange (e.g. the Internet). These developments allow civic-minded
individuals and organizations more easily to establish transnational relationships and maintain
their channels of communication (ibid.: 678).
While almost all research on globalization and policy networks is relatively recent, the work
has the potential of encouraging even more growth for this analytical framework. The reason is
that global polities of governance dier signicantly from national governments, or even regional
alliances. United Nations global policy-making bodies dier from national and regional alliances
in that they tend to be decentralized, and that they tend to lack means of enforcing policies (for
instance, nations can choose not to ratify or implement UN resolutions usually without any fear
of retribution). Consequently, network strategies employed by actors on the global stage will
inevitably dier from the strategies examined in current literature, reecting the dierent challenges
required to gain actors acquiescence and avoid disagreements.
Future directions for policy network research
We reiterate the central research questions which motivate policy network research, namely, how
these networks form, how and why they persist over time, and also how they change. Pre-
sently, most literature focuses on the second question: scholars have amassed a trove of infor-
mation about how routine activities occur within the context of already-established policy domains
and policy networks. Large gaps still exist in the literature on the origins of policy networks, as
well as how they change.
Some scholars have taken steps to address these shortcomings. For instance, Knoke (2004)
proposed an analytical framework which would enable researchers to study how policy domains
and consequently policy networkschange. He argued that changes which are disruptive to
routine activitieswhich he terms focusing events”—are central to these changes. A promi-
nent example of a focusing event, which permanently altered actors perceptions of the world
around them, is the September 11 terrorist attacks. Other focusing events include the exponential
growth of the Internet (Rethemeyer 2007), which enabled and empowered organizational and
individual actors alike to accomplish much more (particularly in terms of communications and
networking) than was ever possible before.
Other analytical frameworks include Marsh et al.s (2009) attempt to merge Grants (1978)
distinction between insider and outsider groups with Marsh and Rhodes (1992) policy
network classication system, reasoning that each approach makes up for each others shortcomings.
They applied this analytical framework to a case study, and concluded that the amalgamation of
the two approaches could allow scholars to develop a better classication system of the types of
interest groups and policy networks. Another recent framework proposed by Sandström and
Carlsson (2008) argued that while network orientation has long been a vital part of policy sci-
ence, most existing research does not focus on how a networks structure aects its perfor-
mance. Their framework proposes that an eective policy networkthat is, one that is both
ecient and innovativeconsists of a heterogeneous set of actors working very closely together.
Voets et al. (2008) noted that existing research on policy networks focuses specically on e-
ciency and eectiveness as measures of network performance, and argued that network activity
entails additional costs, such as democratic quality and capacity building. Thus, the authors
Wu and Knoke
160
employed the discourse of New Public Management to provide new assessment criteria to
measure these other costs of policy network activity.
Another frequently voiced criticism of the policy network approach is its lack of a theoretical
grounding. Consequently, researchers have ample opportunities for developing new ideas and
theoretical frameworks to address this gap. For instance, some researchers (e.g. Knoke 2009;
Siegel 2008) have proposed analyzing policy networks using the concept of political capital,
which is the political network equivalent of social capital (Knoke 2011).
Another possible theoretical framework for policy network research is the incorporation of
the advocacy coalition framework (ACF) to policy network analysis (Weible and Sabatier 2007).
Like policy network analysis, ACF assumes that actors cooperate with allies who share similar
policy preferences and outcomes. Additionally, ACFunlike policy network analysisprovides
researchers with mechanisms that can explain policy changes.
Other researchers have tried incorporating new research methodology into the study of policy
networks. For example, Bevir and Richards (2009) and Pal and Ireland (2009) echo previous
criticism that policy network theory cannot be used to provide causal generalizations, and conse-
quently, legitimate advice to policy-makers. To address this shortcoming, Bevir and Richards
proposed a decentered approach towards the study of policy networks, arguing that research
methods such as textual analysis and ethnography would allow researchers to understand
meanings behind traditions of networksin other words, understanding how network partici-
pants view themselves and their world. In pursuit of a similar goal, Pal and Ireland noted the
importance of creating a comprehensive map of global policy networks so that researchers can
understand broader issues aecting their networks of interests, not just narrow issues and specic
organizations and individuals.
Another critique of policy network theory is that existing theory does a poor job explaining
the genesis and evolution of policy networks. Scholars have tried to address this shortcoming by
incorporating other theoretical lines of thought; for example deLeon and Varda (2009) pro-
posed a theory based on collective action theory to develop structural signatures of exchanges
among network participants. Others oered completely new theories. For example, Provan and
Kenis (2008) proposed three models of governance with distinctive structural properties and
tried to understand why network actors choose to adopt one form over another. Ultimately,
they sought to understand the impact that each form of governance has on network outcomes,
including the evolution of both the network and of governance strategies.
Ideally, policy network research will continue to develop until it achieves characteristics we
take for granted in other more established elds of social research: a distinct and grounded
theoretical framework that explains not only how established policy networks operate, but also
how these networks form and change over time. Additionally, this theoretical framework
should enable interested scholars to generate testable hypotheses and identify distinct variables
which would enable these hypotheses to be tested empirically.
Bibliography
Adshead, M. 2002. Developing European Regions? Comparative Governance, Policy Networks and European
Integration. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Benson, J.K. 1982. A framework for policy analysis, in D.L. Rogers and D. Whetten (eds) Interorganizational
Coordination: Theory, Research and Implementation. Ames, IA: Iowa State University Press.
Bevir, M. and D. Richards. 2009. Decentering policy networks: A theoretical agenda, Public Administration
87: 314.
Browne, W.P. 1998. Groups, Interests, and US Public Policy. Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Press.
Policy network models
161
Burstein, P. 1991. Policy domains: Organization, culture, and policy outcomes, Annual Review of Sociology
17: 32750.
Carpenter, D., K. Esterling and D. Lazer. 2003. The strength of strong ties: A model of contact-making in
policy networks with evidence from US health politics, Rationality and Society 15: 41140.
Compston, H. 2009. Policy Networks and Policy Change . New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
deLeon, P. and D.M. Varda. 2009. Toward a theory of collaborative policy networks: Identifying structural
tendencies, Policy Studies Journal 37: 5974.
Dowding, K. 1995. Model or metaphor? A critical review of the network approach, Political Studies 43:
13658.
—— 2001. There must be an end to confusion: Policy networks, intellectual fatigue, and the need for
political science methods courses in British Universities, Political Studies 49: 89105.
Galaskiewicz, J. 1979. Exchange Networks and Community Politics. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Grant, W. 1978. Insider groups, outsider groups and interest group strategies in Britain, Warwick: University
of Warwick Department of Politics Working Party no. 19.
Greenaway, J., B. Salter and S. Hart. 2007. How policy networks can damage democratic health: A case
study in the government of governance, Public Administration 85: 71738.
Katzenstein, P. 1976. International relations and domestic structures: Foreign economic policies of
advanced industrial states, International Organization 30: 145.
Kenis, P. and V. Schneider. 1991. Policy networks and policy analysis: Scrutinizing a new analytical
toolbox, in B. Marin and R. Mayntz (eds) Policy Networks: Empirical Evidence and Theoretical Considerations.
Boulder, CO, Frankfurt: Campus Verlag and Westview Press.
Kisby, B. 2007. Analyzing policy networks: Towards an ideational approach, Policy Studies 28: 7190.
Knoke, D. 1998. The organizational state: Origins and prospects, Research
in Political Sociology,
8: 14763.
—— 2001. Changing Organizations: Business Networks in the New Political Economy. Boulder, CO: Westview
Press.
—— 2004. The sociopolitical construction of national policy domains, in C.H.C.A. Henning and C. Melbeck
(eds) Interdisziplinäre Sozialforschung: Theorie und empirische Adwendungen. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.
—— 2009. Playing well together: Creating corporate social capital in strategic alliance networks, American
Behaviorial Scientist 52: 1690708.
—— 2011. Policy networks, in J.P. Scott and P. Carrington (eds) The Sage Handbook of Social Network
Analysis, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
——and E.O. Laumann. 1982. The social structure of national policy domains: an exploration of some
structural hypotheses, in P.V. Marsden and N. Lin (eds) Social Structure and Network Analysis. Beverly
Hills, CA: Sage Publications.
——, F.U. Pappi, J. Broadbent and Y. Tsujinaka. 1996. Comparing Policy Networks: Labor Politics in the US,
Germany and Japan. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Laumann, E.O. and F.U. Pappi. 1976. Networks of Collective Action: A Perspective on Community Inuence
Systems. New York: Academic Press.
——, J. Galaskiewicz, and P.V. Marsden. 1978. Community structure as interorganizational linkages,
Annual Review of Sociology 4: 45584.
——and D. Knoke. 1987. The Organizational State: A Perspective on the Social Organization of National Energy
and Health Policy Domains. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
——and F.U. Pappi. 1973. New directions in the study of community elites, American Sociological Review
38: 212230.
Lehmbruch, G. 1984. Concertation and the structure of corporatist networks: Order and conict in
contemporary capitalism, in J.H. Goldthorpe (ed.) Order and Conict in Contemporary Capitalism. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
—— 1989 Institutional
linkages and policy
networks in the federal system of West Germany, Publius 19:
22135.
McGann, J.G. and R. Sabatini. 2011. Global Think Tanks: Policy Networks and Governance. New York:
Routledge.
Maoz, Z. 2010. Networks of Nations: The Evolution, Structure, and Impact of International Networks, 18162001.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Marsh, D. (ed.). 1998. Comparing Policy Networks. Buckingham: Open University Press.
——and R.A.W. Rhodes (eds). 1992. Policy Networks in British Government. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
——and M. Smith. 2000. Understanding policy networks: Towards a dialectical approach, Political Studies
48: 421.
Wu and Knoke
162
——, D. Toke, C. Belfrage, D. Tepe. and S. McGough. 2009. Policy networks and the distinction between
insider and outsider groups: The case of the Countryside Alliance, Public Administration 87: 62138.
Mikkelson, M. 2006. Policy network analysis as a strategic tool for the voluntary sector, Policy Studies 27:
1726.
Pal, L.A. and D. Ireland. 2009. The public sector reform movement: Mapping the global policy network,
International Journal of Public Administration 32: 62157.
Provan, K.G. and P. Kenis. 2008. Modes of network governance: Structure, management, and eectiveness,
Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 18(2): 22952.
Rethemeyer, R.K. 2007. Policymaking in the age of internet: Is the internet tending to make policy
networks more or less inclusive? Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 17: 25984.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 1985. Power dependence, policy communities and inter-governmental networks, Public
Administration Bulletin 49: 429.
—— 1990. Policy networks: A British perspective, Journal of Theoretical Politics 2: 293317.
Richardson, J. 2000 Government, interest groups and policy change, Political Studies 48(5): 100625.
Sandström, A. and L. Carlsson. 2008. The performance of policy networks: The relation between network
structure and network performance, Policy Studies Journal 36: 497524.
Siegel, J. 2008. Contingent political capital and international alliances: Evidence from South Korea,
Administrative Science Quarterly 52: 62166.
Voets, J., W. Van Dooren and F. de Rynck. 2008. A framework for assessing the performance of policy
networks, Public
Management Review 10: 7790.
—— 2004. From
corporatism to lobbyism: A change of paradigm in the theory and analysis of advocacy,
Zeitschrift für Parlamentsfragen, 35: 76176.
von Winter, T. 2001. From corporatism to etatism: Changes in the structure of the German poverty
policy network, Zeitschrift für Politikwissenschaft 11: 1573608.
Weible, C.M. and P.A. Sabatier. 2007. A guide to the advocacy coalition framework: Tips for researchers,in
F. Fischer, G.J. Miller and M.S. Sidney (eds) Handbook of Public Policy Analysis: Theory, Methods, and
Politics. London: CRC Press.
Witte, J. M., W.H. Reinicke and T. Benner. 2000. Beyond multilaterialism: Global public policy networks,
Internationale Politik und Gesellschaft 2: 17688.
Policy network models
163
Part IV
Understanding the
agenda-setting process
13
Policy agenda-setting studies
Attention, politics and the public
Christoffer Green-Pedersen and Peter B. Mortensen
Introduction
The agenda-setting approach has a long tradition in public policy studies. Seminal work by
Schattschneider (1960) and Bachrach and Baratz (1962) pointed to the crucial role of attention
to policy problems. The allocation of attention was the second face of power (Bachrach and
Baratz 1962), and the conict of conicts is crucial in politics (Schattschneider 1960). From these
seminal studies grew the literature known as policy agenda-setting studies (Baumgartner et al. 2006).
The crux of this tradition is precisely the focus on attention. Policy-making cannot be under-
stood without understanding the agenda-setting process, which draws attention to policy pro-
blems that need to be addressed through policy decisions. The rst studies in policy agenda-setting
were classics like Cobb and Elder (1983) and Kingdon (1995). They mostly applied a case study
perspective and focused on how agenda-setting leads to policy decisions. Kingdon (1995: Chapter
23) became inuential in the study of policy decisions from an agenda-setting perspective.
A new tradition in the policy agenda-setting tradition took o with the publication of Baum-
gartner and Jones (1993) seminal book Agendas and Instability in American Politics, which pushed
policy agenda-setting studies in a dierent direction in several related ways. Most notably, while
previous studies focused on the role of agenda-setting dynamics in relation to specic policy
decisions (see e.g. Zahariadis 1995), Baumgartner and Jones (1993) focused on more general
patterns of agenda-setting in political systems. Instead of focusing on individual policy decisions,
they focused on how attention to broader policy issues changed over time and how these changes
paved the way for often dramatic changes in public policy. Another eect of the change in
focus was the establishment of extensive datasets to measure attention dynamics over time and
across a large number of policy issues, for instance through coding of attention to dierent issues
in congressional hearings.
In recent years, the policy agenda-setting tradition has taken a new turn through a surge in
comparative work following the path laid out by Baumgartner and Jones. Part of this work has
been related to a comparative evaluation of the punctuated equilibrium model (see Chapter 12).
However, the recent interest in comparative policy agenda-setting studies goes far beyond
testing the punctuated equilibrium model to an interest in understanding attention dynamics
and how they are shaped by factors like party competition and political institutions. These
167
questions lead to new insights into how public opinion and elections aect public policy. This
chapter reviews this recent trend and focuses on how the new insights into agenda-setting
dynamics inform our understanding of public policy and policy change.
Comparative studies of policy agendas
Over the past ve years, a network of scholars (www.comparativeagendas.org) studying agenda-
setting across a wide range of Western countries has emerged. The network emphasizes attention
dynamics rather than policy change. A central element is the establishment of comparative large-
scale datasets on attention to policy issues in, for instance, executive speeches (e.g. speeches at the
opening of parliament), party manifestos, mass media and parliamentary activities (bills, inter-
pellations, parliamentary questions, etc.). Many of these attention dynamics studies have clear
implications for our understanding of policy dynamics and will therefore be introduced below.
One of the network s research areas is attention dynamics in executive speeches. While they
do not directly represent policy decisions, they often contain a governments policy intentions
or plans for the coming year and therefore their dynamics are of obvious interest in relation to
policy dynamics. Some of the studies test the punctuated equilibrium model (see Chapter 12)
(e.g. John and Jennings 2010); one study of the UK focuses on the responsiveness to public
opinion (Jennings and John 2009); another examines the eect of factors like coalition composition
and government life-cycle in the Dutch context (Breeman et al. 2009).
A central issue for comparative investigation of executive speeches has been the role of elections
and government change (Mortensen et al. 2011). This discussion is closely linked to the politics
matters approach in policy studies. From this perspective, elections are an important driver of
policy change. They often lead to a change in the color of the government and a government of a
dierent color will pursue dierent policy goals (cf. Schmidt 1996; Imbeau et al. 2001). Based on
this theory, one would expect that electionswhen they lead to a change in government color
lead to a change in issue priorities in executive speeches. A government of a dierent color
would focus on dierent policy issues. However, the studies of executive speeches over the past
50 years in three West European countries (the UK, the Netherlands and Denmark) found that
elections and changes in government color had very little eect. Only in the UK, the political
system where one should expect the strongest eect, are there signs of a small eect from a change
in government color (Mortensen et al. 2011). In other words, the color of the government has
surprisingly little eect on the policy agenda of modern governments. The issues and thus policy
problems, which they attend to, seem to be driven by other factors than the color of the government.
Nevertheless, the limited eect of elections and change in government color should not be
interpreted as a sign of no change in the policy priorities of government. In the long run, they
change substantially. Core issues like economy and defense have lost their dominance of executive
agendas (Jennings et al. 2011) and issues like health care, the environment and crime have
gained importance across countries. This does not imply that party competition is irrelevant for
understanding what issues governments prioritize, but rather that we learn little about the
timing of such processes if we focus on elections. To attract attention to issues, political parties
need policy problems dened in a favorable way. And since policy problem developments are
independent of elections, little is gained from focusing on elections when we want to under-
stand the timing of major changes in government agendas. This comparative study indicates that
it is more important whether or not parties nd themselves in government or opposition
because policy responsibility is key to shaping governments prioritization of issue attention.
This idea is further explored in Green-Pedersen and Mortensen (2010). Once a government
holds power, it is also expected to provide solutions to whatever societal problems emerge. So
Green-Pedersen and Mortensen
168
when the banking system collapses, major pollution events happen or the media report on waiting
lists for hospital treatment, it is the government s problem, no matter whether the present
governments policies have caused these problems in any way. Health care is a good example.
All governments in the Western world face a dicult dilemma between a huge surge in the pos-
sibilities of detecting and treating diseases and the need to keep health care costs under control
(Green-Pedersen and Wilkerson 2006). Thus, health care is a policy issue that governments in
the Western world, regardless of party color, have been more or less forced to pay increasing
attention to (Mortensen et al. 2011). Consistent with this idea of the burden of policy
responsibility of being in government, Green-Pedersen and Mortensen (2010) have developed a
model of issue competition that points to the agenda-setting power of opposition parties. A
central implication of the model is that opposition parties are freer to focus continually on issues
that are advantageous to them, whereas government parties are forced to respond more often to
issues brought up on the so-called party system agenda. Using data on issue competition in
Denmark covering 25 years and 23 issue categories, the empirical evaluation of this model clearly
shows how opposition parties are capable of raising issues that the government needs to address
later in executive speeches, for instance.
Paying attention is of course not the same as making policy. However, from an agenda-setting
perspective increasing attention is very likely to lead to policy measures. There are limits to how
much a government can talk about health care, for instance, without doing something in terms
of policy. A recent study of law and order in Denmark (Seeberg 2011) shows that it can lead to
signicant policy changes when opposition parties raise an issue like law and order. The gov-
ernments rst response is most likely to address the issue in speeches, and so on, but if the issue
does not die out in terms of attention, the government will also respond by changing policies,
in this case by introducing longer and stricter sentences. Where the above study of attention to
dierent issues in executive speeches focuses on similarities in attention to issues across coun-
tries, other studies focus on explaining cross-national dierences in attention to policy issues and
investigating the policy consequences. These cross-national studies often focus on cross-national
dierences in how much attention political parties pay to dierent policy issues. The underlying
idea is that certain issues are politicized, which implies that all political parties will pay attention
to them, whether or not they want to.
Green-Pedersen and Krogstrup (2009), for instance, study the politicization of immigration in
Denmark and Sweden. The issue has been politicized in Denmark but not in Sweden and the
explanation for this lies in the composition of the right-wing bloc of parties and the incentives
this oers for mainstream right-wing parties. In Denmark the Liberals and the Conservatives
dominate the right-wing bloc in terms of parliamentary seats. After 1993, when they found them-
selves in opposition, their strategy was to gain a majority with the extreme right. This involved
a successful attempt to politicize immigration, even though it meant a conict with the center-
right party, the Social Liberals, which had supported the right-wing government before 1993.
Sweden only has one mainstream right-wing party: the Conservatives. In terms of gaining a
parliamentary majority, the mainstream right in Sweden is thus very dependent on the three
center-right parties, and collaboration with the extreme right, including an attempt to politicize
immigration, has thus not been an attractive option. The policy consequences of these dierences
in politicization are signicant despite considerable skepticism toward immigration in both coun-
tries. In Denmark the consequence has been a signicant tightening of the rules on immigration
and for acquiring citizenship. This has not happened in Sweden.
The same basic explanatory model, where dierences in party incentives to politicize issues
lead to cross-national dierences in issue politicization, which again generate cross-national
dierences in public policies, has been used to explain cross-national dierences in policies with
Policy agenda-setting studies
169
regard to morality issues like abortion and euthanasia. Green-Pedersen (2007) has investigated
why euthanasia is legal in the Netherlands, but not in Denmark and found that the explanation
was a conict between religious and secular parties in the Dutch party system. In times of
increasing secularization, morality issues have been used by the secular parties to put pressure on
religious parties, such as the Christian Democrats. These parties have based their continuing
electoral survival on issues like the welfare state and on avoiding issues such as abortion where
their distinctive religious prole has become an increasing liability. The secular parties tried to
politicize morality issues by demanding more permissive regulation of abortion and euthanasia,
for instance. In Denmark, there is no conict between religious and secular parties. Political parties
are generally uninterested in morality issues. They are considered non-political, ethical issues,
which are not relevant for party competition. The policy consequences of this denition of the
issues are mixed. On the subject of euthanasia, there has been no drive for permissive regulation
in Denmark, whereas a permissive abortion regulation was adopted in the early 1970s. How-
ever, there has been no general move toward the more permissive regulation that is found in
the Netherlands (cf. also Engeli et al. 2012). The two countries thus dier in their policy prole
on morality issues despite similarities in public opinion. In both countries, there is support for
legalizing euthanasia, but it plays no role in Denmark because of the non-political character of
the issue (Green-Pedersen 2007).
These recent studies all show how important it is to study party incentives and party com-
petition in terms of understanding primarily cross-national di erences in attention to policy issues,
but also cross-national dierences in public policy. The dierence in regulation of euthanasia in
Denmark and the Netherlands cannot be explained without understanding the cross-national
dierences in party incentives to politicization and the same goes for the dierence in immigration
policies between Denmark and Sweden.
Linking attention, public opinion and policy change
While the comparative studies have focused on explaining cross-national variation in attention
to policy issues and then looked at the policy consequences of these changes, other studies have
focused on how agenda-setting actually aects national policy-making. Do changes in the political
agenda foreshadow changes in public policies? And does the eect of changes in the political
agenda depend on the policy preferences expressed by the mass public?
By integrating the study of political agendas with classic assumptions about re-election
oriented representation it has been hypothesized that the political agendadened as the col-
lective attention of elected national policy-makersmatters to public policies, but the direction
of the eect is crucially dependent on the policy opinions expressed by the mass public, because
the potential electoral costs of unpopular policies increase with the issues importance on the
political agenda (see Mortensen 2010).
Macro-political institutions like Congress or national parliaments handle hundreds of issues
every year, most of which are not very important from a re-election perspective because they,
for various reasons, are subject to relatively low or decreasing political attention. Mass media
coverage tends to uctuate with the tides of the political agenda and if an issue does not attract
much attention in macro-political venues like national parliaments or Congress it probably does
not receive much attention among a broader public audience either (see e.g. Bennett 1990;
Bennett et al. 2007). Hence, on many issues national policy-makers have some leeway to leg-
islate as they see t without much concern about being punished at the next election by ret-
rospective voting. On the other hand, debates and activities in macro-political arenas both
reect and reinforce outside attention to the issue. Hence, re-election concerns about a given
Green-Pedersen and Mortensen
170
issue are assumed to rise with increased macro-political attention to that issue (see also Sulkin
2005). When that happens, the argument goes, the majority of the re-election-oriented national
policy-makers seek to change policies toward the position expressed by the mass public on those
issues. In other words, the policy eects of changes in the political agenda depend upon the
policy preferences expressed by a majority of the mass public. For instance, in terms of public
spending the implication is that popular spending issues where most of the public prefers increased
spending do benet in terms of monetary appropriations from increasing attention in the
macro-political arena. Unpopular spending domains where most of the public prefers decreased
public spending, on the other hand, are expected to suer from increasing macro-political atten-
tion. Conversely, in times of decreasing macro-political attention where public opinion (and
hence re-election motives) presumably will be less important to national spending decisions,
unpopular spending domains may benet relatively.
Using public spending as a measure of public policy, this agenda-policy hypothesis has been
evaluated empirically in statistical time series regressions utilizing a Danish dataset of public spending
attitudes, public spending, and the political agenda covering six issues from 1980 to 2003 (see
Mortensen 2010). Across the issues, the results show that public opinion clearly aects policy
changes after taking account of other potentially relevant agenda and spending determinants. For
instance, in popular spending domains (in Denmark issues like law and order, pollution control,
health and primary education where a majority over time and in every poll has expressed a
preference for increased spending), there is a positive relationship between changes in macro-
political attention and changes in public spending on these issues. In unpopular spending domains
(in Denmark these may be issues like defense, development aid and culture) there is a negative
relationship between changes in macro-political attention and changes in public spending.
A theoretically more elaborate version of this basic agenda-policy hypothesis has been pre-
sented and evaluated in a US study of the relationship between changes in congressional attention
and federal budget appropriations across 12 spending domains and 33 years (19702003) (see
Mortensen 2009). The modied claim is that the policy (spending) eects of attention shifts are
strongest when the trade-o between re-election incentives and intensive group interests is low,
which is the case when attention to popular issues peaks and attention to unpopular issues
declines. Put dierently, when popular issues are subject to increased macro-political attention
congressional policy-makers can satisfy both public spending attitudes and specialized spending
advocates by increasing spending on such issues. On the other hand, when popular issues attract
decreasing attention policy-makers may become more hesitant to follow a narrow re-election
incentive and withdraw monetary resources because of (anticipated) erce opposition from vested
spending interests. Thus, in popular spending domains the association between attention and
spending changes is expected to be driven mainly by increased attention followed by relatively
large spending increases, not by decreased attention followed by relatively large budget cuts.
Conversely, in spending domains in which a majority of the US public prefers less spending,
the relationship between congressional attention and public spending may be driven by decreased
congressional attention followed by increased spending investments advocated by special interest in
times of less outside visibility, not by congressional attention peaks paving the way for large pub-
licly supported spending cuts. Subsystem loyalties or erce opposition from groups or agencies with
intensive interests in a given unpopular spending program may not suce to fully avoid cutbacks
during macro-political attention peaks. However, as opposed to popular spending programs,
unpopular programs are certainly not expected to benet from increased macro-political attention,
but to be built up in quieter times of decreasing macro-political attention (see Mortensen 2009).
Utilizing data from the US policy agendas project (see www.policyagendas.org) the empirical
analyses support this conditional model of the agenda-policy relationship. In popular spending
Policy agenda-setting studies
171
domains such as crime, environment, and health where most of the US public in every poll
since 1970 has expressed a preference for increased spending, increases in congressional attention
to these domains are followed by spending increases. In comparison, decreases in attention to
popular spending domains are not to a similar extent followed by spending cuts. The reverse
happens in unpopular spending domains where a majority of the US public in all polls since
1970 has expressed a preference for reduced spending (i.e. space exploration, foreign aid and
welfare). Here, decreases in congressional attention are followed by spending increases, whereas
attention increases do not show a spending eect. In other words, well-organized spending
coalitions working within domains that are not very popular with the general public can better
pursue their spending interests in times of decreasing outside attention and may be able to block
large spending cuts when attention increases.
While these results are consistent with Redfords (1969) classic conception of macro and
subsystem politics (see also Baumgartner and Jones 1993), the two studies oer the rst large N
empirical illustration of these ideas and advocate a more explicit conuence of the policy agenda-
setting perspective developed by Baumgartner and Jones and more mainstream perspectives on
representation and congressional policy-making. Furthermore, they demonstrate that policy chan-
ges also happen when issues are not politicized, but these changes can hardly be explained by
factors like party competition and public opinion.
More important in times of low attention is subsystem politics dominated by organized
interest groups, experts, advocacy coalitions, and bureaucrats with vested interests in the given
subject. A good example of policy change without a major surge in macro-political attention is
tobacco regulation, which in many West European countries has undergone substantial change
over the past few years without being subject to party competition or strong support in public
opinion. Western Europe has seen a surge in restrictions on smoking that is hard to explain by a
surge in macro-political attention (cf. Albæk et al. 2007). Thus, a change in macro-political atten-
tion is an important, but not a necessary condition for policy change, and it is not a satisfactory
stand-alone explanation if we want to understand directions of policy change.
One should note how these agenda-setting-inspired models of the attention-policy link dier
from opinion-policy studies focusing on the broader concept of public saliency (see e.g. Page
and Shapiro 1983; Soroka 2003; Baumgartner and Jones 2004). While the latter tend to focus
on an issues saliency to the public, the former focus on the policy-making process and the
preferences of the relevant policy-makers. For instance, an issue might be salient to the general
public without being subject to macro-political intervention because party competition does
not form around that issue, just as macro-political intervention may anticipate, reduce, or per-
haps even prevent increased public saliency of an issue. Furthermore, some problems do not
have simple cures and will turn into major problems despite political action, but from a gov-
ernmental re-election point of view, it may be too late to respond at that time. In a similar vein,
as also implied by Redfords (1969) distinction between subsystem and macro-political actors, all
policy-makers are most likely neither equally nor constantly concerned about potential voter
reactions. This explicit focus on the policy-makers and the policy-making process also suggests
that one considers not only the majority attitudes of the general public but also the demands
and interests of specialized policy advocates with more intensive interests in the given policy
programs. In other words, the ndings reported in this section seem to call for a more general
model of public policy-making that transcends the classic division between models of electoral
competition and responsiveness to the mass public, on the one hand, and models that stress the
power of special interests and subsystem actors, on the other. In this way, Schattschneiders (1960)
strong legacy is still very signicant in current developments in the literature on agenda-setting
and public policy.
Green-Pedersen and Mortensen
172
Conclusion
While early agenda-setting studies were somewhat narrowly concerned with describing dier-
ent agendas and studying agenda-setting per se, the recent wave of agenda-setting studies is much
more inspired by and in dialogue with other major approaches to the study of public policy.
Examples include literature on party competition, for instance the politics matters approach,
literature on government coalitions, institutionalism, representation and the role of public
opinion, mediatization of politics, as well as more classical literature on public spending and
budgeting.
This, of course, implies that there is no narrow theoretical focus uniting the new scholars of
agenda-setting and public policy, for instance the mandate theory underlying the major research
program on party manifestoes (see e.g. Klingemann et al. 1994). What characterizes the group of
agenda-setting scholars is a common interest in the concept of attention as well as rather strictly
standardized approaches to how agenda-setting data are collected and coded across time and
countries.
Still, it is possible to draw some general insights about what we have recently learned from an
agenda-setting approach to public policy. First, shifts of party governments and elections are not
strongly related to shifts in government agendas and policy. As the review of studies shows, this
does not imply that political parties and their competition for electoral support are unimportant for
political agendas and thus public policies, but only that elections, even when they lead to a change
in government color, are not very central for understanding the dynamic of political agenda and
public policy. Instead, the competition ongoing in-between elections between government and
opposition parties has, for instance, been shown to be important for policy change.
Second, changes in attention have important policy consequences but this does not imply that
policy change only happens as a result of changes in attention, nor does it imply a linear rela-
tionship where changes in attention push public policies in certain directions. Rather, changes
in attention are important for public policy because they change the policy process. When an issue
suddenly reaches the macro-political agenda, factors like party competition and public opinion
become important to explain public policies. When issues receive limited macro-political attention,
public policies are better explained by the nature of the political subsystems related to the issue.
Third, attention to political issues and thus the public policy agenda shows less cross-national
variation than one would expect from an institutional approach. As the health care example showed,
the issues and related problems matter and they might be universal at least across rather closely
integrated (e.g. West European, countries). This does not mean that variation does not exist as the
examples about immigration in Denmark and Sweden and morality issues in Denmark and the
Netherlands showed. However, dierent dynamics of party competition seem to be a more important
cause of variation than institutional dierences.
Bibliography
Albæk, Erik, Christoer Green-Pedersen, Lars Beer Nielsen. 2007. Making tobacco consumption a political
issue in the United States and Denmark: The dynamics of issue expansion in comparative perspective,
Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis: Research and Practice 9(1): 120.
Bachrach, Peter and Morton S. Baratz. 1962. Two faces of power, American Political Science Review 56:
94752.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
—— and Bryan D. Jones. 2004. Representation and agenda-setting, Policy Studies Journal 32(1): 124.
——, Christoer Green-Pedersen and Bryan D. Jones. 2006. Comparative studies of policy agendas, Journal
of European Public Policy 13(7): 95570.
Policy agenda-setting studies
173
Bennett, W. Lance. 1990. Toward a theory of press-state relations in the United States, Journal of
Communication 40(2): 10325.
——, Regina C. Lawrence and Steven Livingston. 2007. When the Press Fails. Political Power and the News
Media From Iraq to Katrina. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Breeman, G., D. Lowery, C. Poppelaars, S. L. Resodihardjo, A. Timmermans and J. de Vries. 2009.
Political attention in a coalition system: Analyzing queens speeches in the Netherlands 19452007,
Acta Politica 44(1): 127.
Cobb, Roger W. and Charles D. Elder. 1983. Participation in American politics. The Dynamics of Agenda-building.
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Engeli, Isabella, Christoer Green-Pedersen and Lars T. Larsen (eds). 2012. Morality Politics in Western
Europe: Parties, Agendas, and Policy Choices. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Green-Pedersen, Christoer. 2007. The conict of conicts in comparative perspective: Euthanasia as a
political issue in Denmark, Belgium, and the Netherlands, Comparative Politics 39(3): 27391.
——and John Wilkerson. 2006. How agenda-setting attributes shape politics: Problem attention, agenda
dynamics and comparative health policy developments in the US and Denmark, Journal of European
Public Policy 13(7): 103952.
——and Jesper Krogstrup. 2009. Immigration as a political issue in Denmark and Sweden, European
Journal of Political Research 47(5): 61034.
——and P.B. Mortensen. 2010. Who sets the agenda and who responds to it in the Danish parliament? A
new model of issue competition and agenda-setting, European Journal of Political Research 49(2): 25781
Imbeau, Louis M., François Petry and Moktar Lamari. 2001. Left-right party ideology and government
policies: A meta-analysis, European Journal of Political Research 40(1): 129.
Jennings, W. and P. John. 2009. The dynamics of political attention: public opinion and the queens
speech
in the United
Kingdom, American Journal of Political Science 53(4): 83854.
——, Shaun Bevan, Arco Timmermans, Laura Chaques, Gerard Breeman, Sylvain Brouard, Christoer
Green-Pedersen, Peter John, Peter B. Mortensen and Anna Palau. 2011. Eects of the core functions of
government on the diversity of executive agendas. Comparative Political Studies 59(1): 7498.
John, P. and W. Jennings. (2010. Punctuations and turning points in British politics: The policy agenda of
the Queens speech, 1940-2005, British Journal of Political Science 40(3): 56186.
Kingdon, John W. 1995. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York: HarperCollins College Publishers.
Klingemann, Hans-Dieter, Richard Hoerbert and Ian Budge. 1994. Parties, Policies, and Democracy.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Mortensen, Peter B. 2009. Political attention and public spending in the United States, Policy Studies
Journal 37(3): 43555.
—— 2010. Political attention and public policy: a study of how agenda-setting matters, Scandinavian
Political Studies 33(4): 35680.
——, Cristoer Green-Pedersen, Gerard Breeman, Laura Chaqués Bonafont, Will Jennings, Peter John,
Anna M. Palau Rogué, Arco Timmermans. 2011. Comparing government agendas: Executive speeches
in the Netherlands, United Kingdom, and Denmark, Comparative Political Studies 44(8): 9731000.
Page, Benjamin I. and Robert Y. Shapiro. 1983. Eects of public opinion on policy, American Political
Science Review 77(1): 17590.
Redford, Emmette S. 1969. Democracy in the Administrative State. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schattschneider, Elmer E. 1960. The Semisovereign People. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Schmidt, Manfred G. 1996. When parties matter: A review of the possibilities and limits of partisan
inuence
on public policy, European Journal of
Political Research 30(2): 15583.
Seeberg, Henrik. 2011. Parties and politics: how policy changes when the opposition party sets the
agenda, Aarhus University Department of Political Science.
Soroka, Stuart N. 2003. Media, public opinion and foreign policy, Harvard International Journal of Press and
Politics 8(1): 2748.
Sulkin, Tracy. 2005. Issue Politics in Congress. Cambridge; Cambridge University Press.
Zahariadis, Nikolaos. 1995. Markets, States and Public Policy: Privatization in Britain and France. Ann Arbor,
MI: University of Michigan Press.
Green-Pedersen and Mortensen
174
14
Focusing events and policy windows
Thomas A. Birkland and Sarah E. DeYoung
Introduction: focusing events in the agenda-setting process
Policy scholars have long argued that the stages model of the policy process is not a useful
model for generating testable hypotheses about policy-making (Nakamura 1987; Sabatier 1988;
Sabatier 1991a, 1991b). But scholars still nd the stages as useful sites for the study of
important elements of the policy process, from problem recognition through implementation
(deLeon 1999). Among the most intensively studied stages is agenda-setting, which is the pro-
cess by which some issues gain and others lose attention among policy-makers and the public.
Agenda-setting is important to all theories of the policy process because the denition of the
alternatives is the supreme instrument of power (Schattschneider 1975: 66). Groupsor, more
specically, advocacy coalitions, in Sabatiers Advocacy Coalition Frameworkengage in rheto-
rical battles, in many dierent venues, to gain access to the agenda while attempting to deny
agenda access to other actors (Cobb and Ross 1997). Group competition, a major driving force
in agenda-setting, can be erce because of the limited capacity of any system or institution to
accommodate all issues and ideas (Walker 1977; Baumgartner and Jones 1993; Cobb and Elder
1983). This competition is over both which problems are most important, and over what causes
and solutions surround any one problem (Hilgartner and Bosk 1988; Lawrence and Birkland
2000, 2004; Birkland and Lawrence 2009). The agenda-setting process is therefore a system of
sifting issues, problems and ideas, and implicitly assigning priorities to these issues.
Focusing events as an aspect of agenda-setting
John Kingdon argues that agenda change is driven by two broad phenomena: changes in indicators
of underlying problems, which lead to debates over whether and to what extent a problem
exists and is worthy of action; and focusing events, or sudden shocks to policy systems that lead to
attention and potential policy change.
John Kingdon used the term focusing event within a general discussion of Focusing Events,
Crises, and Symbols (Kingdon 2003, 94100). Kingdon calls focusing events a little push”“like
a crisis or disaster that comes along to call attention to the problem, a powerful symbol that
catches on, or the personal experience of a policymaker. Kingdon found that some policy
175
domains are less prone to sudden events than are low-visibility policy domains that are prone to
sudden shocks (Birkland 1997) which trigger a great deal of rapid attention, followed by a steep
drop-o in attention after the acute phase of a disaster or crisis (Downs 1972). Kingdon further
notes that focusing events gain their agenda-setting power by aggregating their harms in one
place and time. A plane crash that kills 200 people gets more attention than 200 single fatal car
wrecks; aviation is therefore a domain that is more prone to focusing events than is automobile
safety, where problems tend to be discovered through the accumulation of information. A
starker example in the United States would be the example of the 9/11 attacks, which were
socially, politically, and economically devastating, even though the death toll of about 3,000
people is less than 10 percent of annual road fatalities in the United States. Other problems
cancer, heart disease, other forms of accidentskill far more people than terrorist attacks, but
focusing events are much more sudden, and their harms more easily spoken of in terms of a place
(Oklahoma City) or a time (9/11).
Before Kingdons book was published, there was a broad acknowledgment that disasters and
crises were important in the policy process, but little systematic research on their agenda-setting
power. Cobb and Elder examine events they call circumstantial reactors, such as the 1969
Santa Barbara oil spill, that led to a reconsideration of the whole question of oshore drilling
regulations (1983: 83). Broader ecological change, such as population growth, economic shifts,
and black migration, are also circumstantial reactors, but these changes are much more subtle
than natural disasters or technological accidents, and are therefore less likely to serve as a time
and spacedenite rallying point for group attention and mobilization. As Kingdon argues,
subtle changes are less likely to be viewed as events than are sudden, dramatic, and visible
problems. These elements of the policy process have a greater inuence on the problem stream
and on the accumulation of ideas and evidence to justify policy change.
Traditionally, sudden events were thought to simply bowl over everything standing in the
way of prominence on the agenda (Kingdon 2003: 96). Kingdon portrays focusing events as
being more varied and subtle, and includes as focusing events personal experiences of policy-
makers with matters of personal interest, such as disease that aect them or their families. Kingdon
also argues that the emergence and diusion of a powerful symbol is a focusing event that
acts as reinforcement for something already taking place (2003: 97). When symbols of
events propagatethe elderly woman in New Orleans sheltering herself from the rain with an
American ag, the raising of the ag at Ground Zero in a manner reminiscent of the raising of
the ag at Iwo Jima, or the images of oil-soaked wildlife after oil spillsthese symbols would not
have their power if it were not for the event itself. The propagation of the symbol amplies the
focusing power of the event, particularly if the symbol is particularly evocative (Birkland and
Lawrence 2002). But Kingdon seems to argue that the sudden uptake of a symbol or idea
what scholars in the new media call a memeis itself a focusing event.
Kingdons notion of a focusing event is important, but the term has often been uncritically
adopted
in the literature,
often as a term of art that is never precisely dened. This may be because
Kingdon dened and described focusing events in a way that is too broad to guide focused
empirical research. He conates sudden crises and shocks with individual experience and symbol
propagation that are often reective of what Peter May (1992) calls political learning about more
eective policy arguments, which is less about the idea of focusing attention through an event, the
latter term suggesting a phenomenon that is easily placed in time.
Second, Kingdon compares sudden events with political events, such as protest activity, that
are purposefully caused, such as the 1963 March on Washington for Jobs and Freedom, a key
event in the history of the civil rights movement. Including these events in the denition of
focusing events confuses the role of political mobilization in the politics stream with the
Birkland and DeYoung
176
revelation and depiction of problems in the problem stream. Shocking and sudden focusing
events are not purposefully caused, and can be viewed as exogenous to a policy community or
domain, even if the policies and practices adopted by key members of that community make
such events more likely.
Third, Kingdonsdenition of a focusing event is retrodictive, which is unsurprising given
the nature of his research method. While this denition is suggestive of a way of empirically
studying the agenda-setting eects of events, it was insucient to develop a testable model of
focusing event politics. Birkland (1997, 1998) focused his model of potential focusing events on
policy domains prone to crises more on the crisis and disaster aspect of this denition, a direc-
tion that has been broadly adopted, as we show here. Birkland denes a potential focusing event as
an event that is sudden, relatively rare, can be reasonably dened as harmful or revealing the
possibility of potentially greater future harms, inicts harms or suggests potential harms that are
or could be concentrated on a denable geographical area or community of interest, and that is
known to policy-makers and the public virtually simultaneously (1997: 22).
The term potential highlights that an event may inuence the agenda, but one cannot say
with certainty precisely what, if any, that eect will be, and that one can only study that events
eects compared with a similar class of events. While we may know intuitively that an event
the Deepwater Horizon Oil Spill, 9/11, or Hurricane Katrinawill gain a lot of attention, it is
dicult to know in advance how focal that event will be. Will the event make a more sig-
nicant and discernible dierence on the agenda than competing events and issues? Will that
event have any discernible inuence on policy changes? But we cannot collect a set of events from
one particular class of event and a priori decide that these events are equally and signicantly
inuential. Only careful analysis can do so.
Foundations of focusing event theory
Focusing event theory is part of the broader scholarship on the agenda-setting process; it relies
heavily on the idea that agenda space is limited, and that groups and interests compete for
attention. One strand of this research focuses on the nature of the problems themselves including
their expansion to a larger more attentive audience (Cobb et al. 1976; Cobb and Elder 1983;
Cobb and Ross 1997) and how long that attention may last (Downs 1972). The nature of the
actors and the nature of the problems interact with each other to promote or impede issue
expansion. These theories are important because they help us to understand how groups seek to
nd or express the meaning of an event (Schattschneider 1975; Molotch and Lester 1974, as
cited in Best 2010; Nohrstedt 2010).
A focusing event, by denition, increases attention to a public issue or problem. Baumgartner
and Jones (1993) note that this attention is usually negative attention, and negative attention often
yields further attention, thereby moving issues closer to potential policy changes. However,
political elites do not always resist change, even if policy monopolies are reorganized. Focusing
events, particularly in policy domains characterized as policies without publics, (May 1990) yield
internal mobilization eorts to promote the change that policy elites prefer (Cobb and Elder
1983). Indeed, Best (2010) cites Molotch and Lesters (1975) claim that actor-promoted events
(APEs, in her term) are more likely to generate attention when the actors are elites with which
news media already have steady contacts, and whose actions are considered important by deni-
tion. The messages these actors seek to convey are generally pro-status quo, or at least pro-elite,
to the extent that elites sometimes desire policy change, particularly in policies without pub-
lics (May 1990). Later we consider Bests challenge to this proposition in her groundbreaking
work on purposive events and agenda-setting in the news media.
Focusing events and policy windows
177
A second strand is the use of language, stories, metaphors, and symbols, to advance or retard
issues on the agenda. Contained in this strand is the process of social construction, by which
societies collectively dene and explain the nature and cause of problems. Students of the media
explain how issues gain the attention of journalists, how journalists and their sources use sym-
bols and stories to explain complex issues, and how news consumers respond to these issues and
symbols (Edelman 1967, 1988; Stone 1989, 2002; Majone 1989; Schneider and Ingram 1991).
Related to this is the literature on problem framing in government and the mass media (Entman
1993; Burnier 1994; Lawrence 2000), which has been protably applied to studies of focusing
events (Glascock 2004; Gunter 2005; Liu et al. 2011). Framing theory argues that that participants
in policy debate frame stories about problems to fulll news-gathering routines designed to make
the story both ecient and compelling (Bennett 2003), and to motivate action by its supporters,
inaction by its opponents, or both. These symbols are promoted by a policy entrepreneur, who
is an individualactive in the policy community because of their technical expertise in their eld,
political expertise, and ability to broker deals that lead to new programs and policies (Kingdon
2003; Mintrom 1997; Mintrom and Vergari 1998). Recent studies referencing focusing events
have further restated the roles of policy entrepreneurs (Gunter 2005; Wood 2006). Focusing
events often gain their power from the propagation of symbols, involvement of policy entre-
preneurs, as well as through group mobilizationall of which can overlap with one another in
order to cause momentum for agenda change and potential policy change.
The special role of group coalescence and mobilization
A third theoretical strand that is important for understanding focusing events within the agenda-
setting tradition is group coalescence and mobilization, because of the impact of the nature of
the policy community on the policy process (Baumgartner and Jones 1993: 43). Groups coalesce
to form advocacy coalitions based on mutual interests and values. Sabatier predicts that two to
four advocacy coalitions will form in most policy domains. However, some domains prone to
sudden disasters may be characterized as policies without publics (May 1990), in which policy-
making is often the domain of technical experts, with little public mobilization around particular
policy changes after a major crisis or disaster, (Birkland 1998) beyond the usual diuse claims
that policies should work better in some way. These domains are characterized by one advocacy
coalition, which may be quite weak. In many policy domains characterized by focusing events,
the events drive an internal mobilization eort among existing group members to resolve a
problem about which the public is broadly concerned, but is generally unable or unmotivated
to organize around. In other words, focusing events are not always triggers for mass mobilization or
sustained public attention.
However, policy domains that are part of the broader political and policy debate can see very
intense group activity. Birklands 1997 study found that the earthquake and hurricane policy
domains were very much characterized by an internal mobilization model of agenda-setting and
policy change, while in the oil spill and nuclear power policy domains, there were discernible
advocacy coalitions that were engaged in direct competition. Even here, though, there are impor-
tant dierences. Birkland argued that oil spills have a much greater likelihood of mobilizing
groups to oppose oil shipping and exploration because of the very visible and deeply felt damage
done by these spills, as evidence by images of oily otters after Exxon Valdez, or idled shing
boats after the Deepwater Horizon spill. In this case, oil companies sought to contain the scope
of conict, in Schattschneiders terms, while the highly polarized nuclear power policy domain
was less inuenced by the dominant event, the Three Mile Island nuclear accident. The degree
of polarization therefore inuences post-event politics (Walgrave and Verhulst 2009).
Birkland and DeYoung
178
Focusing events may trigger greater attention to problems and solutions because they increase
the likelihood of more inuential and powerful actors entering the conict on the side of policy
change (Schattschneider 1975; Baumgartner and Jones 1993), by way of greater claims of policy
failure and a more active search for solutions, leading to a greater likelihood of policy change
(Birkland 2006).
But one must not make too much of event-triggered group mobilization. Sometimes we
attribute greater power to events than they deserve. Kingdon notes that we cannot trace the dis-
covery or the propagation of a policy idea to its rst instance, lest we engage in innite
regress. In a similar manner, in some events we have to ask: Which came rst, the problem, or
the event? Among the public there is widespread belief that the Three Mile Island (TMI)
nuclear power plant accident in 1979 was the event that stalled the movement toward more
nuclear power plants for generating electricity. As Baumgartner and Jones note in their chapter
on nuclear power, the policy image of nuclear power had eroded before TMIthe major
milestones in that erosion were the creation of the Nuclear Regulatory Commission (NRC)
and the abolition of the Atomic Energy Commission and its congressional champion, the Joint
Committee on Atomic Energy (JCAE). Birkland (1997: Chapter 5) found that, at the time of
TMI, the nuclear power policy domain was highly polarized and the policy community was
already ercely debating both the meaning of TMI (which was not, is still not, self-evident) and
the nature of nuclear power generally. The lack of one clear interpretation of the nature and
meaning of the TMI accident meant that all the participants in the debate could use the acci-
dent for their own rhetorical ends: as evidence either for the defense in depth notion of
nuclear safety, or for the idea that nuclear power contained unknown risks, that other incidents
were equally or more serious than TMI, and that heretofore poorly understood systems acci-
dents could yield catastrophic disasters (Perrow 1999). In the end, TMI was an important event,
and it was focal in its agenda-setting meaning, but its role in group mobilization and actual
policy-making is less clear.
Apart from group eorts to expand issues, major events often reach the agenda without
group promotion through media propagation of news and symbols of the event. This coverage
of a sudden and shocking event, such as a particularly horric airline crash, or school shooting,
makes the public aware of these events without eorts on the part of group leaders to induce
attention. This media propagation of symbols gives less powerful groups another advantage in
policy debates. Pro-change groups are relieved of the obligation to create and interpret powerful
images and symbols of the problem. Rather, groups only need to repeat the already existing
symbols that the media have seized upon as the most important in the current crisis. These obvious
symbols are likely to carry more emotional weight than industry or governmental assurances
that policy usually works well. Carpenter and Sin (2007) found that the images of fragile chil-
dren who had been poisoned by Sulfanilamide were inuential in triggering a strong outcry that
led to more stringent regulation and licensing for medications in the Food and Drug Act of
1938. Thus, media-generated symbols of health, environmental, or other crises or catastrophes
are often used by groups as an important recruiting tool thereby expanding the issueand as
a form of evidence of the need for policy change.
To conclude, all these theoretical strands assume that agenda-setting is not a neutral, objec-
tive, or rational process. Rather, it is the result of a society, acting through its political and social
institutions, building a consensus on the meanings of problems and the range of acceptable
solutions. There are many possible constructions that compete with each other to tell the story
of why a problem is a problem, who benets or is harmed by the problem, whose fault it is,
and how it can be solved (Guseld 1981; Schneider and Ingram 1991; Schneider 2008; Stone
1989, 2002).
Focusing events and policy windows
179
Some empirical applications of focusing event theory
In this section we show how the application of the focusing event concept can reveal important
features of agenda-setting, group activity, and potential convergence or divergence in what a policy
community deems to be the real problem revealed by a focusing event.
Ab initio, the inuence of a particular event on the formal agenda of the news media and
political institutions should be detectable because focusing events are more sharply dened in
time than are social, demographic, or ideological changes. Take, for example, both news media
and congressional attention to terrorism before and after the September 11 terrorist attacks (Figure
14.1). In this gure, data on the number of New York Times articles and the number of witnesses
appearing before congressional hearings on these issues are normalized to the same scale, for ease
of comparison. The key focusing event in this data is obvious, but the increase in attention is much
more acute in the news media than in Congress. The news media tend to focus to a much
greater extent on the seeming novelty of a particular event itself, while Congress tends to be
seized by the broader problemin this case, terrorismfor a longer time than the media, whose
interest in the broader problem drops o rather rapidly.
The pattern shown in Figure 14.1 is not particularly surprising. But attention is not the same
as the substance of the agenda. Birkland found that the dominant topic of discussion in con-
gressional hearings can change considerably when testimony is oered about a particular event,
compared with testimony about the general problem itself, as shown in Table 14.1.
Differences in the substance of discussion after focusing events
We know that focusing events gain increased attention, and we can plot that attention in terms
of media coverage and congressional activity. However, does the substance or content of the
discussion change in the presence of a recent event from the typical discussion?
Figure 14.1 Comparative attention to terrorism
Source: LexisNexis search for term terrorism in headline, lead, or key terms, by desk; testimony in
LexisNexis congressional testimony database, by term terrorism. Birkland 2006, Figure 2.1
Birkland and DeYoung
180
In most policy domains that are prone to sudden, dramatic events, there are two discernible domi-
nant topics: those that dominate inter-event periods, when focusing events are often dim mem-
ories, and periods in which an issue dominates the agenda as a direct consequence of a recent
event. Table 14.1 reects this proposition. These categories were designed so that parallels could
be drawn among the four domains: the term disaster relief, for example, is roughly analogous
to the term cleanup in the industrial domains because they both involve the immediate response
to a disaster or accident. In all but the hurricane domains, the dominant issue on the agenda
changes when an event is specically mentioned. In the other domains, the existence of an event
on the agenda inuences the actual substance of discussion in the domain. The oil spill and
nuclear power policy domains have at two broad advocacy coalitions, generally a pro-industry
and pro-environment coalition. There appears to be one advocacy coalition in earthquake policy,
a professional community that works to educate Congress and to advocate for policy change intra-
disaster. Such a community is not present, or not called upon, by Congress, and most testimony
in the hurricane domain is therefore about the rapid and generous delivery of disaster relief.
This research led Birkland to suggest that focusing events led to a convergence of opinion
about the nature of problems on the agenda, and to assume that an event led to something like
convergence toward a policy solution. Indeed, in the oil spill domain, this supposition was
strongly conrmed by the passage of the Oil Pollution Act of 1990 soon after the Exxon Valdez
oil spill; the oil spill broke a 14-year legislative logjam. This convergence proposition was also built
on the normative conviction that there should be some convergence on one or very few problem
denitions, which should yield a narrow range of policy options from which to choose.
Contrary to this supposition, Hilgartner and Bosk (1988) and Lawrence (2000) argued that
the elevation of an issue on the agenda can yield a competition over how to frame or describe the
problem, thereby creating a proliferation of causal stories (Stone 1989) about why some events
happened, and what should be done. Lawrence and Birkland found that in the case of a parti-
cular focusing eventthe Littleton school shootingsconsiderable attention was paid to the
school violence problem, broadly conceived, but the causal stories vary considerably, as shown
in Figure 14.2.
Here, we see considerable divergence in the dominant frames or causal stories, where the news
media assigned more importance to guns, rank and le members of Congress to guns, pop culture,
and a potpourri of other causes, while the creation of additional school programsor the increased
funding or enforcement e ort devoted to themwas the modal frame in legislation. The expla-
nation is simple: Congress, not being directly responsible for the management of schools, politically
constrained on the gun issue, and constitutionally constrained to regulate speech and expression,
settled on where it can have the most visible inuence. In this case, Congress, in seeking a policy
solution, largely turned to distributive spending to encourage greater eorts by schools to engage
in a wide range of social service programs to prevent school violence (Birkland and Lawrence 2009).
Table 14.1 The substance of the agenda when events are or are not mentioned in testimony
Testimony on specic event All other testimony All testimony
Earthquake Disaster relief NEHRP Disaster relief
Hurricane Disaster relief Disaster relief Disaster relief
Oil spill Spill cleanup and costs Liability, compensation
and costs
Liability, compensation
and costs
Nuclear Power Cleanup Licensing Licensing
Source: Birkland (1998), Table 1
Focusing events and policy windows
181
Finally, it is possible to study the ideas contained in legislation in a disaster-prone domain and
consider whether legislative ideas converge to a focused few ideas, or expand to cover much
wider ground. The results of this analysis are provided in Table 14.2, which shows the main ideas
contained in legislation that followed major aviation security incidents (including the aftermath
of the 1996 ValuJet and TWA crashes, the latter of which was widely believed to have been the
result of a terrorist bombing, even though it was not).
This empirical work shows that thinking on focusing events has evolved, from the simple
idea that focusing events bowl over other issues, to the more sophisticated idea that focusing
events have variable inuences on policy communities, on the nature of policy debate, and the
content of policy ideas in dierent policy domains.
Broader applications of the focusing event idea
Since Birklands (1997) renement of Kingdons (2003) denition of focusing events, other scholars
have applied or mentioned focusing event theory as an important aspect of the policy process.
This work generally falls into three broad categories: research that cites Kingdon or Birkland
uncritically, accepting the denitions without any critical analysis, often simply to acknowledge
that events matter; work that cites Kingdon or Birkland and use the focusing event theory to
build, reinforce, or expand the denitions of focusing events and their causal mechanisms; and
work that seems to us to misapply the focusing event concept to other phenomena that better
explain the processes being described.
A great deal of work relies on Kingdons or Birklands discussion of focusing events by simply
acknowledging the importance of focusing events, without careful dissection of agenda-setting
theory. Works that cite Kingdon only (e.g. Oakley 2009; Prince 2010; Vaughan and Arsneault
Figure 14.2 Dominant problem frames in school violence, by venue
Source: Based on Table 1 in Lawrence and Birkland (2004)
Birkland and DeYoung
182
Table 14.2 Key issues addressed in aviation security legislation
Topic Aviation Security
Improvement Act
of 1990
Federal Aviation
Authorization Act
of 1996
Federal Aviation
Administration
Authorization Bill
Airport Security
Improvement Act
of 2000
Aviation and
Transportation
Security Act
Homeland
Security Act
of 2002
Airport access control
Baggage matching 
Background checks of employees 
Cargo and mail security 
Cockpit security
Employee ID systems
Explosives and explosives detection 
Create or restore air marshals
Modify existing organizations
Create new organizations 
Passenger proling 
Allow pilots to carry fatal weapons 
Allow pilots to carry nonfatal weapons
Certication of screening companies
Require screening personnel be US citizens
Require all airport personnel be screened
(including ight crews)
Screenersgeneral issues
Make screeners federal employees 
Provide security training to the aircrew
Provide security training to pilots
Total 7 8 1 1 17 5
Source: Birkland (2004).
2008) are works that contain overviews of major agenda-setting theory, with a focus on the
streams model, but that fall short of carefully dierentiating focusing events from other drivers
of agenda change. Similarly, works that cite Birkland but not Kingdon (e.g. Ackleson 2005;
Chenoweth and Clarke 2010; Davis 2006; Einsiedel 2000; Melis and Pulwarty 2001; Verhulst
and Walgrave 2009) often simply recapitulate Birklandsdenition of a focusing event testing
the denition or the underlying theory. The second body expands on theory by applying a case
and then building an argument for whether the case or event can be considered as a focusing
event, usually by using quantitative and qualitative data to reinforce or analyze how the case adheres
to the focusing event concept. These studies may also reconsider the denition of focusing events
in light of the new data and interpretation. For example, Busenberg (2000) makes an interesting
case for the second-order eects of policy changes that can be engendered by focusing events.
He showed how the enactment of the Oil Pollution Act (OPA) of 1990 soon after the Exxon
Valdez oil spill created an atmosphere in which coalitions and oil companies were more willing
to collaborate to prevent and mitigate future spills, and that the OPA induced companies more
open to innovative strategies than they had been before the spill and the OPA.
A particularly promising study is Bests (2010) analysis of how local newspapers in Denver
treated news events related to homelessness. Best coded story frames to consider, among other
things, whether stories were episodic or thematic, and whether the events being covered were
actor promoted events (APEs) or non-actor promoted events (NAPEs). Best draws on a wide
range of literature on problem framing to develop sophisticated models to nd that NAPEs
were highly likely to trigger thematic stories about the problem of homelessness, which appears
to support the idea, implicit in Birklands work and explicit in work by Lawrence (2000) and
Molotch and Lester (1975) that NAPEs will trigger greater thematic coverage. But, as we descri-
bed earlier, the idea that an event triggers a broader discussion does not mean that the potential
explanations in the media focus on broader systemic problems.
Best found that, in news coverage of high-prole murders of homeless men in Denver, news-
papers were more prone to problematize (in Lawrences term) individual choices to remain
homeless than they were to cast light on systemic causes of homelessness. Contrary to her
expectations, APEs were found to be more likely to challenge the status quo, which Best claims
is contrary to Molotch and Lesters theory that APEs promote the status quo. But focusing
event theory and agenda-setting theory could explain the pro-change orientation of elites as a
form of internal mobilization among a set of elite who perceive homelessness to be a problem
deserving attention and policy change. Best also notes that the articles that contained content
that promoted change and homelessness amelioration were most often written or promoted by
organizations that were dedicated to social change (2010: 87).
The third category of literature is characterized by a form of overreaching in which other
phenomena are characterized as focusing events. For example, Collins and Kapuçu (2008) discuss
the importance of warning systems for tornadoes, using tornadoes as a focusing event. But
their use of the term is synonymous with a presumably attention-grabbing event (the tornado
itself). Indeed, many uses of the term do not delve beyond this meaning.
Another common misuse of the concept comes when the surprising result of an election is
cited as a focusing event, as when Béland (2005) and Blankenau (2001) state or imply that the
1991 election of Harris Woord to the US Senate was a focusing event that propelled health
care reform onto the agenda. In Kingdons streams metaphor, these surprising results are best
understood as a change in the political stream that can be harnessed, as was done by health care
reformers, to claim that the political atmosphere has changed such that a window of opportu-
nity for policy change is more likely. An election is not a focusing event because it is expected,
planned, and part of normal governmental routine. And it is very dicult to discern whether
Birkland and DeYoung
184
Woords election was more a reection of growing attention to health care reform than a trigger
of it. In any case, the election is better accommodated in other aspects of Kingdons model, and
need not be force-tted into the focusing event framework.
Similarly, some researchers imply that indicators are synonymous with focusing events, and
they confuse an indicator change with a focusing event, as in the following inference: Indicators
are inherently interconnected with focusing events and feedback in the sense that they reect an
objective measure of the former and are prone to subjective constructs regarding the latter
(Galland and McDaniels 2008: 519). This claim is problematic because indicators are as much sym-
bols as they are facts. But while the essential idea that indicators and focusing events interact is a good
insight, what distinguishes the agenda-setting power of a focusing event is its symbolic power in a
particular place and time, not in indicators of a problem. This is not to deny the idea that a focusing
event can trigger a search for more and better indicators of the problem revealed by the event.
Finally, we also found examples in which focusing events are mentioned without reference
to the literature at all, as when Green-Pederson (2007: 624) argues that Focusing events are
hard to predict or even include in variable-oriented explanations. The latter claim may be true,
but without any theoretical warrant or appeal to the literature as the basis for this claim.
Most of the studies we found were not comparative studies of similar types of events within a
broader class of events, such as disasters or natural disasters or industrial accidents. Birk-
lands 1997 study revealed considerable dierences in the outcomes of event-driven debates. By
contrast, the studies we reviewed here made few such comparisons of policy community com-
parisons for matching focusing events with corresponding communities. Most research focuses
on policy changes over time in connection with one event in one community. (e.g. Carpenter
and Sin 2007) or comparing the policy dierences across countries (Lowry 2006), rather than across
events within similar domains, such as Birklands (1997) comparison of hurricane and earthquake
coalition organization.
Fishman (1999) makes a valuable distinction between Type One (common) and Type Two
(novel) focusing events. This distinction is crucial in understanding the way in which the event
may cause a window of opportunity (Kingdon 2003) because the event type will have varying
contextual factors that will inuence possible policy solutions, as well as on framing and symbol
propagation.
Conclusion and future directions: focusing events and policy change
A common feature of the focusing event literature is that it often enthusiastically applies the
focusing event concept to all manner of events. Many of these events are not rare, or sudden, or
harmful, in the sense that Birklandsdenition suggests. For those policy domains in which
focusing events are important one can at least make a prima facie case that events can often be
precursorsor, if we might be so bold, to be triggersof policy change. Birkland shows this
phenomenon in studying how the Exxon Valdez oil spill broke a 14-year-long legislative
deadlock over comprehensive oil spill liability legislation. The September 11 terrorist attacks are
widely understood to have triggered major policy change in the United States (in the form of
homeland security initiatives and the restructuring of the Federal Emergency Management
Agency (FEMA) into the Department of Homeland Security (DHS)), although the shape and
nature of that change is very broad and cannot be said to have resulted from some sort of
sudden consensus about the problem revealed by the event. Instead, the event inuenced many
policy communities and policy regimes (May et al. 2006). But the mechanism by which agenda
change is turned into policy change is not yet well dened; we can tell stories about these
changes, but the theory remains thin.
Focusing events and policy windows
185
Birkland (2006) outlined a theory of event-driven policy change and learning which is beyond
the scope of this chapter. To summarize, he argues that focusing events reveal policy failures
which are the fodder for interest group debate, because these failures reveal the problems that
policy entrepreneurs join to solutions in the post-event window of opportunity. But, as we have
discussed, any event is a potential focusing event that has the potential to open a window, and, even
if the window opens, has the potential to yield policy change. Birklands model allows, therefore,
for an accumulation of knowledge driven by events, until, at some point, an event brings together
all other event-driven knowledge at a point where it is possible for the policy system to show
evidence of learning from the accumulation of events. This formulation is attractive, because
it ties to the literature on ideas and learning from the policy process and from organizational
theory. However, these bodies of literature are not fully reconciled in a way that would support
policy change. But recent research shows that the theoretical construction is promising and can
be accommodated in broader theoretical frameworks, such as the ACF (Albright 2011).
Among the works we reviewed for this chapter, there seems to be a sensenot explicitly stated,
howeverthat Birklandsdenition of focusing event may be so restrictive that there would be
few events to study, thereby dening too small a set of phenomena as focusing events. The varia-
bility of the implicit or explicit denitions of the term focusing event suggest that it may be
useful to attempt to create some categories or typologies of events, much as Birkland (1997:
Chapter 6) did. Neither Birkland nor other scholars have followed up on these tentative categories
with more careful research, but Fishmans (1999) notion of Type One and Type two events is
promising. To the extent that future research is undertaken on focusing events, our goal should
be to improve the explanatory and predictive power of any theory of these events. Such a
theory should lend itself to replication and testing across multiple policy domains over many
years. A good foundation has been laid in the social sciences, and with continued sudden, dra-
matic, and unsettling events gaining attention, there is no paucity of cases or of policy domains
subject to these events, all of which provide fruitful material for research.
Bibliography
Ackleson, Jason. 2005. Border security technologies: Local and regional implications, Review of Policy
Research 22(2): 13755.
Albright, Elizabeth A. 2011. Policy change and learning in response to extreme ood events in Hungary:
An advocacy coalition approach, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 485511.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Béland, D. 2005. Ideas and social policy: An institutionalist perspective, Social Policy and Administration
39(1): 118.
Bennett, W. Lance. 2003. News, The Politics of Illusion. New York: Longman.
Best, R. 2010. Situation or social problem: The inuence of events on media coverage of homelessness,
Social Problems 57(1): 7491.
Birkland, Thomas A. 1997. After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy and Focusing Events. Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press.
—— 1998. Focusing events, mobilization and agenda setting, Journal of Public Policy 18(3): 53 74.
—— 2004. Learning and policy improvement after disaster: The case of aviation security, American
Behavioral Scientist 48(3): 34164.
—— 2006. Lessons of Disaster. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
—— and Regina G. Lawrence. 2002. The social and political meaning of the Exxon Valdez oil spill, Spill
Science and Technology Bulletin 7(12) (June): 1722.
——and Regina G. Lawrence. 2009. Media framing and policy change after Columbine, American
Behavioral Scientist 52(10): 140525.
Blankenau,
Joe. 2001. The fate
of national health insurance in Canada and the United States: A multiple
streams explanation, Policy Studies Journal 29(1): 3855.
Birkland and DeYoung
186
Burnier, DeLysa. 1994. Constructing political reality: Language, symbols and meaning in politics: A
review essay, Political Research Quarterly 47(1): 23953.
Busenberg, George J. 2000. Innovation, learning and policy evolution in hazardous systems, American
Behavioral Scientist 44(4): 67991.
Carpenter, Daniel and Gisela Sin. 2007. Policy tragedy and the emergence of regulation: The Food, Drug
and Cosmetic Act of 1938: 1, Studies in American Political Development 21(2): 149.
Chenoweth, E. and S.E. Clarke. 2010. All terrorism is local: Resources, nested institutions and governance
for urban homeland security in the American federal system, Political Research Quarterly 63(3): 495507.
Cobb, Roger W. and Charles D. Elder. 1983. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-
Building. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
——and Marc Howard Ross. 1997. Cultural Strategies of Agenda Denial: Avoidance, Attack, and Redenition.
Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
——, Jeannie-Keith Ross and Marc Howard Ross. 1976. Agenda building as a comparative political
process, American Political Science Review 70(1): 12638.
Collins, Matthew, L. and Naim Kapuçu. 2008. Early warning systems and disaster preparedness and
response in local government, Disaster Prevention and Management 17(5): 587600.
Davis, Charles. 2006. Western wildres: A policy change perspective, Review of Policy Research 23(1): 11527.
deLeon, Peter. 1999. The stages approach to the policy process: What has it done? Where is it going,in
Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Downs, Anthony. 1972. Up and down with ecology: The issue attention cycle, The Public Interest 28
(Summer): 3850.
Edelman, Murray J. 1967. The Symbolic Uses of Politics. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.
—— 1988. Constructing
the Political Spectacle.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Einsiedel, Edna F. 2000. Cloning and its discontents; A Canadian perspective, Nature Biotechnology 18(9):
94344.
Entman, Robert M. 1993. Framing: Toward classication of a fractured paradigm, Journal of Communication
42(4): 519.
Fishman, Donald, A. 1999. ValuJet Flight 592: Crisis communication theory blended and extended,
Communication Quarterly 47(4): 345.
Galland, Daniel and Timothy McDaniels. 2008. Are new industry policies precautionary? The case of
salmon aquaculture siting policy in British Columbia, Environmental Science and Policy 11(6) (October):
51732, doi:10.1016/j.envsci.2008.05.002.
Glascock, Jack. 2004. The Jasper dragging death: Crisis communication and the community newspaper,
Communication Studies 55(1): 29.
Green-Pedersen, Christoer. 2007. The growing importance of issue competition: The changing nature
of party competition in Western Europe, Political Studies 55(3): 60728.
Gunter, Valerie J. 2005. News media and technological risks, Sociological Quarterly 46(4): 67198.
Guseld, Joseph. 1981. The Culture of Public Problems: Drinking Driving and the Symbolic Order. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Hilgartner, James and Charles Bosk. 1988. The rise and fall of social problems: A public arenas model,
American Journal of Sociology 94(1): 5378.
Kingdon, John W. 2003. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies, 2nd edn, Longman Classics in Political
Science. New York: Longman.
Lawrence, Regina G. 2000. The Politics of Force: Media and the Construction of Police Brutality. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
——and Thomas A. Birkland. 2000. The politics of event driven problem denition: School violence,
media frames, and policy responses,
paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political
Science Association. Washington,
DC.
——and Thomas A. Birkland. 2004. Guns, Hollywood, and criminal justice: Dening the school shootings
problem across public arenas, Social Science Quarterly 85(5): 1193207.
Liu, X.S., E. Lindquist and A. Vedlitz. 2011. Explaining media and congressional attention to global climate
change, 19692005: An empirical test of agenda-setting theory, Political Research Quarterly 64(2): 40519.
Lowry, William. 2006. Potential focusing projects and policy change, Policy Studies Journal 34(3): 31335.
Majone, Giandomenico. 1989. Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
May, Peter J. 1990. Reconsidering policy design: Policies and publics, Journal of Public Policy 11(2): 187206.
—— 1992. Policy learning and failure, Journal of Public Policy 12(4): 33154.
Focusing events and policy windows
187
——, Joshua Sapotichne and Samuel Workman. 2006. Policy coherence and policy domains, Policy Studies
Journal 34(3): 381403.
Melis, T.S and Pulwarty, R.S. 2001. Climate extremes and adaptive management on the Colorado River:
Lessons from the 19971998 ENSO event, Journal of Environmental Management 63(3): 307.
Mintrom, Michael. 1997. Policy entrepreneurs and the diusion of innovation, American Journal of Political
Science 41(3) (July): 73870.
——and Sandra Vergari. 1998. Policy networks and innovation diusion: The case of state education
reforms, The Journal of Politics 60(1): 12648.
Molotch, Harvey and Marilyn Lester. 1974. News as purposive behavior, American Sociological Review
39(February): 10113.
——and Marilyn Lester. 1975. Accidental news: The great oil spill as local occurrence and national event,
American Journal of Sociology 81(2): 235 61.
Nakamura, Robert T. 1987. The textbook policy process and implementation research, Policy Studies
Journal 7(1): 14254.
Nohrstedt, D. 2010. Do advocacy coalitions matter? Crisis and change in Swedish nuclear energy policy,
Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 20(2): 30933.
Oakley, M.R. 2009. Agenda setting and state policy diusion: The eects of media attention, state court
decisions and policy learning on fetal killing policy, Social Science Quarterly 90(1): 16478.
Perrow, Charles. 1999. Normal Accidents Replacement: Living With High-Risk Technologies. Princeton NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Prince,
M.J. 2010. Avoiding blame,
doing good, and claiming credit: Reforming Canadian income
security, Canadian Public AdministrationAdministration Publique du Canada 53(3): 293322.
Sabatier, Paul A. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy-oriented
learning therein, Policy Sciences 21: 12968.
—— 1991a. Political science and public policy and toward better theories of the policy PR, PS: Political
Science and Politics 24 (June):14456.
—— 1991b. Toward better theories of the policy process, PS: Political Science and Politics 24(2): 14456.
Schattschneider, E.E. 1975. The Semisovereign People. Hinsdale, IL: The Dryden Press.
Schneider, Anne and Helen Ingram. 1991. The social construction of target populations: Implications for
politics and policy, American Political Science Review 87(2): 33448.
Schneider, Saundra. 2008. Whos to blame? (Mis) perceptions of the intergovernmental response to disasters,
Publius: The Journal of Federalism 38(4) (September 1): 71538. doi:10.1093/publius/pjn019.
Stone, Deborah A. 1989. Causal stories and the formation of policy agendas, Political Science Quarterly 104
(2): 281300.
—— 2002. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making. New York: Norton.
Vaughan, Shannon K. and Shelly Arsneault. 2008. Not-for-prot advocacy: Challenging policy images
and pursuing policy change, Review of Policy Research 25(5): 41128.
Verhulst, J. and S. Walgrave. 2009. The rst time is the hardest? A cross-national and cross-issue comparison
of rst-time protest participants, Political
Behavior 31(3): 45584.
Walgrave, S.
and J. Verhulst. 2009. Government stance and internal diversity of protest: A comparative
study of protest against the war in Iraq in eight countries, Social Forces 87(3): 135587.
Walker, Jack L. 1977. Setting the agenda in the US senate: A theory of problem selection, British Journal
of Political Science 7: 42345.
Wood, Robert S. 2006. Tobaccos tipping point: The master settlement agreement as a focusing event,
Policy Studies Journal 34(3): 41936.
Birkland and DeYoung
188
15
Agenda-setting and
political discourse
Major analytical frameworks and
their application
David A. Rochefort and Kevin P. Donnelly
Three questions are central to the agenda-setting perspective in public policy analysis:
1 Among all competing concerns of individuals and groups, what determines which ones will
succeed in gaining the active attention of political decision-makers?
2 How do problems and solutions come to be matched together in public policy formulation?
3 Who are the key actors in agenda-setting, and by what means do they pursue their objectives?
At times, circumstances are such that it is neither puzzling nor questionable why ocials would
be preoccupied with a given predicament. That is, the perception of threat is so reexive, the
dimension of calamity so tangible and evident, no intermediation is necessary between social
awareness of a problem, on the one hand, and government engagement, on the other. Yet issues
of this type, which do not merely occupy space on the radar screen of government but command it,
are exceptional. The broader class of misfortunes and ills in society do not receive automatic attention
from public policy-makers. Rather, they must vie for standing within an appropriate institutional
arenalegislative, administrative, or judicialalready busy with matters current and pending.
Powerful interests outside and inside government can be inuential in gaining consideration
for an issue. However, the more visible an issue, the more widespread its signicance, and the
more controversial its claims, the less likely will it be that some narrow group of actors, however
well positioned and resourceful, might control its fate. In the politics of public policy-making,
most issues are malleable entities subject to interpretation and prioritization in a contest over the
construction of meaning. Although factual information helps to document a problems existence,
rarely is there consensus about which facts are most relevant, how they should be assembled to
create a picture of the whole, or what the implications are concerning those things government
should, or should not, do in remedying a situation. Sorting out these possibilities may be
likened to an exercise in collective political cognition, one rooted in opinion, values, and beliefs
as much as objective analysis.
189
The argumentative turn in policy studies is a phrase that has come into usage as a way of
referring to the critical role of discourse within this disorderly process (Fischer and Forester
1993). Majone has written:
Argumentation is the key process through which citizens and policymakers arrive at moral
judgments and policy choices. Public discussion mobilizes the knowledge, experience, and
interest of many people, while focusing their attention on a limited range of issues. Each
participant is encouraged to adjust his view of reality, and even to change his values, as a
result of the process of reciprocal persuasion.
(1989: 2)
Language is more than just a serviceable instrument of con ict and compromise in public debate,
however. Language can also be a vehicle for expressing identity, arming or challenging the
hierarchical status quo, and embedding discussion of issue specics within larger categories of
social understanding (see, e.g., Edelman 1988). All are pertinent to a politys response to demands
for change through eective policy choice.
The purpose of this chapter is to review three major veins of research on the role of political
discourse in public policy development with special focus on the identication and typing of
issues within the agenda-setting phase. The three areas of scholarship are problem denition,
framing, and political narrative. Each possesses elements distinctive from the concerns and approa-
ches of the other two, although important points of overlap exist. All perspectives arise from
multiple disciplinary sources. Perhaps owing to this intellectual admixture, scholars situated
within particular literatures often have not adequately acknowledged the relevance of similar
work in other elds. Our aim, therefore, is to promote a synthesis toward greater interrelationship
and accumulation of knowledge going forward. Following an overview of main concepts
within these parallel bodies of work, we will demonstrate their applicability via a pair of case
studies of recent public policy controversies in Great Britain and the United States.
Problem denition
In a slim volume called The Semisovereign People published in 1960, E. E. Schattschneider out-
lined an understanding of the linkage among social conict, issue creation, and government
response that continues to inspire research and writing in the public policy eld several decades
later. Schattschneiders main interest was the mobilization of bias determining which concerns
get organized into and out of the political game. One critical asset in the competition for
political attention is large-scale public support, which can either be enhanced or reduced by the
way an issue is dened. Indeed, for Schattschneider, the denition of the alternatives is the
supreme instrument of power (1960: 69).
Building on this work, Cobb and Elder (1972) elaborated a model of agenda-setting that
identies issue characteristics as a key factor in conict expansion. In general, issues successfully
cast in terms of certain qualitiesambiguity and abstraction, social signicance, long-term rele-
vance, lack of technical complexity, and familiaritypossess greater potential for visibility and
salience. Thus, the description of issues, or problems, by policy entrepreneurs can be an impor-
tant strategy for gaining advantage in the process of political gate keeping that limits the policy
agenda (Kingdon 1995).
As noted by Cobb et al. (1976: 126), Agenda building is a process ideally suited to com-
parative analysis (see also Baumgartner et al. 2006). This is so because all political communities
face the same basic challenge of deciding which issues should be given priority in ocial
Rochefort and Donnelly
190
decision-making. These scholars suggest a framework for cross-cultural investigation centering
on the major characteristics of issue careers, including the way public issues are initiated, the degree
to which issue demands are specic or general in form, the process of issue expansion, and an
issues method of entrance onto the formal agenda. Use of language is pervasive across these
dimensions of the policy process and can help to explain both issue-specic and regime-specic
tendencies.
Rochefort and Cobb (1993, 1994) examined more closely the categories of claims within the
discourse of problem denition. Providing an anatomy of problem description, they focused
on ve areas of discussion that repeatedly arise in political debate over social issues: problem
causation; nature of the problem (severity, incidence, novelty, proximity, crisis status); character-
istics of the problem population; end-means orientation of problem dener; and nature of the
solution. In eect, this listing of categories provides a template for analyzing problem denition
as a distinctive form of rhetoric made up of a habitual vocabulary (1994: 15).
Each of these dimensions of description can be addressed in a way calculated to maximize a
problems perceived importance and handling as a public issue rather than as a private trouble
(Mills 1959). Problems attributed to social causes beyond individual control, that are widespread
in scope, have severe impacts, threaten the average citizen, have reached a dangerous crisis
point, involve sympathetic problem populations, and point to solutions viewed as eective and
aordable represent predictable items of attention inside the political arena. At the same time,
the polarity of these same dimensions can be reversed by problem deners seeking to contain
public support for an issue and deem it unworthy of decision-makers precious time and resources.
Hirschman (1991) identied a counter-rhetorical strategy evident across various periods of history
to undermine reform proposals by portraying them as perverse (likely to backre), futile
(beyond the eective capability of government), and jeopardizing (prone to damage an existing
policy or system). Hirschman presents these arguments as the archetypal conservative response
to progressive proposals, although they are equally apt in patterning the discourse of objection
by liberals to policy innovations from the political right.
As Stone (2002) notes, the language of counting is prominent in problem denition. Num-
bers serve to document both the occurrence of a problem and its impacts. Numbers may lend
the appearance of precision to policy arguments, but, in fact, they are subject to manipulation,
open to diering interpretations, and can acquire symbolic meanings just as happens with words
and images. It is not merely that most social problems are associated with high and low
est
imates.
Measurements can dier widely as a result of time frame selected, categorization of people
and events, the reference points and comparisons used in establishing context, and other choices
supportive of, or detrimental to, the interests of a problem dener.
In the eort to persuade, practitioners of problem denition resort to language that is factual
and language that is gurative, sometimes combining the two for maximum impact. Figurative
language refers to words, phrases, and comparisons that convey meanings beyond their literal con-
tent. Analogies are statements that compare problems, or issues, by asserting a logical equiva-
lence, often leaving to inference the nature and extent of similarities between the two.
Analogies can be used to underscore the severity of a situation, suggest causal relationships, and
make predictions about the likely outcome of policy action or neglect. Metaphors are a closely
related form of comparison that link items through implied argument. British scholar Adrian
Beard (2000) observes: Metaphor is deeply embedded in the way we construct the world
around us and the way that world is constructed for us by others (p.21). Especially prominent
in the world of politics, Beard notes, are metaphors of sport and war.
One area of problem denition scholarship that draws directly from the discipline of sociol-
ogy, particularly the social construction of reality perspective, is the consideration of problem
Agenda-setting and political discourse
191
ownership (see, e.g., Guseld 1981). Sometimes what is at stake in denitional disputes is the
determination of which group in society will gain recognition as established experts for explaining
and resolving a given social problem. Status, inuence, and resources all potentially hinge on
which professional, disciplinary, or moral point of view wins out.
Although problem denition is integral in issue creation, it also relates to the function of
policy design. Causation is a basic feature of description that can steer attention to a certain method,
level, or object of government intervention because it is in keeping with a problems attributed
origins. Sometimes problems achieve agenda standing when they are dened as well suited for
the application of a policy approach already well established and widely supported. In this sense,
it is said, solutions give rise to problems, as well as the other way around. Characterization of
problem populations the individuals and groups who are seen as aected by, or the source of,
a social problemconditions the types of instruments viewed by policy-makers as appropriate
forms of treatment due to judgments about blame, deservingness, deviancy, and potential for
change. Not just the substance of programmatic action, namely benets and burdens, is shaped
by these components of problem denition, but also the techniques of program implementation
and the rhetoric that imbues the chosen policy (Schneider and Ingram 1997; Rochefort 1986).
Framing
That reality is complex, multidimensional, inherently confusing, and overwhelming in its entirety
constitutes the fundamental premise of the framing perspective. A natural cognitive process is
to narrow the eld of perception to make reality more manageable for interpretation and for
use as a guide to action. As Noakes and Johnston (2005: 2) write: In the simplest of terms,
framing functions in much the same way as a frame around a picture: attention gets focused on
what is relevant and important and away from extraneous items in the eld of view.
Framing enables individuals and groups to make sense of the world, but because it is selective
with regard to information considered, many dierent coherent meanings are possible. Rein
and Schön (1993: 147) discuss the creation of multiple social realities, which leads people facing
a common situation to see dierent things, make dierent interpretations of the way things are,
and support dierent courses of action concerning what is to be done, by whom, and how to do
it. The framing approach echoes the problem denition perspective in underscoring the malle-
ability of social problems and, in particular, the divergent impressions that result when a causal
picture having multiple, simultaneous, and sequential inuences is cast in partial terms. However,
the framing paradigm weaves this insight into a model broad enough to encompass thematic,
ideological, cultural, group identity, and motivational elements (Noakes and Johnston 2005).
The intellectual sources of framing analysis are multidisciplinary to an exceptional degree.
Anthropologist Gregory Bateson was one of the earliest scholars to make use of the concept of a
frame (Noakes and Johnston 2005). Subsequently, various applications of framing have appeared
in linguistics, social psychology, media studies, and articial intelligence, in addition to political
science and policy analysis. The framing perspective has also emerged as one of the most
inuential paradigms for theoretical and empirical research on social movements, an inherently
cross-disciplinary area with bearing on public policy initiation.
In tracing the impact of framing within political science, Druckman (2010) focuses on two
main types of application. First is the question of how an individual forms preferences, that is a
rank ordering of a set of objects or alternative actions (2010: 280). By representing the item
under consideration in dierent ways or contexts, framing has been shown to produce dierent
valuative outcomes. Second is the role of framing in political communication and a speakers
ability, at times, to evoke varying audience reactions depending on which facet or dimension of
Rochefort and Donnelly
192
a topic has been emphasized. Iyengar (1996) pursued a similar line of inquiry with respect to public
aairs information in the media, nding, for example, that episodic treatment of social pro-
blems focusing on isolated instances versus more contextual thematic reports tends to result in
viewers favoring individualistic explanations for those problems. As Entman (1993) has noted,
to the extent that public opinion proves susceptible to manipulation, framing research conrms
the possibility of elite control, thereby raising far-reaching implications for democratic theory.
Rein and Schöns(1993)workonframe analysis represents a methodical, conceptually sophis-
ticated extension of these ideas into the policy realm (see also Schön and Rein 1994). These
authors examine policy controversies in terms of rival frames that are distinguished by alternative
factual interpretations, social meanings, and normative recommendations. The policy process is
a battle to set the agenda by means of one of these divergent models of reality. How this battle
turns out will serve the symbolic and material interests that shape, and are advanced by, a certain
complex of beliefs, values, and perspectives. None of this means frames are easy to identify,
however. On the contrary, frames exist in the world of (often unspoken) mental constructs. Fur-
ther, similar policy actions may align with dierent frames, or the same frame can give rise to
multiple policy solutions. And yet, when a frame has been successfully decoded, it not only has
great explanatory power, it can also be the rst step in an emotional and cognitive transaction
by which starkly contending interests begin to nd common ground.
A frame sets the larger tableau within which political language is used. Statements of caus-
ality, metaphorical comparisons, claims of professional ownership, and larger story narratives all
may animate a policy debate, although the proposition of scholars in this eld is that relevance
and impact will be determined by compatibility with the dominant understanding of what is at
stake in an issue conict. In their study of the US death penalty, Baumgartner et al. (2008)
found that media coverage shifted in line with the rise of the innocence frame, with elements
critical of capital punishment becoming much more common in news stories.
Often, language performs the crucial function of naming a policy terrain so as to accentuate
the overarching frame of interpretation (Rein and Schön 1993): female liberation, health care
rights, environmental justice, workforce competitiveness, and so on. Since frames consist of tone
as well as substance, there is also a relationship between framing and the expressive aspects of
policy discourse, as would be seen, for example, in harsh condemnation of shiftless welfare cheats,
sympathetic support for victims of cancer, and compassionate identication with neighbors
at the mercy of rising prices at the gas pump. In a study of Druze Arabs in Israel, Krebs and
Jackson showed the importance of political rhetoric in framing a campaign for expanded citizenship
rights as the collective reward for military sacrice:
In short, the Druze trapped Jewish leaders in a rhetorical cul-de-sac in which they
maneuvered their Jewish opponents onto a rhetorical playing eld on which the Druze
could not lose, for no rebuttal would have been acceptable to key audiences, both domestic
and international.
(2007: 52).
In so far as framing contributes to an issues or a problems perceived degree of importance, it
has obvious repercussions for determination of agenda priorities. Framing is also relevant when
analyzing the content of disputes in the politics of agenda-setting, although researchers dier on the
pattern. Baumgartner and Jones (1993) have stressed noncontradictory argumentation in which
rival frames are advanced without direct challenging of the alternatives, while other scholars have
focused on the clash between opposing frames and the discursive and other tactics used by
advocates to gain the upper hand within such competitions (see, e.g., Cobb and Ross 1997).
Agenda-setting and political discourse
193
Narrative
Many of the same observations made about problem denition and framing apply to the narrative
perspective on public policy-making. Scholars view narratives as devices that bring order and
meaning to a situation. Patterson and Monroe (1998: 315) state that narrative refers to the ways in
which we construct disparate facts in our own worlds and weave them together cognitively in
order to make sense of our reality. Further, Jones and McBeth (2010: 330) write that narra-
tive cognition may be fundamental to a meaningful human existence. Narratives make use of
metaphors, symbols, analogies, synecdoche, and other forms of gurative language in heightening
a messages impact (Stone 2002). Narrative analysis also has its roots in disparate elds, most notably
anthropology, literary theory, history, marketing, neuroscience, psychology, and psychoanalysis.
What is distinctive about the study of narratives and public policy is the focus on stories as a
means for representing reality. A story is an account with a guiding arc structured around a
beginning, middle, and end. Most simply, there is a problem, an explanation for occurrence of
the problem, and a tension-resolving solution (Fischer 2003). In fullling the form of a story,
policy narratives contain predictable elements (Patterson and Monroe 1998). There are characters
or actors, with special prominence given to the roles of victims, villains, and heroes. There is a
point of view, which is the speakers perspective of what is important, true, worthy of comment,
and goes without saying. There is a sequential ordering of events to give coherence to a problems
origins and development. And there is the setting, which is the socio-cultural context in which a
speaker embeds the account.
The purpose of constructing such a story is neither neutral nor desultory. Rather, it is to
make a point, to register an objection, and to recommend a remedy or, as some put it, to propound
a moral. In other words, policy narratives have a normative element centrally concerned with
human intention. As Fischer (2003: 163) states, the narrative is especially geared to the goals of
the actors and the way changing goals and intentions causally contribute to social change. It
seeks to comprehend and convey the direction and purpose of human aairs. A full-bodied,
well-articulated story can go far in dispelling the confusing facts and conicting voices sur-
rounding a public policy issue, superimposing an interpretation of events that is both lovely
and useful (Kaplan 1993: 176).
Stepping back from the particulars, it is possible to recognize the repetition of several common
story lines within public policy discourse. Stone (2002) identies two main types, stories of
decline and stories of control. The former describes circumstances in which conditions are
deteriorating, disaster looms, and therefore swift action is needed to avert catastrophe. Stone
calls attention to subtypes of stories of decline: the stymied progress story (positive change in
an area is being undone), and the change is only an illusion story (contrary to appearances,
reality is worse or better than appreciated). Stories of control focus on problems that had been
understood as beyond eective social intervention, but in fact can now be meliorated by public
policy action. Dierent versions of this story form develop themes of conspiracy (powerful
groups or entities have actually been controlling things behind the scenes for their own advantage),
or blaming the victim (people aected
by problems have
brought these diculties on them-
selves). With respect to the latter, Douglas Torgerson (1996), a Canadian policy specialist,
emphasizes the need for deconstructing stigmatized identities in social policy to uncover the
discursive opposition of a privileged center versus a neglected margin. Whatever the genre,
all policy narratives are likely to intermingle statistics, journalistic reporting, anecdotal portrayals,
and other factual and emotive supports for the sake of an explicit or implicit argument.
Ross examines competing narratives with regard to sense making of the attacks of September 11,
2011, from dierent national perspectives. He bases his discussion on the succinct premise that:
Rochefort and Donnelly
194
Narratives are explanations for events (large and small) in the form of short, common-sense
accounts (stories) that often seem simple. However, the powerful images they contain and
the judgments they make about the motivations and actions of their own group, and
others, are emotionally signicant for groups and individuals.
(2011: 1)
A dominant narrative for Americans, which depicts the attack as evil behavior motivated by
religious and political extremism, construes 9/11 as an act of war. Here, the response that seems
appropriate is massive military intervention abroad to defend the United States proactively by
tracking down and eliminating the terrorists and their supporters. A dierent narrative that is
heard in many parts of the Islamic world may or may not deem the attack as evil incarnate, but
relates it to objectionable activities by the United States in the Middle East over a period of
years. The American military response is predicted to extend these past injustices by harming
innocent Muslim populations while ignoring the precipitating factors and conditions that gave
rise to 9/11. Analyzing the contradictions between such narratives, Ross underscores the sig-
nicance of divergent group beliefs and experiences, facts that are selectively remembered and
interpreted, and preexisting narratives within a culture that guide collective responses to stress.
Jones and McBeth (2010) have introduced a Narrative Policy Framework (NPF) for assessing
the impact of policy narratives by means of empirical quantitative methodology. Their goal, in
short, is to subject a postpositivist concept to positivist standards of evaluation. As outlined, NPF
takes into account the principal elements of narrative form (plot, setting, characters, and moral)
while categorizing generalized story content with respect to ideology (or another belief system).
The methodology then uses these inputs to generate hypotheses concerning the potential impact,
or utility, of narrative for individuals and groups within a policy dispute. Elaborating on this
approach, Shanahan et al. (2011) drew upon the NPF to formulate an additional set of hypotheses
incorporating independent and dependent variables of interest concerning policy outcomes,
policy learning, policy change, public opinion, and strategy from Sabatier and Jenkins-Smiths
(1993) well known Advocacy Coalition Framework.
Two cases
During the summer of 2011 London experienced days of rioting marked by violence, social
unrest, and destruction on a massive scale. The turbulence generated a sweeping national exam-
ination of conscience in British society on topics ranging from income inequality to the decline
of moral virtue. The fall of 2011 witnessed an outpouring of citizen protests on Wall Street and
in dozens of cities around the United States. Few anticipated this Occupy movement and the
strong chord its message struck with large segments of the American people. A brief review of each
of these cases will serve to illustrate the potent role of language in political situations surrounding
the emergence (and reemergence) of divisive social issues.
Riots in the United Kingdom
Late in the evening of Saturday, August 6, 2011, riots broke out in the north London neigh-
borhood of Tottenham. Rioters set buildings on re, clashed with police, and smashed the win-
dows of local shops. In subsequent days, the violence and destruction spread to neighboring cities
and towns. According to the Guardian newspaper, by the third night Buildings were torched,
shops ransacked, and ocers attacked with makeshift missiles and petrol bombs as gangs of
hooded and masked youths laid waste to streets right across the city (Dodd and Davies 2011).
Agenda-setting and political discourse
195
Calm did not return until the fourth night following Prime Minister David Camerons decision
to deploy an additional 10,000 police ocers across the streets of London.
Both during and immediately following the riots, political commentary focused on a central
question of problem denition and narrative composition: Who or what was to blame for this
historic display of social unrest? The immediate precipitant was obvious. Days earlier, police had
shot and killed Mark Duggan when attempting to arrest him in an investigation of gun vio-
lence. A peaceful protest in Tottenham denouncing the police role in Duggans death, which
some suggested was racially motivated, ultimately got out of hand (Faiola 2011). Yet, according
to the New York Times, the circumstances of Mr. Duggans death appeared to be remote from
the forces driving the riots, at least in the assessment of many of those who are most familiar
with the neighborhoods aected. Instead, this incident was simply the original trigger for the
violence (Burns 2011). While most seem to accept the truth of this observation, this is where
agreement ended in regard to underlying cause of the riots.
Drastic cuts to services, or austerity measures, surfaced as one prominent culprit noted in the
media. Consider the following account oered by Nina Power of the Guardian, who suggested
a context to Londons riots that cant be ignored.
Since the coalition came to power just over a year ago, the country has seen multiple student
protests, occupations of dozens of universities, several strikes, a half-a-million-strong trade
union marches and now unrest on the streets of the capital Each of these events was
sparked by a dierent cause, yet all take place against a backdrop of brutal cuts and enforced
austerity measures. The government knows very well that it is taking a gamble, and that its
policies run the risk of sparking mass unrest on a scale we havent seen since the early
1980s. With people taking to the streets of Tottenham, Edmonton, Brixton and elsewhere
over the past few nights, we could be about to see the government enter a sustained and
serious losing streak.
(8 August 2011)
Power also proposed basic income inequality as a critical driver of the riots. After rst establishing
the link between inequality and social issues, Power stated that [d]ecades of individualism,
competition and state-encouraged selshnesscombined with a systematic crushing of unions and
the ever-increasing criminalisation of dissenthave made Britain one of the most unequal countries
in the developed world. Ravi Somaiya of the New York Times echoed this view in stating that
Economic malaise and cuts in spending and services instituted by the Conservative-led gov-
ernment have been recurring ashpoints for months (Somaiya 2011). Political commentators
were not the only ones delivering this message. In the aftermath of the riots, Labour Party leader
Ed Miliband called the cause of the riots complex, but frequently pointed to Britains unequal
society as a key contributor (Dunt 2011). The long-term pattern of deterioration within this
constructed narrative is consistent with Stones
(2002) stories of decline. By
assigning blame to
the Government as a guilty party in igniting the riots, this interpretation also pointed to a logical
solutionroll back the cuts and create a more equal society. Little in the way of specic policy
proposals has yet accompanied the linking of inequality to the rioting. However, in a major speech
delivered against the backdrop of his old secondary school, Miliband set the stage for possible future
action by urging the governing party to establish a formal commission of inquiry to investigate the
cause of the riots, and he tasked it, in particular, with examining issues of inequality (Miliband 2011).
Other commentary, however, tagged the rioters as reckless law-breakers skilled at exploiting
New Age social media outlets. Quickly dispensing with the notion that the riots were in some
way a valid political expression, The Daily Telegraph oered the following:
Rochefort and Donnelly
196
What we have experienced in London and elsewhere since Saturday night is a wholly new
phenomenon: violent disorder whose sole intent is criminal. These are not protesters, as the
BBC stupidly insisted on calling them: they are looters and vandals and thieves. The unstruc-
tured nature of their violence has made it exceedingly dicult for the police to gather any
worthwhile intelligence on them. Yet their sophisticated use of social media allows them to
muster at will. They have had the whip hand for four days and the police have constantly
had to play catch-up.
(Telegraph View 2011)
Government ocials in London expressed parallel sentiments. During a press conference
just days following the initial night of rioting, deputy assistant commissioner to the Metropoli-
tan police, Steve Kavanagh, blamed the rioting on really inammatory, inaccurate messages
on Twitter, adding that [s]ocial media and other methods have been used to organise these
levels of greed and criminality (Halliday 2011). Going further, Mike Butcher, a digital aide to
Londons mayor, told the BBC that [m]obile phones have become weaponised in their cap-
ability of spreading information about where to target next. Butcher remarked it was unbe-
lievable that BlackBerry Messenger had not been shut down during the riots (Minicucci 2011).
Ultimately, government authorities chose not to interrupt service. However, this criminal,
rather than political, framing of the riots impacted solution development. London police
authorities launched an ocial investigation into the use of BlackBerrys as an organizing tool by
the rioters.
A broader theme in discourse about the riots was the issue of moral decay. Prime Minister
Cameron pointed to the UKs slow-motion moral collapse as overriding cause of the riots:
These riots were not about race: the perpetrators and the victims were white, black and
Asian. These riots were not about government cuts: they were directed at high street stores,
not Parliament. And these riots were not about poverty: that insults the millions of people
who, whatever the hardship, would never dream of making others suer like this.
No, this was about behaviour. People showing indierence to right and wrong. People
with a twisted moral code. People with a complete absence of self-restraint.
(15 August 2011)
Cameron announced that his plan to xabroken Britain would be back on the top of [his]
political agenda. This policy vision, which centered on the goal of reversing general social
decay, originated during the previous 2010 election, but it was dusted o as the ideal response
to the current violence.
In a Wall Street Journal op-ed, Britains chief rabbi, Jonathan Sacks, wrote that no one should
have been surprised by the London riots. In his view, Britain is the latest country to pay the
price for what happened half a century ago in one of the most radical transformations in the
history of the West. In virtually every Western society in the 1960s there was a moral revolu-
tion, an abandonment of its entire traditional ethic of self-restraint (Sacks 2011). Not to be
outdone, another religious leader, the Archbishop of Canterbury, Rowan Williams, sermonized
on moral failings by criticizing an educational philosophy at every level [that] has been more
and more dominated by an instrumentalist model; less and less concerned with a building of
virtue, character and citizenship. The solution, according to Dr. Williams, could be found in
rebuilding the skills of parenting in some of our communities, [and] in rebuilding education
itself (Walton 2011). These, of course, are not new ideas in socially conservative circles. In
eect, the riots provided a context, not to mention a pretext,
for attaching existing solutions to a
Agenda-setting and political discourse
197
new problem, which is a well-known sequence in problem denition (Kingdon 1995). The
dynamic of religious gures asserting the relevance of their special brand of expertise also represents
a striking illustration of the struggle for problem ownership that frequently occurs in public
policy debate.
Occupy Wall Street
On September 17, 2011, a protest movement emerged on the streets of Lower Manhattan, the
likes of which had not been seen in the US for decades. On that day, a small group of protesters
gathered to occupy parts of Wall Street and camp out in nearby Zuccotti Park in a dramatic
attempt to draw attention to growing inequalities in American wealth and income. Although
this initial action turned out to be fairly modest in scope, within weeks similar demonstrations
cropped up in dozens of cities across the nation and the world. Increasingly larger groups of pro-
testers claiming solidarity with the Occupy movement set up encampments in city parks and
other public spaces from Boston to Oakland, Nashville to Reno. Proudly leaderless and vague
in its goals, the Occupy movement nonetheless captured the attention of law-makers and
dramatically shifted the focus of American political discourse.
In the early days of the Occupy protests, political commentary focused on explaining the
movement itself. An array of competing narratives resulted. Tying the movement to the story
of our economic woes, Paul Krugman (2011), a liberal columnist for the New York Times,
outlined the following three acts:
In the rst act, bankers took advantage of deregulation to run wild (and pay themselves
princely sums), inating huge bubbles through reckless lending. In the second act, the
bubbles burstbut bankers were bailed out by taxpayers, with remarkably few strings
attached, even as ordinary workers continued to suer the consequences of the bankers
sins. And, in the third act, bankers showed their gratitude by turning on the people who
had saved them, throwing their supportand the wealth they still possessed thanks to the
bailoutsbehind politicians who promised to keep their taxes low and dismantle the mild
regulations erected in the aftermath of the crisis. Given this history, how can you not
applaud the protesters for nally taking a stand?
Starkly dierent was the take of conservative columnist for the Washington Post, Charles Krau-
thammer, who linked the Occupy movement to President Obamas recent calls for the rich to
pay their fair share:
To the villainy-of-the-rich theme emanating from Washington, a child is born: Occupy
Wall Street. Starbucks-sipping, Levis-clad, iPhone-clutching protesters denounce corpo-
rate America even as they weep for Steve Jobs, corporate titan, billionaire eight times over.
These indignant indolents saddled with their $50,000 student loans and English degrees
have decided that their lack of gainful employment is rooted in the malice of the million-
aires on whose homes they are now marchingto the applause of Democrats suering
acute Tea Party envy and now salivating at the energy these big-government anarchists will
presumably give their cause.
(13 October 2011)
Aside from reecting the ideological predispositions of these two pundits, such accounts spoke
to a broader eort on the part of media gures to contextualize the ongoing social unrest.
Rochefort and Donnelly
198
Certain political commentators drew analogies to other grassroots movements. Nicholas Kristof,
an international news reporter for the New York Times, drew a parallel between the Occupy
movement and the pro-democracy protesters in Cairos Tahrir Square:
[T]here is the same cohort of alienated young people, and the same savvy use of Twitter
and other social media to recruit more participants. Most of all, theres a similar tide of
youthful frustration with a political and economic system that protesters regard as broken,
corrupt, unresponsive and unaccountable.
(Kristof 2011)
Use of this particular analogy sent a powerful message by framing the Occupy movement as part of
a global phenomenon in which a virtuous younger generation had stood up to an ineective
and illegitimate power structure. Other observers, including President Obama, compared the
Occupy and Tea Party movements, the latter coalescing two years earlier around the goals of
shrinking government and an originalist interpretation of the Constitution. During an interview
Obama suggested:
In some ways, theyre not that dierent from some of the protests that we saw coming
from the Tea Party. Both on the left and the right, I think people feel separated from their
government. They feel that their institutions arent looking out for them.
(Dwyer 2011).
This comparison both anointed (prematurely) the Occupy movement as a potent political force
and presented the idea that a counterweight to the Tea Party movement was now emerging.
The formulation of comparisons to movements as diverse as the Arab Spring and the Tea Party
is testament to the amorphous nature of the Occupy protests. However, it also illustrates the
extent to which analogies portray political events in dramatically dierent lights in the creative
application of political discourse.
Despite its ambiguity, the Occupy movement articulated an agenda clear and motivating
enough to draw thousands of Americans into the streets. This may be due, in part, to the fact
that protesters proposed a new framework for debating US economic policy. Unlike during the
previous two years, in which the national debt, government spending, and draconian cost-cutting
measures dominated the discourse, the Occupy movement spotlighted economic inequality as a
transcendent issue. A New York Times editorial chastised the chattering classes [who] keep com-
plaining that the marchers lack a clear message and specic policy prescriptions, and oered the
following defense:
At this point, protest is the message: income inequality is grinding down that middle class,
increasing the ranks of the poor, and threatening to create a permanent underclass of able,
willing but jobless people. On one level, the protesters, most of them young, are giving
voice to a generation of lost opportunity.
(New York Times Editorial 2011)
Along with their physical presence, the protesters supported their inequality frame with pow-
erful sloganizing. Put simply, We are the 99%. This phrase eectively hit home the move-
ments essential complaintthat wealth is highly concentrated in the top 1 percent of the
population while the status quo serves the nancial elite at the expense of the many. Similarly,
by featuring a raised st”—the universal symbol of solidarity and resistanceon the Occupy
Agenda-setting and political discourse
199
Wall Street website and at rallies across the nation, the group reinforced the scope of their
solution: A revolution of the mind as well as the body politic (OccupyWallSt.org).
Critics of the Occupy movement portrayed its participants in a negative light to discredit
their message. In her appearance on the Fox News Hannity program, conservative author and
commentator Ann Coulter assured the viewing audience that none of these kids at Occupy
Wall Street are coming from places like Yale, they are coming from the most bush league schools
which is why none of them can even say why they are there. Further, Coulter expressed con-
dence that Americans are reacting the way they should, which is with hilarity and revulsion
(Coulter 2011). Even more contemptuously, talk radio show host Rush Limbaugh told his
audience:
[W]hen I was ten years old I was more self-sucient than this parade of human debris
calling itself Occupy Wall Street If you look at the minutes and read their website, these
people are announcing that theyre parasites, that they are not self-sucient and that they
are totally dependent on the very things and people they re protesting.
(Limbaugh 2011)
Here was a classic tactic of conict containment via rhetoric: defuse the issue and block its expansion
by means of a direct verbal attack on a protest group and its leaders (Cobb and Elder 1972).
Other more mainstream critics elected to challenge the inequality frame head on. Repre-
sentative Paul Ryan, in a prominent speech before the Heritage Foundation, asked the audience
to consider [w]hether we are a nation that still believes in equality of opportunity, or whether
we are moving away from that, and toward an insistence on equality of outcome. The latter,
Ryan suggested, constitutes the moral basis of class warfarea false morality that confuses fairness
with redistribution, and promotes class envy instead of social mobility (Ryan 2011). Mitt Romney,
front-runner for the 2012 Republican presidential nomination, responded to a question about
the Occupy protests by saying: I think itsdangerous,this[is]classwarfare (Boxer 2011). The contest
of economic frames was classic: inequality versus competition, fairness versus winner-take-all.
The fact that prominent Republicans saw the need to defend, not merely promote, their
preferred economic frame illustrates the surprising strength of the Occupy movement. What
remains unclear at the time of this writing, however, is the long-term impact of such rhetorical
point-counterpoint on US politics and public policy.
Discussion and conclusion
The two cases we have discussed may be notable for their timeliness and for the signicance of
issues being raised, but they are not unique from a discursive standpoint. The patterns of argu-
mentation, descriptive construction, and storytelling are commonplace, making it easy to demon-
strate the applicability of the problem denition, framing, and narrative perspectives across the
political landscape. This should not be surprising if it is true, as has sometimes been claimed,
that all language is political and all politics is language. Yet the very pervasiveness of poli-
tical discourse inclines the subject to certain ambiguities that should be noted at the close of this
review.
First, although much work in the eld of discourse analysis has been devoted to typing the
rhetorical strategies that recur in politics, the raw material in any given case study is always unique,
with its own combination of themes, accents, and emotions. This situation makes it likely that
no two analysts will interpret a case precisely the same way, either in identifying critical ele-
ments of language or in explicating their role in the outcome of a conict. The focus on politics
Rochefort and Donnelly
200
as a text has, in short, opened the door to all the creativity and all the inconsistency that one
nds in other elds of textual analysis, such as literary studies. Thus, even though it is possible to
recognize a close connection among the problem denition, framing, and narrative approaches,
these frameworks have oddly served as alternative lenses at times, that is, as intellectual spheres
with their own reference points, observational criteria, and conceptual intentions. Whether this
pluralism has proved boon or bane to the broad community of scholars and students interested
in the impact of political language is questionable.
Second, it is understandable that the uidity of political discourse analysis has now given rise
to attempts to pin down crucial variables through quantitative measurement. The Narrative
Policy Framework of Jones and McBeth (2010) has already been cited as an illustration of this
quantifying impulse, one that aims to gain a place for language variables within the policy stu-
dies literature with respect to such basic processes as policy change and policy learning. Simi-
larly, the specication, tabulation, and interrelating of basic numerical indicators has been highly
useful in documenting the rise and fall of rival policy frames for those working within this
perspective (see, e.g., Baumgartner et al. 2008; Baumgartner and Jones 1993). Various media
and survey studies have also conrmed hypothesized relationships between language construc-
tions and political attitudes of dierent kinds. So far, however, the ambitiousness of this quan-
titative vein of work, worthwhile though it may be, continues to outstrip its accomplishments,
nor has it done much to integrate the divergent traditions of scholarship within this area.
Third, a persistent barrier to positivist analysis in searching for regularities in the expressions
of political language, on the one hand, and their impact on agenda setting, on the other, is
the shifting meaning of similar language and narratives depending on context. Within the
American national healthcare debate, it has been intriguing to note the contradictory uses of
what might be called the rhetoric of foreign standards. In the hands of dierent polemicists,
the same examples of national health systems elsewhere have been used either to shame the
United States for being a laggard in providing universal coverage and cost control, or to praise
the US health care system as the best in the world. Even aside from such blatant paradoxes,
important nuances of discursive meaning are likely whenever attention shifts from one policy
domain to another. Thus, Rochefort et al. (1998) found substantial dierences in rhetorical uses
of the concept of community within policy debates concerning mental health, criminal jus-
tice, and social service programs in the US and Canadian province of Quebec. Underlying
similar sounding language were both divergent value assumptions and alternative pathways for
policy design.
A concern with the potent use of language in politics is not new. It dates back at least as far
as Platos academy in ancient Greece and the rst formal analyses of rhetoric written by Aris-
totle, former student and faculty member there. Today, however, researchers from many dif-
ferent disciplines who share an interest in the politics of public policymaking are injecting new
energy and concepts into this eld of study. This academic focus is being matched and doubtless
heightened by a dramatic expansion in the techniques and forms of media available to the practi-
tioners of political language, inside and outside government. The purpose of this chapter has
been to signal promising trends in the major scholarly approaches surrounding this development
while encouraging greater awareness of their intellectual common ground.
Bibliography
Bardach, Eugene. 2009. A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis. Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Agenda-setting and political discourse
201
——, Green-Pedersen, and Bryan D. Jones. 2006. Comparative studies of policy agendas , Journal of European
Public Policy 13(7): 95974.
——, Suzanna L. De Boef and Amber E. Boydstun. 2008. The Decline of the Death Penalty and the Discovery
of Innocence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Beard, Adrian. 2000. The Language of Politics. London: Routledge.
Boxer, Sarah B. 2011. Romney: Wall Street protests Class Warfare, National Journal, 5 October. Available at:
http://nationaljournal.com/2012-presidential-campaign/romney-wall-street-protests-class-warfare20111004.
Burns, John F. 2011. Cameron deploys 10,000 more ocers to riots, New York Times, 10 August, p. A4.
Cameron, David. 2011. Speech on the ght-back after the riots, Witney, Great Britain, 15 August.
Available at: http://www.newstatesman.com/politics/2011/08/society-ght-work-rights.
Cobb, Roger W. and Charles D. Elder. 1972. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-
Building. Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
——and Marc H. Ross (eds). 1997. Cultural Strategies of Agenda Denial: Avoidance, Attack, and Redenition.
Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.
——, Jennie Keith-Ross and Marc Howard Ross. 1976. Agenda building as a comparative political process,
American Political Science Review 70(1): 12638.
Coulter, Ann. 2011. Remarks on Fox News’“Hannity, 14 October. Available at: http://www.foxnews.
com/on-air/hannity/2011/10/17/ann-coulter-sounds-brainless-wall-street-protesters.
Dodd, Vikram and Caroline Davies. 2011. London riots escalate as police battle for control, The Guardian,8
August. Available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2011/aug/08/london-riots-escalate-police-battle.
Druckman, James N. 2010. Whats it all about? Framing in political science, in Gideon Keren (ed.)
Perspectives on Framing. New York: Psychology Press, 279302
Dunt, Ian. 2011. Miliband: if Cameron doesnt
hold an inquiry
I will, Politics.co.uk, 12 August. Available
at: http://www.politics.co.uk/news/2011/08/12/miliband-pushes-for-national-inquiry-into-eng.
Dwyer, Devin. 2011. Obama: Occupy Wall Street not that dierent from Tea Party protests, ABC
News, 18 October. Available at: http://abcnews.go.com/blogs/politics/2011/10/obama-occupy-wall-
street-not-that-dierent-from-tea-party-protests/.
Edelman, Murray. 1988. Constructing the Political Spectacle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Entman, Robert M. 1993. Framing: Toward clarication of a fractured paradigm, Journal of Communication
43(4): 518.
Faiola, Anthony. 2011. Riots breakout in London neighborhood, Washington Post, 7 August. Available at:
http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/riots-break-out-in-london-neighborhood/2011/08/07/gIQAn0
sA0I_story.html.
Fischer, Frank. 2003. Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative Practices. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
——and John Forester (eds). 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Guseld, Joseph R. 1981. The Culture of Public Problems. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Halliday, Josh. 2011. London riots: BlackBerry to help police probe Messenger looting role”’, Guardian,
8 August. Available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk/2011/aug/08/london-riots-blackberry-messenger-
looting.
Hirschman, Albert. 1991. The Rhetoric of Reaction: Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press.
Iyengar, Shanto. 1996. Framing responsibility for political issues, Annals of the American Academy of Political
and Social Science 546(1): 5970.
Jones, Michael D. and Mark K. McBeth. 2010. A narrative policy framework: Clear enough to be
wrong? Policy Studies Journal 38(2): 32953.
Kaplan, Thomas J. 1993. Reading policy narratives: beginnings, middles, and ends, 16785, in Frank
Fischer and John Forester (eds) The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Kingdon,
John. 1995. Agendas, Alternatives,
and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Krauthammer, Charles. 2011. The scapegoat strategy, Washington Post, 13 October. Available at: http://
www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/the-scapegoat-strategy/2011/10/13/gIQArNWViL_story.html.
Krebs, Ronald R. and Patrick Thaddeus Jackson. 2007. Twisting tongues and twisting arms: The power
of political rhetoric, European Journal of International Relations 13(1): 3566.
Kristof, Nicholas. 2011. The bankers and the revolutionaries , New York Times, 1 October, SR11.
Krugman, Paul. 2011. Confronting the malefactors, New York Times, 6 October, A27.
Rochefort and Donnelly
202
Limbaugh, Rush. 2011. Remarks on the Rush Limbaugh Show”’, 5 October. Available at: http://www.
rushlimbaugh.com/daily/2011/10/05/anti_capitalist_protestors_face_dilemma_should_they_buy_stu.
Majone, Giandomenico. 1989. Evidence, Argument, and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Miliband, Ed. 2011. Speech on the London riots, Haverstock School in Chalk Farm, Great Britain, 15
August. Available at: http://www.newstatesman.com/politics/2011/08/society-young-heard-riots.
Mills, C. Wright. 1959. The Sociological Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Minicucci, Daniela. 2011. The role of digital and social media in the London riots, Global News, 9 August.
Available at: http://www.globalnews.ca/feature/6442461111/story.html.
New York Times editorial. 2011. Protesters against Wall Street: Its obvious what they want, New York
Times, 9 October, p. SR10
Noakes, John A. and Hank Johnston. 2005. Frames of protest: A roadmap to a perspective,129, in
Hank Johnston and John A. Noakes (eds) Frames of Protest: Social Movements and the Framing Perspective.
Oxford: Rowman and Littleeld.
OccupyWallSt.org. 2011. A modest call to action on this September 17th, 17 September. Available at:
http://occupywallst.org/article/September_Revolution/.
Patterson, Molly and Kristen Renwick Monroe. 1998. Narrative in political science, Annual Review of
Political Science 1: 31531.
Power, Nina. 2011. There is a context to Londons riots that cant be ignored, Guardian, 8 August.
Available at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2011/aug/08/context-london-riots.
Rein, Martin and Donald Schön. 1993. Reframing policy discourse, 14566, in Frank Fischer and John
Forester (eds) The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Rochefort, David A. 1986. American Social Welfare Policy: Dynamics of Formulation and Change. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press.
——and Roger W. Cobb. 1993. Problem denition, agenda access, and policy choice, Policy Studies
Journal 21(1):
5671.
——and Roger W.
Cobb. 1994. Problem denition: An emerging perspective in David A. Rochefort
and Roger W. Cobb (eds) The Politics of Problem Denition: Shaping the Policy Agenda. Lawrence, KS:
University Press of Kansas, 131.
——, Michael Rosenberg and Deena White. 1998. Community as a policy instrument: A comparative
analysis, Policy Studies Journal 26(3): 54868.
Ross, Marc H. 2011. The political psychology of competing narratives: September 11 and beyond, Social
Science Research Council. Available at: http://essays.ssrc.org/sept11/essays/ross.htm.
Ryan, Paul. 2011. Remarks before the Heritage Foundation, Washington, DC, 26 October. Available at:
http://blog.heritage.org/2011/10/26/video-rep-paul-ryan-on-saving-the-american-idea/.
Sabatier, Paul A. and Hank Jenkins-Smith. 1993. Policy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Coalition
Approach. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Sacks, Jonathan. 2011. Reversing the decay of London undone, Wall Street Journal, 20 August. Available
at: http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424053111903639404576516252066723110.html.
Schattschneider, E.E. 1960. The Semisovereign People: A Realists View of Democracy in America. Hinsdale, IL:
Dryden Press.
Schneider, Anne and Helen Ingram. 1997. Policy Design for Democracy. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas
Press.
Schön, Donald A. and Martin Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies.
New York: Basic Books.
Shanahan, Elizabeth A., Michael D. Jones and Mark K. McBeth. 2011. Policy narratives and policy processes,
Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 53561.
Somaiya, Ravi. 2011. London sees twin perils converging to fuel riot, New York Times, 8 August, A4.
Stone, Deborah. 2002. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making. New York: Norton.
Telegraph View editorial. 2011. The criminals who shame our nation, The Telegraph, 9 August. Available
at: http://www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/telegraph-view/8691352/The-criminals-who-shame-our-nat
ion.html.
Torgerson, Douglas. 1996. Power and insight in policy discourse: Post-positivism and problem denition,
in
Laurent Dobuzinskis, Michael
Howlett, and David Laycock (eds) Policy Studies in Canada: The State of
the Art. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 26698.
Walton, Je. 2011. Church of England bishops: Lack of virtue at fault for London riots, The Institute on
Religion and Democracy, 22 August. Available at: http://www.theird.org/page.aspx?pid=2012.
Agenda-setting and political discourse
203
16
Mass media and policy-making
Stuart Soroka, Stephen Farnsworth, Andrea Lawlor and Lori Young
Mass media can, and often do, play a critical role in policy-making. The typical view of media
is that they matter in the early stages of the policy processthat media can help to set an
agenda, which is then adopted and dealt with by politicians, policy-makers, and other actors.
The impact of media is rarely so constrained, however. Our argument here, in short, is that
media matter, not just at the beginning but throughout the policy process.
Many of the standard accounts of policy-making have a much too narrow view of the timing
of media eects. That said, the ways in which mass media can matter are relatively well under-
stood. Existing work tells us that media can draw and sustain public attention to particular issues.
They can change the discourse around a policy debate by framing or dening an issue using
dialogue or rhetoric to persuade or dissuade the public. Media can establish the nature, sources,
and consequences of policy issues in ways that fundamentally change not just the attention paid
to those issues, but the dierent types of policy solutions sought. Media can draw attention to the
players involved in the policy process and can aid, abet or hinder their cause by highlighting
their role in policy-making. Media can also act as a critical conduit between governments and
publics, informing publics about government actions and policies, and helping to convey public
attitudes to government ocials.
Allowing for the possibility that any and all of these eects can be evident not just in the
early stages but throughout the policy process makes clear the potentially powerful impact we
believe that media can have on policy. Indeed, mass media are in the unique position of having
a regular, marked impact on policy, but from outside the formal political sphere, often without
even being recognized as a policy player.
This chapter reviews the state of the literature on media and policy-making. It reviews two
of the most prominent theories in the study of media and policy-making: agenda-setting and
issue framing. It then considers some of the normative implications of the regular impact of
media on policy-making. Is the fact that media matter to policy-making a good thing? There
are benets, to be sure, but also costs, and we consider below the costs associated with the well-
known event-driven, sensationalist tendencies in media content. We then nish with a brief
example from Canadian environmental news coverage; an example which illustrates some of
the problematic tendencies in media content, and highlights some of the issues with media as a
policy actor.
204
Agenda-setting and issue attentiveness
The policy agenda-setting literature has its roots in early work in political behavior focused on
how media coverage of political events impacts electoral outcomes. Berelson et al.s (1954) seminal
study on voting, for instance, notes that the media persuades individuals by prioritizing parti-
cular stories over others, or by airing a greater volume of stories related to some policy domains,
but not others. McCombs and Shaws (1972) Chapel Hill study, which spawned a vast literature
on public agenda-setting, examines the medias role in focusing public attention on particular
issues, concluding that the media can eectively set the public agenda by consistently and pro-
minently featuring issues in their news coverage. Cobb and Elders (1972) early work is the policy-
oriented equivalent, and these authors were followed by a growing body of literature focused
on the sources of the policy agenda, that is, the general set of issues that are communicated in a
hierarchy of importance at a point in time (Cobb and Elder [1972]1983: 14).
Though by no means the only source of the policy agenda, existing work suggests that media
can be an important one. Consider work by Flickinger (1983) and Mayer (1991), for instance, on
the role of media in the rise of consumer protection as a policy issue, or Pritchard s (1986) work
on the impact of media coverage on the decision to prosecute murderers (also see Pritchards
(1992) review of the role of the news media in public policy). All of this work points toward an
impact of media on policy-makers that is very similar to what Cohen famously observed about the
public, namely, that the mass media may not be successful much of the time in telling people
what to think, but it is stunningly successful in telling its readers what to think about (Cohen
1963: 13). The policy equivalentmass media may not dene the nature or direction of policy
change, but can certainly steer attention towards certain policy domains over othersis of no small
consequence. Recent work by both Kingdon (1995) and Baumgartner and Jones (1993) has
made this especially clear. For each, issue attentiveness is a critical precursor of policy change.
The same was true in Anthony Downs (1972) work on the issue attention cycle, the cano-
nical model of public issue attentiveness. Downs suggested that (policy) issues move cyclically in
and out of the public consciousness. The life cycle of an issue moves incrementally from periods
of low to high salience, ultimately retreating to the background after the public has moved onto
to other issues. The notion itself is not earth-shattering, but Downs description of the process is
valuable. It also points to the role of media in aecting change in issue salience.
Note too that while most of the preceding work focuses on the role of media in aecting
some kind of aggregate policy agenda, the role of media in setting the policy agenda can also be
seen at the individual level, that is, impacting individual political and policy actors directly.
Politicians are aected by media in the same way as ordinary citizens (Eilders 2001; Dearing and
Rogers 1996). They rely on media cues to prioritize information and to disseminate public opi-
nion (Walgrave and Van Aelst 2006: 100; Cook et al. 1983). Politicians can be even more sus-
ceptible to media content depending on whether they are subject to electoral punishment on a
set of issues (Kingdon 1984). However, legislators, like voters, cannot pay attention to all issues
at a given time; their attention is nite, and therefore they tend to focus on key issues that are
benecial to their constituents, country and indeed, their own career. Unsurprisingly, there are often
high levels of congruence among these issues and the issues that are of concern to the public
(Baumgartner et al. 1997: 350).
Of all this said, media quite clearly do not matter to all policy issues all the all the time, and there
is a growing body of work exploring the ways in which media inuence varies systematically
across issues. Some work has compared the impact of media across issues directly. Soroka (2002),
for instance, argues for three dierent issue types, where sensational issuescharacterized by low
complexity and the possibility for dramatic eventsare those for which media are most likely to
Mass media and policy-making
205
play a leading role. (Also see Walgrave et al. 2007.) Indeed, there are a number of studies suggesting
that the complexity of issues seriously constrains the potential for media eects, on both the public
and policy-makers (e.g. Zucker 1978; Yagade and Dozier 1990), and a series of studies that focus
on the role of often sudden and unexpected focusing events in attracting media, and then policy,
attention to issues (e.g. Birkland 1998; Kingdon 1994). The impact of media on policy also appears
to be contingent on the source of the news: reliable and respected news outlets have more impact
than marginal and questionable news sources (Bartels 1996). Additionally, the possibility that
media have a marked impact on the political agenda increases when there is heightened coverage
of the same issue, at the same time, by dierent media outlets (Eilders 2000, 2001).
Even with these caveats, the accumulated literature suggests an important (and often indepen-
dent) role for media in determining which issues are important, and whenfor the public, and
for policy-makers as well. Setting the agenda is just one way in which media may matter to
policy, however. We explore a second below.
Issue framing
As with agenda-setting, the framing literature spans analyses of both policy-making and public
opinion. Druckman oers a cogent denition:
a framing eect is said to occur when, in the of describing an issue or event, a speakers
emphasis on a subset of potentially relevant considerations causes individuals to focus on
these considerations when constructing their opinions.
(2001: 1042; drawing on work by Rabin 1998, among others)
The extent to which this kind of framing is seen as separate from agenda-setting varies somewhat
some authors choose to see framing mainly as shifts in attentiveness to sub-issues (see, e.g.
McCombs et al. 1997; McCombs 2004). Others argue that while agenda-setting looks at story
selection as determinants of public perceptions of issue importance, framing looks at the way
those issues are presented (see, e.g. Price and Tewksbury 1997: 184). We take the view here, in
line with a vast body of work on policy-making, that it is worth considering framing as distinct
from agenda-setting.
Framing theory is based on the belief that how an issue is characterized to an audience will
inuence how it is understood (see, e.g. Scheufele and Tewksbury 2007). Put dierently, issue
framing refers to the selective exposure of information to an audience with the intent of shaping
their understanding of an issue; it is the selection ofand emphasis uponparticular attributes
for the news media agenda when talking about an object (McCombs 2004: 87). Media can
apply frames to issues in order to organize a storyline around a series of events (e.g. Gamson and
Modigliani 1987), or to instruct or persuade the audience in how to evaluate the information
being given to them in a predictable way (e.g. McQuail 1994). Framing issues presuppose that
the information presented to the public will change the way that they view an issue. In other
words, framing an issue involves select[ing] some aspects of a perceived reality in such a
way as to promote a particular problem denition, causal interpretation, moral evaluation, and/
or treatment recommendation (Entman 1993: 52). To frame a story is to often withhold some
information or prioritize some facts over others. In fact, most frames are, according to Entman
(1993), as dened by what they omit or obscure as what they include. (And note that motives
for inclusion or exclusion of information may be conscious or unconscious, see Gamson 1989.)
Frames often inuence the direction of policy by pulling values or emotion into the discus-
sion. Stone argues that problem identication often focuses on framing a story in a way that
Soroka et al.
206
attributes cause and assigns blame (1989: 282). According to Iyengar (1991), thematic frames (those
that give information about general trends such as poverty or social welfare) tend to promote a
sense of social or institutional responsibility, while episodic frames (those that reference indivi-
duals or personal experiences or and stories) place responsibility on the individual. Frame types
prime social values dierently, and simultaneously establish the salience of the subject and promote
a particular policy direction (Sniderman et al. 1991).
Framing is not an activity for media alone, of course. Policymakers are not simply aected by
issue framing in media, but they actively engage in policy framing. Indeed, the policy literature
on framing is much more focused on the ways in which policy re-framing by politicians and/or
bureaucrats can shift attentiveness to or attitudes towards an issue. Consider Edelmans (1997)
work on the role of language and symbols in politics, for instance, connected to a broader body
of constructionist accounts of the policy process (e.g. Lasswell 1949; Spector and Kitsuse 1977;
Rosenau 1993). Consider also Fischers (2003) discussion of politicians use of rhetorical devices
to frame an issue and sway public opinion. Using the example of hiring policy, Gamson and
Modigliani (1987) show that formal terms in thematic, policy-oriented frames (i.e. armative
action) may lend the frame more credibility than vernacular or emotionally charged language
(i.e. preferential treatment), thereby impacting how audiences receive the frame and accept
policy direction from elites (see also Gamson 1992).
Media as a policy actor: challenges
Clearly, media matter to policy, throughout the policy process, and in many dierent ways. Is
this a good thing? It is an inevitable thing, surelyit is nearly impossible to imagine modern
politics and policy-making without some kind of media involvement, after all. Even so, we should
consider some of the issues related to medias role in the policy process. Here, we review the
considerable body of work that criticizes the nature and tone of media content on policy issues.
As we shall see, this work raises serious questions about the potential for and diculties with the
role of mass media in policy-making.
Note rst that work in political communication routinely oers largely critical assessments of the
ability of news content to contribute to informed public debate, particularly with respect to
television news. Biases in reporter coverage and the use of active conict frameskey journalistic
tools in other areas of media coverageare highlighted as important constraints. Studies fault
reporters for focusing on the trivial, for being too closely tied to ocial sources, for not providing
their viewers with enough context to understand contentious policy options, for their bias and
for a lack of technical prociency in the matters about which they write (Entman 2004;
Farnsworth and Lichter 2006, 2011; Herman and Chomsky 1988; Iyengar 1991; Iyengar and
Kinder 1987; Larson 2001; McChesney 1999; Patterson 1994).
Research also questions the possibility that journalistic norms serve to create misleading news
stories. Coverage of environmental issues stands as one example of this phenomenon. Even with
major issues that have been repeatedly featured in the media, such as the global warming debate,
scholars note that attempting to provide roughly equal treatment of both sides of a story can
distort the reality of widespread scientic agreement regarding climate change (Boyko 2005).
Rather than focus on the preponderance of scientic evidence that supports the global warming
hypothesis, scholars argue that US news reports have tended to give roughly equal weight to
skeptics with little peer-reviewed evidence (Boyko 2005; Mooney 2004).
Other journalistic norms may also reduce the likelihood of eective/informative policy discussion
in the mass media. Reporters often prefer conict frames to increase news consumer interest,
but the news reports that emerge often lack sucient context (Iyengar 1991; Iyengar and Kinder
Mass media and policy-making
207
1987). Emphasizing the conict frame of environmental debates decreases public awareness of
the scientic consensus regarding the existence of human-triggered climate change, for instance
(Corbett and Durfee 2008; Nisbet and Myers 2007). Content analyses of climate change news
in the New York Times, the Washington Post, the Los Angeles Times and the Wall Street Journal from
1998 through 2002 suggest that the journalistic attempts to be even-handed sowed far greater
public doubts about global warming than exist within the scientic community (Boyko and
Boyko 2007). Studies of television news have found that these attempts to provide balance in
stories made scientic ndings on climate change appear to the public as far more tentative than
they actually were (Boyko 2007a).
Additional problems with media coverage of complicated policy domains have emerged in
other studies. First, scientic uncertainty and other technical matters tend to be papered over by
reporters who do not mention that correlation is not causation, or that preliminary ndings are
tentative (Murray et al. 2001). Complexities, in other words, that too often are ignored in favor
of a more compelling and denitive, if less accurate, narrative. In cases where policy specialists oer
an interpretation that is too nuanced or too technical (others might say accurate), reporters
are tempted to rely on environmental activists who are quicker with a pithy quote, even though
they may not possess the credentials of the less-quotable scientic experts (Lichter and Rothman
1999). Part of the problem may be the relatively limited policy expertise possessed by many
reporters. Work suggests, for instance, that a lack of expertise has been important in journalists
susceptibility to marginal claims of potential health hazards, such as the relative dangers posed by
pesticides on apples or Bisphenol A (BPA) in water bottles when compared, for example, to
cigarette smoking or obesity (Murray et al. 2001; Lichter 2009).
Second, when elected ocials weigh in on policy, political issues tend to become increasingly
prominent in the public discussion. That is, the interaction of politics and policy in the media
tends to reduce attention to substantive policy matters and refocus concern on estimations of
politically viable policy options (Miller et al. 1990; Wilkins and Patterson 1991).
Third, and perhaps most relevant, one problem in policy coverage by the media is that the
very long-term nature of some policy domains works against the traditional newsroom norms of
timeliness and novelty (McCright and Dunlap 2003; Trumbo 1995). While news coverage can
focus intensely on scientic issues when a hurricane makes landfall or when a severe drought
decimates crop yields, media attention can evaporate as quickly as it emerges (Mazur 2009; Mazur
and Lee 1993). For instance, content analysis of climate change reports in the New York Times
and Washington Post from 1980 to 1995 shows an attention cycle of media interest in global
warming, where coverage increases in the early stages of discussion but erodes over time
(McComas and Shanahan 1999). Early coverage was anchored by dire projections from scientists,
while a middle phase of coverage focused on disagreements among scientists to maintain interest,
and a later phase of reduced coverage concentrated on the economic costs and political debates
over potential remedies. The rapid turnover of issues in mainstream news works against gradual
long-term stories like climate change, particularly if the dire early predictions do not appear to
come to pass shortly after they are made (Stevens 1993).
An expository analysis: environmental coverage in Canada
1
The preceding section has drawn on work focused on environmental policy in particular for good
reason: there is a growing body of work dealing with the problems with media coverage of envir-
onmental issues. A recurring theme is the tendency for a strong connection between environ-
mental coverage and major eventsor, more precisely, a lack of environmental coverage in the
absence of major weather or climate events. For instance, a comparison of global warming news
Soroka et al.
208
in top circulation newspapers in the US and the UK found a much greater volume of coverage
in the UK, though the number of news reports in both nations increased notably (and tem-
porarily) around key environmental events, such as new expert reports on greenhouse gas
emissions caused by air travel (a key issue of the G8 summit in June 2005), and the release of Al
Gores lm, An Inconvenient Truth, a year later (Boyko 2007a).
The biggest challenge in media coverage of environmental politics may be, then, that despite
the long-term nature of many environmental issues, environmental news is really not all that
dierent from other types of news: as with coverage of a wide range of policy issues, events with
immediate impacts are both easier and more attractive to cover than continuous monitoring of a
known issue. And in the absence of such events, regardless of the actual state of the environ-
ment, environmental issues will disappear from the media agenda (and quite possibly the policy
agenda as well).
This event-driven tendency in media is relatively easily illustrated. We focus here on a body
of content-analytic data of all news stories from the nightly newscast for CTV in Canada (the
nightly newscast with the largest audience shares in each country) from 1999 to 2009. Data were
gathered using full-text indices in Nexis, and relying on the Nexis topic eld to identify stories
for which a major theme (based on the Nexis subject-coding scheme) was the environment.
In total, the database includes 1,789 news stories.
We begin by subject-coding stories based on an iterative automated process. We rst look at
frequencies for all words and phrases in the stories (analyzed together), using WordStat. We
then take the most common words and phrasesthose relating to the environmentand build
a dictionary of commonly used terms. We add these terms, gradually, to the topic dictionarythe
product of a combination of data processing and common sense. A story is then coded as a given
topic if at least two keywords for that category were present in the text. The resulting codes thus
are indicators of the prevalence of specic language relating to various environmental issues.
Our focus here is on two topics in particular: pollution/climate change, and weather and
natural disasters.
2
Figure 16.1 shows trends in coverage for both topics over time. What is most
important to draw from the gure is (a) the tendency for weather and natural disasters to pro-
duce more news than pollution and climate change and (b) the lack of any upward trend in
coverage of environmental issues in spite of increasing environmental diculties worldwide.
Media coverage of pollution and climate change does not, at least in terms of the volume of
coverage, appear to reect trends in environmental indicators.
The more striking nding from these data is shown in Table 16.1, however. The table pre-
sents results from a relatively simple Granger causality testa statistical test of the temporal
relationship between the number of articles relating to disasters/weather and the number of
articles dealing with pollution/climate change.
Analyses rely on weekly data, and Granger tests proceed as follows. Total current coverage of
disasters/weather is regressed on the last weeks coverage of disasters/weather, as well as the last
weeks coverage of pollution/climate change. Results show, controlling for past coverage of
disasters/weather, whether pollution/climate change coverage systematically leads to disasters/
weather coverage. The same model is also estimated in the opposite direction: pollution/climate
change coverage is regressed on last weeks coverage of pollution/climate change, and last weeks
coverage of disasters/weather. Drawing on both models, we have a good sense of the extent to
which disasters/weather leads pollution/climate change, and vice versa.
Both models are estimated simultaneously using OLS vector autoregression; estimated coef-
cients are shown in Table 16.1. In the rst column, we see that current coverage of disasters/
weather is related to the previous weeks coverage of disasters/weather. (The coecient is .32,
and is statistically signicant.) The same is not true for the previous weeks coverage of
Mass media and policy-making
209
Figure 16.1 Coverage of natural disasters/weather and pollution/climate change by year
Source: Stuart Soroka, Stephen Farnsworth, Lori Young and Andrea Lawlor (2009) Environment
and energy policy: Comparing reports from US and Canadian television news. Paper presented
at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Toronto.
Soroka et al.
210
pollution/climate change. That is, there is no relationship between current coverage of weather
or disasters, and the preceding weeks reports on pollution or climate change.
The second column includes the model for current coverage of pollution or climate change.
Here, we see that current coverage of pollution and climate change is related to last weeks coverage
of climate change (a coecient of .26), but also to last weeks coverage of disasters and events (a
coecient of .06). There is, then, evidence here of a unidirectional causal eect: coverage of
pollution and climate change is systematically (and positively) led by coverage of weather and
disasters. (Put dierently, coverage of disasters and events Granger-causes coverage of pollution
and climate change.)
In sum, these data suggest that substantive coverage of environmental themes such as air pollu-
tion, global warming and climate change increases after major weather-related disasters and events.
Indeed, one interpretationdrawing on the literature discussed aboveis that coverage of pollu-
tion and climate change is dependent on weather-related disasters and events. As we might expect,
reporters apparently nd it hard to write about climate change without reference to high tem-
peratures and weather-related disasters. A sustained conversation on the environment is unlikely,
our ndings suggest, to exclude a steady stream of oods, hurricanes, ice storms, power blackouts,
and other climate mayhem.
Conclusions
There is little doubt that mass media play an important role in policy-making. A growing body of
literature highlights this role, both in terms of issue attentiveness and policy framing. We have argued
here, however, that it is important to note, rst, that media matter not just at the beginning but
throughout the policy process, and second, that medias involvement in the policy process poses
some real diculties. In short, the complexities of policy-making are likely not to be well served
by well-known tendencies in media coverage. That media matter to policy-making seems beyond
doubt. Whether their contribution tends to be positive on balance is, however, up for discussion.
Notes
1 This section draws on analyses in Soroka et al. 2009.
2 The rst is captured using the following keywords: acid rain, air, carbon, climate change, emission*, global
warming, greenhouse gas*, pollution, pollute*, toxic, toxin*, ozone; the second is based on: ood*, forest
re*, wildre*, wild re*, hurricane*, storm*, drought*, rain*, wind*, ice, weather, tornado*.
Table 16.1 Coverage of natural disasters/weather and pollution/climate change
DV:
disasters/
weather
t
DV: pollution/climate Change
t
Disasters/weather
t-1
.315* .061
a
(.109) (.035)
Pollution/climate Change
t-1
.019 .259*
(.051) (.043)
Constant 1.114* .776*
(.109) (.090)
R-sq .101 .079
Notes: N=520. * p < .05; a p < .10. Estimates rely on weekly data. Cells contain coefcients from an OLS vector
regression, with standard errors in parentheses.
Source: Author
Mass media and policy-making
211
Bibliography
Bartels, L.M. 1996, September. Politicians and the press: Who leads, who follows? in APSA. San
Francisco, CA.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
——, Bryan D. Jones and Beth L. Leech. 1997. Media attention and Congressional agendas, in Shanto
Iyengar and Richard Reeves (eds) Do the Media Govern? Politicians, Voters, and Reporters in America
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Berelson, Bernard R., Paul F. Lazarsfeld and William N. McPhee. 1954. Voting: A Study of Opinion Formation
in a Presidential Campaign. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Berger, B. 2001. Private issues and public policy: Locating the corporate agenda in agenda-setting theory,
Journal of Public Relations Research 13(2): 91126.
Birkland, Thomas A. 1998. Focusing events, mobilization, and agenda setting, Journal of Public Policy
18(1): 5374.
—— 2007. Agenda setting in public policy, in Frank Fischer, Gerald J. Miller and Mara S. Sidney (eds)
Handbook of Public Policy Analysis. London: Taylor & Francis.
Boykoff, Maxwell. 2005. The disconnect of news reporting from scientic evidence, Nieman Reports,
Harvard University, winter: 86.
—— 2007a. From convergence to contention: United States mass media representations of anthropogenic
climate change science, Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 32: 47789.
—— 2007b. Flogging a dead norm? Newspaper coverage of anthropogenic climate change in the United
States and the United Kingdom from 20032006, Area 39: 47081.
——and Jules M. Boyko. 2007. Climate change and journalistic norms: A case study of US mass media
coverage, Geoforum 38: 1190204.
Cobb, R.W. and C.D. Elder. [1972]1983. Participation in American Politics: The Dynamics of Agenda-Building.
Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
Cohen, Bernard C. 1963. The Press and Foreign Policy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Cook, Fay Lomax, Tom R. Tyler, Edward G. Goetz, Margaret T. Gordon, David Protess, Donna R. Le,
and Harvey L. Molotch. 1983. Media and agenda setting: Eects on the public, interest group leaders,
policy makers, and policy, The Public Opinion Quarterly 47(1): 1635.
Corbett, Julia B. and Jessica Durfee. 2008. Testing public (un)certainty of science: Media representations
of global warming, Science Communication 26: 12951.
Dearing, James W. and Everett M. Rogers. 1996. Agenda-Setting. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Downs, Anthony. 1972. Up and down with ecology: The issue attention cycle”’, The Public Interest 28: 3550.
Druckman, James N. 2001. On the limits of framing eects: Who can frame? The Journal of Politics 63:
10411066.
——and Michael Parkin. 2005. The impact of media bias: How editorial slant aects voters, The Journal of
Politics 67(4): 103049.
Edelman, M. 1964. The Symbolic Uses of Politics. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
—— 1977. Political Language. New York: Academic Press.
Eilders, C. 2000. Media as political actors? Issue focusing and selective emphasis in the German quality
press, German Politics 9(3): 181206.
—— 2001. Conict and Consonance in Media Opinion: Political Positions of Five German Quality Papers. Berlin:
WZB Discussion Papers.
Entman, Robert. 1993. Framing: Toward clarication of a fractured paradigm, Journal of Communication
43(4): 518.
—— 2004. Projections
of Power: Framing
News, Public Opinion and Foreign Policy. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Farnsworth, Stephen J. and S. Robert Lichter. 2006. The Mediated Presidency: Television News and Presidential
Governance. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littleeld.
—— and S. Robert Lichter. 2011. The Nightly News Nightmare: Media Coverage of US Presidential Elections,
19882008. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littleeld. Third Edition.
Fischer, Frank. 2003. Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative Practices. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Flickinger, Richard. 1983. The comparative politics of agenda-setting: The emergence of consumer
protection as a public policy issue in Britain and the United States, Policy Studies Review 2(3): 42944.
Soroka et al.
212
Gamson, W.A. 1989. News as framing: Comments on Graber, American Behavioral Scientist 33: 15766.
—— 1992. Talking Politics, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
——and A. Modigliani. 1987. The changing culture of armative action, in R.G. Braungart and M.M.
Braungart (eds) Research in Political Sociology. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
Gandy, O.H., Jr. 1982. Beyond Agenda Setting: Information Subsidies and Public Policy. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Herman, Edward S. and Noam Chomsky. 1988. Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass
Media. New York: Panetheon.
Hilgartner, Stephen and Charles L. Bosk. 1988. The rise and fall of social problems: A public arenas
model, American Journal of Sociology 94(1): 53 78.
Iyengar, Shanto. 1991. Is Anyone Responsible? How Television Frames Political Issues. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
—— 1993. Agenda-setting and beyond: Television news and the strength of political issues, in William
Riker (ed.) Agenda Formation. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
——and Donald R. Kinder. 1987. News That Matters. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Jensen, Carsten. 2009. Policy punctuations in mature welfare states, Journal of Public Policy 29(3): 287303.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agenda-Setting, Alternatives and Public Policies. New York: Harper Collins.
—— 1995. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York: HarperCollins College Publishers.
Lang, Kurt and Gladys Engel Lang. 1966. The mass media and voting, in Bernard Berelson and Morris
Janowitz (eds) Reader in Public Opinion and Communication. New York: Free Press.
Larson, Stephanie. 2001. Poll coverage of the 2000 presidential campaign on network news, paper
delivered at the 2001 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco.
Lasswell, Harold D. 1949. Style in the language of politics, in Harold Lasswell and N. Leites (eds) The
Language of Politics: Studies in Quantitative Semantics. New York: George Stewart, 2039.
Lichter, S. Robert. 2009. Are chemicals killing us? Experts speak out,
STATS (21 May report). Available
at: http://stats.org/stories/2009/are_chemicals_killing_us.html (accessed
2 August, 2009).
Lichter, S. Robert, and Stanley Rothman. 1999. Environmental Cancer: A Political Disease? New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
McChesney, Robert. 1999. Rich Media, Poor Democracy: Communications Politics in Dubious Times. New
York: Times Press.
McComas, Katherine and James Shanahan. 1999. Telling stories about global climate change: Measuring
the impact of narratives on issue cycles, Communication Research 26: 3057.
McCombs, M. 2004. Setting the Agenda: The Mass Media and Public Opinion. Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishing Inc.
——and Donald L. Shaw. 1972. The agenda-setting function of mass media, Public Opinion Quarterly
36(2): 17687.
——and J.H. Zhu. 1995. Capacity, diversity, and volatility of the public agenda: Trends from 1954 to
1994, Public Opinion Quarterly 59: 495525.
——, D.L. Shaw, and D. Weaver. 1997. Communication and Democracy: Exploring the Intellectual Frontiers in
Agenda-Setting Theory. Mahwah: NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
McCright, Aaron M. and Riley E. Dunlap. 2003. Defeating Kyoto: The conservative movements impact
on US climate change policy, Social Problems 50: 34873.
McQuail, D. 1994. Mass Communication Theory: An Introduction, 3rd edn. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Mayer, Robert N. 1991. Gone yesterday, here today: Consumer issues in the agenda-setting process,
Journal of Social Issues 47(1): 2139.
Mazur, Allan. 2009. American generation of environmental warnings: Avian inuenza and global warming,
Human Ecology Review 16: 1726.
——and Linling Lee. 2003. Sounding the global alarm: Environmental issues in the US national news,
Social Studies of Science 23: 681720.
Miller, S. M., A. Evers and H. Winterberger. 1990. The evolving welfare state mixes,inShifts in
the
Welfare Mix: Their
Impact on Work, Social Services and Welfare Policies. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag,
37188.
Mooney, Chris. 2004. Blinded by science: How balanced coverage lets the scientic fringe hijack reality,
Columbia Journalism Review, November/December.
Murray, David, Joel Schwartz and S. Robert Lichter. 2001. It Aint Necessarily So: How Media Make and
Unmake the Scientic Picture of Reality. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littleeld.
Nelson, Barbara. 1984. Making an Issue of Child Abuse: Political Agenda-Setting for Social Problems. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Mass media and policy-making
213
Nisbet, Matthew C. and Teresa Myers. 2007. Twenty years of public opinion about global warming,
Public Opinion Quarterly 71: 44470.
Patterson, Thomas E. 1994. Out of Order. New York: Vintage.
Peters, B. Guy and Brian W. Hogwood. 1985. The Pathology of Public Policy. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Price, V. and D. Tewksbury. 1997. News values and public opinion: A theoretical account of media
priming and framing, in G.A. Barett and F.J. Boster (eds) Progress in Communication Sciences: Advances in
Persuasion. Greenwich, CT: Ablex.
Pritchard, David. 1986. Homicide and bargained justice: The agenda-setting eect of crime news on
prosecutors, Public Opinion Quarterly 50(2): 14359.
—— 1992. The news media and public policy agendas, in. D. Kennamer (ed.) Public Opinion, the Press
and Public Policy. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Rabin, Matthew. 1998. Psychology and Economics, Journal of Economic Literature 36: 1146.
Rosenau, Pauline V. 1993. Anticipating a post-modern policy current? Policy Currents 3: 14.
Schattschneider, E.E. 1960. The Semisovereign People. New York: Rineheart and Wilson.
Scheufele, Dietram A. and David Tewksbury. 2007. Framing, agenda setting, and priming: The evolution
of three media eects models, Journal of Communication 57(1): 920.
Sniderman, P.M., R.A. Brody and P.E. Tetlock. 1991. Reasoning and Choice: Explorations in Political Psychology .
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Soroka, Stuart. 2002. Agenda-Setting Dynamics in Canada. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
——, Stephen Farnsworth, Lori Young and Andrea Lawlor. 2009. Environment and energy policy:
Comparing reports from US and Canadian television news, paper presented at the Annual Meeting of
the American Political Science Association, Toronto.
Spector, Malcolm and John I. Kitsuse. 1977. Constructing Social Problems. Menlo Park, CA: Cummings.
Stevens, W.K. 1993. Scientists confront renewed backlash on global warming, New York Times,1
4Se
ptember.
Stone, Deborah. 1989. Causal stories and the formation of policy agendas, Political Science Quarterly 104(2):
281300.
Trumbo, Craig. 1995. Longitudinal modeling of public issues: An application of the agenda-setting process
to the issue of global warming, Journalism and Mass Communication Monographs 152(August): 157.
—— 1996. Constructing climate change: Claims and frames in US news coverage of an environmental
issue, Public Understanding of Science 5: 26983.
Tuchman, G. 1978. Making News: A Study in the Construction of Reality. New York: Free Press.
Walgrave, Stefaan and Peter Van Aelst. 2006. The contingency of the mass medias political agenda setting
power: toward a preliminary theory, Journal of Communication 56(1): 88109.
——, Stuart Soroka and Michiel Nuytemans. 2007. The mass medias political agenda-setting power: A
longitudinal analysis of media, parliament, and government in Belgium (1993 to 2000) , Comparative
Political Studies 41(6): 81436.
Wilkins, Lee and Philip Patterson. 1991. Science as symbol: The media chills the greenhouse eect,in
Lee Wilkins and Philip Patterson (eds) Risky Business: Communication Issues of Science, Risk and Public
Policy. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 15976.
Yagade, A. and Dozier D.M. 1990. The media agenda-setting eect of concrete versus abstract issues,
Journalism Quarterly 67: 310.
Zhu, J.H. 1992. Issue competition and attention distraction: A zero-sum theory of agenda setting, Journalism
Quarterly 69: 82536.
Zucker, H.G. 1978. The variable nature of news media inuence,
in B.D. Ruben (ed.) Communication
Yearbook, vol 2. New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books.
Soroka et al.
214
Part V
Understanding the
formulation process
17
Policy design and transfer
Anne Schneider
Policy design, whether conceptualized as a verb referring to the process of formulating public
policy, or as a noun describing the content of public policy remains largely uncharted territory.
This chapter reviews what we know about policy designs and develops ideas about how the
study of policy design can contribute to an understanding of policy transfer and diusion. Policy
scholars have long been interested in understanding how policies are copied, stolen, or diuse
across jurisdictions, but much of the attention has been on the politics and geographic proxi-
mity of the innovating statesthat is, the ones that were early adopters (Walker 1969). The
focus in this chapter is on what types of policy designs are most likely to transfer and which
ones may be subject to truncated transfer or to not move at all (Schneider and Ingram 1988).
Theories of policy invention and expert decision-making suggest that individuals search through
large amounts of relevant information stored in memory, reason by analogies, make comparisons,
and either copy or simulate patterns of information to produce desired consequences. These
consequences may focus on good public policy that resolves important collective problems,
or on gaining political capital, or a broad array of more narrow-gauged goals. On the other hand,
social psychologists have documented that even experts are subject to a wide range of cognitive
biases, and these biases nd their way into public policy designs (Kahneman et al. 1982). Rather
than simply a benign process of ecient decision-making, cognitive biases may operate at the
expense of policy that would serve democratic ends. In the remaining parts of this chapter, I
will rst explore policy designing as it commonly occurs with an emphasis on the role of decision
heuristics and cognitive biases, and then develop a framework for analyzing policy designthat
is, policy content. From the analysis of the elements of design found in almost all public poli-
cies, it is possible to identify a number of commonly copied designs and their implications for
democracy.
Background
Two very dierent approaches to the study of policy design have emerged in the literature
(Schneider and Ingram 1988, 1993, 1997, 2005; Howlett and Lejano 2011; Linder and Peters 1985;
Bobrow and Dryzek (1987). What these approaches have in common is a desire to improve the
consequences of public policythe outputs or outcomes of policy. They dier considerably,
217
however, in the focus of attention, dene the term dierently, and also come at the problem of
producing what might be considered good public policy from very dierent perspectives.
The rationalist approach denes policy design as a rational and systematic eort to achieve
eective and ecient policy. Howlett and Lejano (2013), for example, dene policy design as
the eort to more or less systematically develop ecient and eective policies through the
application of knowledge about policy means gained from experience, and reason, the devel-
opment and adoption of courses of action that are likely to succeed in attaining their desired
goals or aim.
(forthcoming: 3)
Design, in this approach, is mainly used as a verb and is a particular type of process emphasizing
rational, scientic, and logical thinking toward identifying the most eective and ecient means
to a given end.
The second tradition, best developed by Schneider and Ingram (1997), but tracing its roots
also to Dahl and Lindblom (1953), Forester (1989), Schőn (1994); Stone (1988) begins with
policy design as policy contentbroadly understoodand not just those aspects of the policy
text and practices that are rationalistic, grounded in science or logic, or even systematically put
into place. Policy design, according to Schneider and Ingram (1997: 2)
refers to the content or substance of public policythe blueprints, architecture, discourses,
and aesthetics of policy in both its instrumental and symbolic form.
Policy designing is the process through which this policy content is produced, and (again) not
just the systematic and rational in terms of clearly stated public policy goals, but also the cognitive
biases embedded in the policy as well as attributes damaging to the linkage between public
policy and democratic principles, such as the intentionally manipulative, deceptive, illogical,
mean-spirited, and unscientic factors that inuenced the choice of design elements.
This chapter begins with the presumption that policy design is more a process of copying and
adaptation than of invention, at least at the policy-maker level. Model legislation and guide-
lines commonly are drafted by policy entrepreneurs who attempt to spread a particular policy
idea throughout the nation. And, policy-makers pay close attention to the policy designs being
used elsewhere, as has been well-documented in the studies of policy diusion (Karch 2007).
Second, the process of designing is not necessarily intended to produce the policy goals that are
touted as the probable result, but are lled with compromises, attempts to build sucient
support for passage, rationales that may have little to do with the actual motivations, and out-
right deception. Policy-makers have both political and policy goals, as well as personal goals
that inuence their choice of design elements. Designs contain embedded social construc-
tions, images, and symbols that send messages to target populations and the broader public
about who is deserving of what, and why (Schneider and Ingram 1993, 1997, 2005). Designs
embed, as well, the cognitive biases and decision heuristics of those who crafted the content of
the policy. For these reasons, it is essential that analysts develop a framework for systematically
analyzing and comparing policy designs (content). It is no longer sucient just to say that it is
education policy, or three strikes and youre out, or an anti-immigration bill. More
information is needed about the actual array of elements in the design. The study of policy transfer,
innovation, and diusion typically has not paid much attention to actually what was transferred
or copied across jurisdictional lines, other than the very broad popularized title for the policy
such as an immigration law as
tough at Arizonas. Thus,
a more careful and comprehensive
Schneider
218
approach to the study of policy design can contribute to a number of areas of policy and
political research.
To limit the study of policy design entirely to those aspects that are rational and systematic is
not necessary and makes a serious mistake in understanding the reasons certain designs are
chosen and the consequences of those designs for democracy. Policy designs can fruitfully be
understood with an analogy to the design of a city. A city probably has some elements that
were designed intentionally to be ecient and eectivesuch as the system of streets and roads,
the placement of light rail and trac lights, the water and power delivery systems. But some
aspectsmany in factof a design were not put in place by any overall intentional or sys-
tematic or scientic process. The used car parked on the sidewalk is an aspect of the design of a
city at a particular moment, as is the green grass or desert landscaping at a new housing devel-
opment. At any given moment, every element in the city is a part of its design. And, the design
of a city is constantly changing as new houses are built, new roads put in place, changes in
trac patterns, landscaping, and so on. Yet, it is possible to stop the scene at any moment and
capture the exact design of that city, at that moment.
This chapter builds on an understanding of how policy designs are crafted and chosen. First,
ample research points out that designs often are copied, borrowed, or stolen from similar poli-
cies elsewhere (Schneider and Ingram 1988). With the exception of some very early studies of
policy diusion (Gray 1973), most of the research has largely ignored the characteristics of the
policies themselves, and focused on which kinds of cities, states, or nations are most innova-
tive”—dened as early adopters. Thus, a huge uncharted area of research is why some kinds
of policy designs are copied and spread whereas others are truncated and others never even begin
to move across jurisdictional lines (see Karch 2007). Second, the reasoning process through
which people arrive at decisions relies heavily on decision heuristicsdeviations from rational
decision-makingthat introduce biases into policy design. And equally important, knowledge
about how people reason has become a fundamental tool of political leaders who manipulate
media and citizens by using policy arguments and designs as a technique to gain public support
for policy that actually will not produce the consequences touted for it and may work to the
actual disadvantage of those that the rhetoric implies will gain from it. Third, this chapter draws
on Schneider and Ingrams theory of degenerative policy-making and policy design to identify
characteristics of policy that often are copied and appropriated from other jurisdictions
(Schneider and Ingram 1993, 1997).
Policy design as a verb: cognitive biases and decision heuristics
This discussion begins with the insight from sociology and social psychology that people have a
tendency to identify with an in group and embellish its virtues as well as nd the other
from which they not only distance themselves, but socially construct as dangerous, undeserving,
lazy, stupid, or other undesirable epitaphs. This apparently fundamental trait of modern human
beings plays a central role in the ways that decision heuristics and cognitive biases aect politics
and public policy.
The in group preference along with the theory of decision heuristics and cognitive biases
form the micro-level theory of this approach to policy design. Kahneman et al. (1982) and
others have identied a number of common heuristics (rules of thumb) that peopleeven
expertsrely on to make decisions. One of the most common in the process of policy design is
availability. Availability refers to the ease by which a particular instance or occurrence or causal
event is brought to mind. Those that are most easily brought to mind include those that are
more recent, more dynamic or colorful, more consistent with biases and prejudices. Why, for
Policy design and transfer
219
example, have the American states altered their policies since the early 1970s to produce the highest
incarceration rate in the world? One could contend that it is simply to gain political capital. But
that brings up the next questionwhy does it work to produce political capital? And a pro-
mising explanation is that most people nd it easy to imagine that if you threaten enough, and
punish severely enough, and catch people when they commit a crime; they will stop committing
crimes. Why has tough on immigration legislation spread like wildre across the United States
in the past several years, but the Utah Compact that advocates a much more benign approach
even though thoroughly grounded in the principles of conservatives has gained almost no traction?
Saying that tough on immigration produces political capital, again, is not enough: why does it
work to produce such presumably large political payos? Decision theory suggests it is easy
for people to buy into the notion that people who are in this country illegally are deceptive,
criminal, lazy, dangerous and other negative social constructions. Decision theory suggests that
this image is considerably easier to imagine than one in which illegal aliens as they are com-
monly called, are good, honest, hard-working people who value their families. Why did policy-
makers leading up to the 2012 elections tie every conceivable policy proposal to job creation?
Decision theory suggests that it is easier for people to imagine that if businesses both large and
small had more money (through tax cuts), they would create more jobs than to believe that if
the government spent more money, it would create more jobs. The highly negative social con-
struction of government, compared with the far more positive construction of business in the
rst decade of the twenty-rst century is a prime reason. As Stimson (1991) has shown, national
moods exist and exert a powerful inuence over what it is that people nd easy to believe.
Social psychologists have also documented an availability cascade in which an assertion is
repeated often enough that the simple repetition adds to the perception of its accuracy.
The combination of policy-makers themselves relying on cognitive biases when they propose
policy and the ease of convincing the public of their contentions has produced an alarming lack
of rationality in the designing process. As David Brooks (2011) said, the American public is
suering from intellectual laziness of massive proportions. He speaks specically of the problems
introduced by contribution bias. Research has shown consistently that people sort through all of
the purported facts and evidence that comes to their attention, but they primarily focus only on
the facts, studies, and anecdotal incidents that conrm what they already know and they easily
dismiss even the most prestigious studies if those contradict their current knowledge. Challenges
to the methodology of global warming studies, for example, come almost exclusively from those
who already believe that either global warming is not occurring or that humans have no hand
in it. In spite of massive scientic consensus, leading candidates for president such as Rick Perry
of Texas in 2012 repeatedly paid attention only to the facts that already supported his beliefs.
Others play into this same tendency toward intellectual laziness when they use specic incidents,
such as Hurricane Katrina, as proof that global warming is occurring.
Closely related to availability, illusory
correlations are another
example of cognitive bias
that inuences policies designs. Illusory correlations are those that are easy to imagine but have
no scientic basis. For example, it is easy to believe that if a business has more money, it will
expand and create more jobs. If America sends its military forces into a small, weak country like
Vietnam, Iraq, or Afghanistan, the war will be won quickly and easily. And if not, it is easy to
justify the mistaken correlation on the grounds, for example, that enough troops were not sent.
Anchoring is another heuristic important in understanding policy designing. The idea here is
that people start from a particular point and then make small adjustments in various directions but
commonly do not make adequate adjustments. Change the anchor point, and a dierent policy
design will emerge. Another heuristic is overcondence in the prediction of eectseven
experts become over time more condent that a highly unlikely event will actually occur. For
Schneider
220
example, scientists involved in nuclear energy research consistently overestimate the likelihood
of nuclear accidents (Kahneman et al. 1982).
Decision-makers have become considerably more savvy about the persuasive techniques that
may be used to gain public support (or opposition) and the arguments surrounding policy
choices have become particularly disingenuous. The ndings of the social psychologists are used
not to correct for cognitive biases, but to rely on them as ways to shift public opinion and
opinion leaders toward a particular point of view. The social construction of government has
become so negative that everyone wants to run as an outsider. The social construction of the word
socialist is viewed as so antithetical to American values that simply labeling a policy proposal
as socialist is commonly used as a way to kill the idea even though the United States has
dozens, even hundreds, of programs that by almost any denition are socialist ranging from
public schools to the ownership of the Green Bay Packers!
An example of how public ocials use the insights from cognitive and decision research to
reinforce certain biases is found in Senator John McCains response when he was asked what he
thought about the cause of Arizonas most destructive forest re in historythe Wallow re of
2011. He had just been briefed about the Wallow re, and it had been compared to the second
most destructive re in Arizona history, the Rodeo-Chedeski re, both of which occurred in
the northeast part of Arizona. McCain was asked:
How do you explain two massive record wildres, all being said, human caused, but how
do you explain such huge res and how do you x this from happening?
(Arizona Republic, B1)
His response:
Well rst of all we are concerned about particular areas down on the border where there is
substantial evidence that some of these res are caused by people who have crossed our
border illegally. They have set res because they want to signal others, they have set res to
keep warm, and they have set res in order to divert law enforcement agents and agencies
from them. So the answer to that part of the problem is, get a secure border.
Liberals quickly jumped all over this comment as there was no evidence that immigrants had
started the re and both of these res were more than 300 miles away from the Mexican border.
McCain retaliated, pointing out that he did not say the Wallow re was caused by an illegal
immigrantand it was factually correct that he had not made that statement. (Two white male
campers had been arrested for letting their campre get out of control and starting this re that
destroyed more than 500,000 acres). His oce retaliated with this statement:
The facts are clear. For years, federal, state and local ocials
have stated that smugglers and
illegal immigrants have
caused res on our southern border.
This statement went on to say that McCainsoce had asked for a study and that it would be
out in about a month. And on July 8, 2011, Jim Pena, a US Forest Service associate deputy
chief, testi ed before the House Subcommittee on National Parks, Forests and Public Lands
that between 2002 and 2011, 457 res were determined to be human-caused in the southwest
border area of the Coronado National Forest. Pena added, Forest Service investigators have
been able to identify the individuals responsible in 31 of those res. Of those 31 res, it was
determined that undocumented aliens were responsible for starting ve.
Policy design and transfer
221
The Arizona Republics fact check upheld McCains position that he had not specically said
that illegal immigrants had caused the re. Yet, there was a clear association being made between
illegals and rean illusory correlation that played directly from the availability heuristic to
make it easier to believe that illegal immigrants are dangerous and the border must be secured
to protect Arizonans from wildres and other dangers that illegal immigrants bring into the state.
Furthermore, although it is true that the statement from McCainsoce only said that facts are
clear and that illegal immigrants have caused res on the southern border, the statement
deceives the reader by not going on to say that ve of 431 res were known to have been
started by illegal immigrants.
Framing eects are well known in the public policy literature and policy-makers have taken
advantage of these to draw together a number of dierent cognitive biases as a way to make a
persuasive argument. Policy analysts (and media fact checkers) may contribute signicantly to
improved policy design by paying careful attention not only to fact checking but also to the
types of cognitive biases built into the rationales and the ways that political leaders are using the
intellectual laziness of the public to gain support for legislation. It is not enough to just look
for the rational, instrumental logic of policy but to unmask the persuasive devices being used to
thwart rational, logical thinking and reliance on well-established facts.
Policy design as a noun (policy content)
Public policy has a common-sense understanding of being everything that government, or gov-
ernment agencies or street-level case workers do. This understanding means that public policy
includes documents such as constitutions, statutes, and court cases as well as agency guidelines,
state and local laws, and actual practices such as the ways that street-level case workers apply the
policy to a particular person or organization. Each of these contains a policy design, but at dif-
ferent levels of analysis. At whatever level the focus might be, an adequate empirical description
of policy design is essential. Development of particular types of designswith elements that tend
to cluster togetheris essential for linking politics to policy design and policy design to policy
consequences. Particular types and styles of political dynamics do not produce policy outcomes
directly, as is sometimes implied. Policy design is not a black box that has no bearing on con-
sequences. Rather, political dynamics produce policy designs and these, in turn, feed forward
to produce not only policy results but also to inuence the subsequent politics of the society.
In fact, it will be argued below that certain kinds of political dynamics are associated with cer-
tain types of policy designs and that these designs, in turn, have consequences for achievement
(or lack thereof) of the purported policy goals, and also systematic consequences for social identity,
political participation, justice, political gain or loss, and democracy in the broad sense of the word.
Policy designs embed aspects of the politics that created them, and the designs tend to reproduce
the same kinds of politics from which they emerged (Schneider and Ingram 1993, 2005).
This approach to policy design places its study within the empirical and normative tradition
of Lasswells who gets what, why, and how (Lasswell 1936). Thus, the study of policy design
as policy contentis a broad, coherent, and essential part of political science. This approach has
led to a new very important area of study called policy centric orientation; and it has led to
new ways of thinking about the empirical and normative aspects of the policy-making process
itself (see Mettler and Soss 2004).
From a normative perspective, public policy in a democracy is charged with the task of creating
democratic institutions; encouraging and promoting an active, engaged, and informed citizenry;
promoting justice as fairness for all people; and solving collective problems in ways that are
ecient and eective.
Schneider
222
From an empirical perspective, all public policies contain a set of central elements that can be
described, studied and compared. The argument made below is that these tend to cluster in
identiable patterns that can be identied and classi ed as certain types of policy designs. The
question is then, what kinds of policies, under what kinds of conditions, are most likely to be
copied, stolen, or borrowed by what kinds of political entities?
The fundamental elements of designs include goals or problems to be solved, target popula-
tions, benets or burdens to distribute, and linkage mechanisms of tools, rationales, underlying
assumptions, an implementation structure, and social constructions (of targets, goals, and other
elements) (Schneider and Ingram 1997). These elements are found in all levels of policyfrom
constitutions, to statutes, to agency guidelines, to state and local laws, and even to the discretion
that street-level agents of government use when they actually put a policy to work.
Goals of a policy at times may seem obvious, since written policy often contains a statement
of the problem to be solved or goals to be achieved. Goals or problems to be solved refer (on
the one hand) to the intentional aspects of designs and indicate what the purported consequences
are desired to be. On the other hand, actual goals may be masked and the policy itself strate-
gically attached to some widely acknowledged public problem that the policy has no realistic
chance of impacting with its true goals being largely hidden from sight (Stone 1988; Kingdon
1984). For example, in the run-up to the 2012 election, job creation was the purported number
one priority of almost all candidates from every party; yet policy proposals directly conicting
with one another attached themselves to this goal with utter disregard of the logic in the con-
nection. Perhaps the most memorable example of policies conveniently attaching themselves to
a problem came in the summer and fall before the 2000 presidential election when candidate
George Bush was arguing that tax cuts were needed because the government had a substantial
surplus. As the economy deteriorated in late summer and early fall, he switched his argument saying
that tax cuts were needed to stimulate the economy and ward o a recession.
Arizonas Senate Bill 1070, widely characterized as the strictest law again undocumented
people in the United States, carries the benecent title, Support Our Law Enforcement and
Safe Neighborhood Acts. The stated intent of the law is to make attrition through enforce-
ment the public policy of all of Arizona. The purpose, in other words, is to rid the state of
undocumented immigrants. The governors rationale for signing the bill, however, focused on
crime, violence, Mexican drug cartels, and the failure of the federal government in keeping
undocumented people out of the country. Opponents argued that Arizonas economy would
be severely damaged by the legislation both because of a likely boycott and because ridding the
state of workers and consumers is not the way to grow the economy. The political consequences
of the Hispanic vote were largely disregarded also even though almost one-third of the Arizona
adult population are of Hispanic origin. No evidence was presented or needed that undocu-
mented people damage the quality of life in Arizonaillusory correlations, availability and the
apparent desire to identify and punish the other were sucient. An early poll showed that 70
percent of the population agreed with the legislation, although that number dropped substantially
over several months.
Target populations are the people, groups, and organizations that are impacted by the policy.
Target populations are critical to policy eectiveness, since the target groups must coproduce or
behave in ways intended by the policy if the policy is to achieve its purported goals. In the
example above regarding Arizonas Senate Bill 1070, one of the reported purposes is to rid
the state of undocumented people. These people must either get the message and leave, or
the provisions of the law that enable local law enforcement to identify the undocumented and
refer them to federal authorities for deportation must be operative. Further, the federal ocials
are the only ones that can actually deport someone. Target populations, however, may not be
Policy design and transfer
223
chosen on the basis of goal achievement, at all. If the goal is to reduce crime, then shifting law
enforcement responsibilities from crime prevention and detection to nding undocumented
people who have not committed any crime, may not be an eective or ecient method of crime
prevention. Target groups may be selected on the basis of their direct linkage to goal achieve-
ment, but they also are selected on the basis of political power, wealth, images (particularly
whether they are deserving or undeserving, or other principles that send messages about
the values of the society. Furthermore, peoples experiences with government as targets shapes
their view of government and their understanding of their role in government. As Schneider
and Ingram argued:
the way targets are treated by policy is central to justice, citizenship, support for democratic
institutions, and democratic problem solving. Policy can either reinforce or undermine
government legitimacy and sense of civic duty.
(1997: 85)
Policy-makers have a choice among dierent target groups that can be involved or excluded
from policy. To create jobs, for example, policy can develop public works programs that actu-
ally create job programs that hire people and put them to work on road construction, bridges,
libraries, tutoring for school children, and aides for child protective services. Alternatively,
policy can cut corporate taxes with the contention that cutting corporate taxes will enable
corporations to expand thereby hiring people. Or policy can create jobs by providing tax credits
for new hires, and so on.
Policies allocate valuesbenets and burdensto target groups and this, too, oers policy-
makers a wide range of choices for solving any given problem. An entire chain of target groups
may be involved as intermediate linkages between policy design and goal achievement.
Some may be in line for benets, others for burdens. Target groups are sent messages by policy
design of what they deserve or do not deserve. Persons without jobs during the virtual collapse
of the US economy were told, on the one hand, that they deserved jobless benets and
that the amount of time they would be eligible would be extended, and on the other hand, that
paying jobless benets encouraged people to not look for jobs and in fact became a factor that
prolonged unemployment.
Rules refer to who is to do what, when, with what resources and limitations. Rules include
the eligibility criteria for receiving benets, as well as the behaviors that would lead to arrest and
punishment. Tools are the incentive and disincentives built into the design intended to insure
that agencies and target groups and any other players in the system take the policy-preferred
actions. Tools have been categorized in terms of the underlying behavioral assumptions: authority
(just doing what one is told to do); positive incentives, negative incentives or punishment, actual
force, symbolic and hortatory tools (persuasive devices), learning tools, and capacity-building
tools are examples. Tools are quite interchangeable and policy designers have a wide range of
choices regarding how to get target groups to follow the rules.
Implementation structures are often built into the policy design. These may be top-down com-
mand and control types of implementation or follow the ideas of adaptive management and
leave considerable discretion to the local implementers.
Rationales are the reasons, justications, or legitimations for the design itself. These may be
straightforward or deceptive, logically consistent or inconsistent, and based on a wide range of dif-
ferent values ranging from justice-oriented rationales to economic, scientic or religious. Ratio-
nales may reect the actual reasons, or the real reasons may be carefully masked as policy-makers
attempt to tie the policy to a popular problem for the purpose of gaining political capital and
Schneider
224
support. Underlying assumptions typically are not laid out in the policy design itself but are brought
to the analysis by the policy analyst. There are three types of assumptions: technical assumptions
that are scientic and can be tested with scientic research (including social sciences); normative
assumptions that the policy design is fair, just, compassionate, treats people as they ought to be
treated, consistent with prevailing values; and behavioral assumptions about what people need
to be motivated to act in policy-preferred ways.
Policy designs containin addition to these empirical elementsother more judgmental
characteristics such as the type of message (positive, negative) being sent to target populations;
the extent of deception in the design and the rationales used to justify it; and the strength of the
logic holding the elements together. These, too, are important aspects of design for the policy
analyst to unmask.
Commonly copied policy designs
One of the least developed aspects of the study of policy design is in the development of design
patterns clusters of elements that commonly go together. The approach that will be presented
here builds from my work and that of my colleague Helen Ingram to classify design types in terms
of the power and the social construction of the target populations and whether benets or burdens
are being distributed. We hypothesized that certain design elements tend to be used, depending
on this classication. Furthermore, subsequent work has contended that some types of policy
design will be more subject to path dependency than other types, and in the remaining part of
this chapter, the point will be made that some types are more likely to transfer than others.
Schneider and Ingram have argued that a great deal can be understood about the elements of
policy design by taking into account the political power of target populations, their social con-
struction (such as deserving or undeserving) and whether benets or burdens are being
distributed. Using this two-dimensional framework, target populations can be clustered generally
into one of four types: advantaged groups (politically powerful and positively constructed as deser-
ving, intelligent, hard-working, and other positive values of the society); contenders who are
politically powerful but carry a negative image as greedy,”“dishonest,”“undeserving of what they
have; dependents (politically weak but constructed as good but weak or helpless people); and
deviants (politically weak and carrying the image of dangerous, violent, mean, selsh). Most of
the research using this framework has focused on the allocation of benets and burdens consistent
with the theory and on the consequences of policy design for political attitudes and participation.
Far less has been done with the ideas that some types of designs are more apt to transfer or diuse
across jurisdictions than others, or are more (or less) likely to converge over time. Schneider
(2006) has shown that a particular type of designpolicies that inict harsh punishment on
those who break the law have been far more path-dependent, over time, than policies that
utilize rehabilitation, probation, house arrest, nes, or other less draconian policies. This study
based on state-level incarceration data from 1927 through 2003 showed far longer periods of
continuous increases in incarceration rates across almost all states than periods of decreases. The
research also found that state-level incarceration rates tend to change in the same direction, at the
same time, as if some kind of national mood were inuencing all of them at once, or that policy
designs were diusing rapidly throughout the nation even though decisions about incarceration
are made at the state and local level and in response to the state and local laws.
The most likely designs to transfer are those that t the dominant patterns identied by
Schneider and Ingram. The rst of these is providing benets to advantaged groups. The design
elements are expected generally to be quite similar across jurisdictions: strong statutes; tight
implementation structures but very little oversight or assessment of results; popular rationales
Policy design and transfer
225
that t into prevailing values, capacity building and learning tools for target groups; and uni-
versalistic rules of eligibility. These designs are politically popular regardless of whether one is
liberal or conservative since the target populations are considered deserving of what they receive
and the rationales are structured carefully to t prevailing values. Also, it is dicult to generate
opposition except on rational/instrumental or scientic grounds that the means will not pro-
duce the desired endsbut since most do not pay much attention to such logic, opposition is
dicult to generate. Strong statutes provide sucient detail to ensure that the benets are
actually delivered and not sidetracked in some ways. Once a program area, however, becomes
oversubscribed”—whereby so many benets are being provided that it becomes politically
risky and dicult to sustain the rationales or create new onesimplementing agencies can be
expected to be given discretion to determine eligibility. Implementation structures are tight in
that there are clear lines of authority and responsibility for carrying out the statutory intent. If
policy is not clear on the linkages between funding and desired outcomes, however, learning
and capacity-building tools may be used to help to guarantee that the programs work. Over-
sight, however, is weak or nonexistent or largely illusory except to prevent fraud that would
endanger the program. Rationales will depend on the prevailing ideas in good currency. If
jobs are needed and valued, the benets will be touted as contributing to job creation. If national
security is involved, the rationale will be based on national security. If fairness or justice is involved
and if that is a value currently in vogue, then it would be used. Policy tools will be largely
benignlearning tools providing adequate discretion even to target populations, capacity build-
ing, and direct handouts. Rules will tend toward the universalistic without means testing and
without other tight restrictions. Benets will tend to be provided now, not well into the future,
and signicant sums of money or tax breaks can be expected. Far less likely to transfer are designs
that inict burdens on advantaged populations, but when regulations are transferred, design
elements will tend to have weak statutes (providing multiple loopholes for advantaged groups to
escape), highly particularistic (only some of the advantaged are subject to the rules), and regulatory
activities can expect to be underfunded.
A second commonly copied type of design is expected to be providing punishment and dis-
cipline to deviant groups. These designs are expected also to involve universalistic rules (everyone
who breaks a particular law is supposed to be treated the same way as others); the rationales
focus on negative social constructions of the target groups as dangerous,”“untrustworthy,
already had their chance,”“violent, and so on. The logic connecting design elements to desired
results is largely unimportant provided that the target groups can continue to be constructed as
undeserving. Even though there is considerable political gain and ideological commitment to
punishing the undeserving, the political leaders do not want to spend much money on this task
if it can be avoided. Evaluation to discern program eectiveness is seldom used when punishment
is provided to undeserving people.
A third commonly copied design involves the provision of services or the discipline of various
kinds of dependent populations (children, women, mothers, disabled, etc.). These designs can
generally be expected to involve very particularistic rather than universalistic rules, typically means-
tested, far more talk than funding, especially from the federal level; tools to induce desired
behavior can be expected to rely on authority, persuasion, and expectations that the clients will
establish their own eligibilityno one will help them to do that. Rules contained in these policies
especially when benets are being distributed are expected to be strict, with complex eligibility
requirements. In contrast to the types of design discussed above where benets are provided to
advantaged groups or punishment to deviant groups, provision of benets to dependents typically
will require evaluation studies to prove the
worthiness of the
policy. Rationales will focus on
justice, fairness, and when discipline or punishment is involvedit is for their own good.
Schneider
226
A fourth type of commonly copied designs pertains to attempts to provide benets to contenders
(such as Wall Street, corporations, big labor, big banks) at the same time that the public
stance is to discipline and restrict these groups. Whether the design elements that are likely to
transfer will be the same across jurisdictions simply is not known but the theory strongly sug-
gests that benecial policy for contenders will transfer and will be the most deceptive of all the
types of designs.
Conclusions
Given the fact that public policies have increasingly been used for political and ideological purposes
rather than to nd the best solution to a collective problem, policy analysts are well advised to
study carefully the design elements and analyze them not simply in terms of their rationality,
but also in terms of who gets what, who wins and who loses, whose image is emboldened and
who is denigrated, and what are the messages being sent to the target populations and the broader
public. What are the impacts on political participation and attitudes? Is it the case that policy
designs embed the social constructions and assumptions and then reproduce that same pattern of
politics? Is policy itself partly responsible for the politics that ensue, as Lowi so famously argued
many years ago? It is not sucient to simply analyze policy designs in terms of their technical
logic and whether they achieve their purported goals? The full array of elements along with the
images, hidden messages, underlying assumptions, deception, and illogic need to be probed by
the policy analyst.
Bibliography
Arizona Republic, Sen. John McCain ties res to illegal border crossings, June 20, 2011, B1.
—— The issue: McCains comments on migrants, Wallow Fire, by Ginger Rough, August 27, 2011.
Bobrow, Davis B. and John Dryzek. 1987. Policy Analysis by Design. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh
Press.
Brooks, David. 2011. The Social Animal: The Hidden Sources of Love, Character, and Achievement. New York:
Random House Digital, Inc.
Dahl, Robert and Charles Lindblom. 1953. Politics, Economics, and Welfare. New York: Harper.
Forester, John. 1989. Planning in the Face of Power. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gray, Virginia. 1973. Innovation in the states: A diusion study, American Political Science Review 67(4):
117485.
Howlett, Michael and Raul Lejano. 2013. Tales from the crypt: The rise and fall (and rebirth?) of policy
design, Administration and Society (forthcoming)
Ingram, Helen and Anne L. Schneider. 1990. Improving implementation through framing smarter statutes,
Journal of Public Policy 10(1): 6687.
——and Anne L. Schneider. 1991. The choice of target populations, Administration and Society 23(3):
33356.
James, Oliver and Martin Lodge. 2003. The limitations of policy transfer and lesson drawing for
public policy research, Political Studies Review 1: 17993.
Kahneman, Daniel, Paul Slovic and Amos Tversky. 1982. Judgment under Uncertainty: Herusitics and Biases.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Karch, Andrew. 2007. Democratic Laboratories: Policy Diusion among the American States. Lansing, MI: University
of Michigan Press.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York: Longman.
Lasswell, Harold. 1936. Who Gets What, When, and How? New York: McGraw Hill.
Lieberman, Robert, Helen Ingram and Anne Schneider. 1995. Social
constructions, American Political
Science Review 89(2):
43744.
Linder, Stephen H. and Guy Peters. 1985. From social theory to policy design, Journal of Public Policy 4(3):
23759.
Policy design and transfer
227
Mettler, Suzanne and Joe Soss. 2004. The consequences of public policy for democratic citizenship:
bridging policy studies and mass politics, Perspectives on Politics 2(1): 5573.
Schneider, Anne Larason. 2006. Patterns of change in the use of imprisonment in the American states: An
integration of path dependence, punctuated equilibrium and policy design approaches, Political Research
Quarterly 59(3): 45770.
——and Helen Ingram. 1988. Systematically pinching ideas: A comparative approach to policy design,
Journal of Public Policy 8(1): 6180.
——and Helen Ingram. 1990. Behavioral assumptions of policy tools, Journal of Politics 52(2): 51029.
——and Helen Ingram. 1993. The social construction of target populations, The American Political Science
Review 87(2): 33446.
——and Helen Ingram. 1997. Policy Design for Democracy. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press.
——and Helen Ingram (eds). 2005. Deserving and Entitled: Social Construction and Public Policy. Albany, NY:
SUNY Press.
——and Mara Sidney. 2009. Whats next for policy design/social construction theory?, Policy Studies
Journal 37(1): 10319.
Schön, Donald and Martin Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Controversies.
New York: Basic Books.
Stone, D.A. 1988. Policy Paradox and Political Reason. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman.
Stimson, James. 1991. Public Opinion in America . Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Utah Compact. 2011. http://www.deseretnews.com/article/700080758/Ocial-text-of-Utah-Compact-
declaration-on-immigration-reform.html (Accessed 10 September 2011).
Walker, Jack. 1969. The diusion of innovations among the American states, American Political Science
Review 63(3): 88099.
Schneider
228
18
Epistemic communities
Claire A. Dunlop
Introduction
Peter M. Haas formulated the epistemic communities framework as a means of exploring the
inuence of knowledge-based experts in international policy-making. Specically, the approach was
designed to address decision-making instances characterized by technical complexity and uncer-
tainty. Control over the production of knowledge enables epistemic communities to articulate
cause-and-eect relationships and so frame issues for collective debate and export their policy pro-
jects globally. Despite the framework being two decades old, there are still relatively few studies
which explicitly test or develop the concept theoretically, thus making it dicult to assess what we
have collectively and cumulatively learned about this topic. This chapter attempts to systematize
key developments in the literature. The rst section outlines the concept locating it in the politics
of ideas literature. The second explores the state of the art in the empirical studies deploying the
epistemic communities framework. The third section considers the theoretical challenges that
researchers face when attempting to study epistemic communities. Discussion here proposes ve
possible causal pathways through which we can explain how epistemic communities help decision-
makers learn. The chapter closes with a brief sketch of potential future research frontiers for
scholars interested in the power of knowledge and epistemic communities in public policy.
Epistemic communities and the politics of ideas
Epistemic communities are groups of professionals, often from a variety of dierent disciplines,
which produce policy-relevant knowledge about complex technical issues (Haas 1992a: 16). Such
communities embody a belief system around an issue which contains four knowledge elements:
(1) a shared set of normative and principled beliefs, which provide a value-based rationale
for the social action of community members; (2) shared causal beliefs, which are derived
from their analysis of practices leading or contributing to a central set of problems in their
domain and which then serve as the basis for elucidating the multiple linkages between possible
policy actions and desired outcomes; (3) shared notions of validity that is, intersubjective,
internally dened criteria for weighing and validating knowledge in the domain of their
229
expertise; and (4) a common policy enterprise that is, a set of common practices associated
with a set of problems to which their professional competence is directed, presumably out of
the conviction that human welfare will be enhanced as a consequence.
(1992a: 3)
The concept was the subject of an International Organization (IO) special edition in 1992 edited by
Haas. In this, the full framework was articulated (1992a) and empirically explored in environmental,
security, trade and international political economy cases studies. This volume still represents the
keystone of the epistemic communities literature. Emphasizing experts inuence over decision-
maker learning as a potentially central mechanism eecting policy development and change, the
epistemic communities framework aims to make sense of policy-making in conditions of
uncertainty and technical complexity. In these settings, decision-makers preferences will be less
clear to them transforming policy-making into an exercise in learning rather than bargaining.
As the main vehicles for authoritative consensual knowledge, epistemic communities have the
ability to help formulate policy in three main ways: elucidating cause-and-eect relationships
and providing advice on the likely results of various courses of action; shedding light on the
complex interlinkages between issues, and helping to dene the self-interest of states (Haas 1992a).
The value added of the approach is that it highlights the importance of actors that are able to
dene complex problems, particularly in the early policy design stages of the policy cycle where the
uncertainty of novel policy problems is at its peak. The framework is intended to complement
existing theories of policy-making that focus upon interests and the calculation of costs and
benets (rational choice), identities and socialization (constructivism), policy legacies (historical
institutionalism) and the use of words and discourse (poststructuralism) (1992a: 6). The core analy-
tical point here is that in the absence of epistemic communities to frame complex issues and proer
new ideas, policy-making would follow more conventional, unreective paths (Haas 2011).
The advent of the epistemic communities framework should be seen as part of the wider
renaissance of knowledge (Radaelli 1995). In political science in the 1990s, scholars were
reminded that, along with the traditional interests and institutions, there was a third i . Ideas also
matter in explaining political decision-making. Although material power, identities and policy
legacies have not disappeared from analysis, this ideational turn emphasizes decision-makers as
sentient agents (Schmidt 2010). As such, they are sensitive to new ideas or new representations
of existing ones. The politics of ideas agenda has been followed enthusiastically and resulted in
empirical analysis that sheds light on how public policy emerges from new ways of thinking,
beliefs, rhetoric and discourse. The contribution of the epistemic communities framework is to
remind us that ideas would be sterile without carriers (Haas 1992a: 27). This is an anthro-
pomorphic conceptualization of knowledge (Radaelli 1997: 169) where those experts who
create the knowledge on which decision-makers depend are central to political analysis. Thus,
to identify an epistemic community is to identify a set of actors with the professional and social
stature to make authoritative claims on politically pertinent and socially relevant issues of the
day. Their success is dependent, not simply on their epistemic resources but also on their political
acumen. Epistemic communities must persuade decision-makers, and successfully navigate the
machinery of government by insinuating themselves into bureaucratic positions, if their consensual
knowledge is to inform policy choices.
The empirical analysis of epistemic communities
The rst step in mapping the eld of epistemic communities scholarship involves exploring the
empirical analysis deploying the term. Bibliographic analysis provides the broad canvas on which
Dunlop
230
we can sketch out some of the signicant details. Using a citation search, we identied some
638 articles, book chapters and books citing Haass 1992 introductory article to the IO special
edition.
1
Results conrm that the idea of epistemic communities is rmly embedded in the social
sciences lexicon; in the past two decades, the concept has travelled across a wide range of dis-
ciplines 54 in fact (see Figure 18.1
2
). Such wide appeal ts with the frameworks aim to explain
the role of experts in the technically complex policy problems which dominate the policy
process in contemporary society. As we would expect Government and Law, Public Adminis-
tration and International Relations (IR) lead the way in citations, though interestingly IR lags a
little way behind the rst two political science sub-elds (see Figure 18.2).
Despite epistemic communities obvious resonance across social scientic disciplines, a review
of the literature reveals supercial engagement. Specically, the actual identication of epistemic
communities using the fourfold belief system that denes them remains rare. Rather, the term is
more frequently used metaphorically to describe any group of experts giving policy advice. A
succinct explanation for this state of aairs is oered by Wright: [A]ctually identifying these
communities can be a dicult process (1997: 11). Practical obstacles, such as identifying,
locating and gaining access to those believed to be members of an epistemic community, may
frustrate attempts to engage with the approach as an analytical tool.
Identication of an epistemic communitys belief system presents a further empirical challenge.
In most cases, authors delineate beliefs using the qualitative soaking and poking (Fenno 1986)
Figure 18.1 Bibliographic analysis of 638 articles, book chapters and books citing Haass 1992
introductory article to the IO special edition
Source: Author
Epistemic communities
231
strategies advocated by Haas. This is especially appropriate when attempting to uncover what
can be sensitive information particularly experts normative and policy beliefs about an issue.
However, in addition to analysing scientic documents and conference proceedings, and conducting
interviews, some scholars have used quantitative surveys (Radaelli and OConnor 2009; Wright
1997) to gather this kind of information. Criticisms have, however, been voiced about the neglect
of how epistemic communities beliefs about an issue are mediated by experts own deeper socio-
political beliefs and psychological motivations (Finlayson 2004; Zelikow, 1994). This question
of social conditioning is explored by Mitchell et al. (2007) in relation to nuclear scientists in the
United States (US) and European Union (EU) member states. Using survey data, they conclude that
values (expressed on the traditional left-right spectrum) and national context matter for epistemic
communities policy preferences.
The challenges of using epistemic communities as an analytical framework are not only prac-
tical. Getting to grips with the structure and power dynamics that may exist within an epistemic
community is important if we are to understand belief system formation and message framing.
For example, in their study of an epistemic community of legal scholars, van Waarden and Drahos
(2002) uncover a hierarchical structure where some actors are more equal than others: it mat-
ters not only what some member says, but who says it (2002: 930). In a related vein, Drake and
Nicolaïdiss (1992) and Dunlops (2009) case studies illustrate the impact that a division of labour
between disciplines within these groups can have on belief system formation and communication.
Yet, in the politics literature, these examples are the exception rather than the rule. In most
Figure 18.2 Bibliographic analysis of 638 articles, book chapters and books citing Haass 1992
introductory article to the IO special edition (subject areas receiving 11 citations or more)
Source: Author
Dunlop
232
cases, where scholars do map out the beliefs which epistemic communities embody, the com-
munity itself is rarely the centre of analytical attention usually losing out to interest groups and
institutions. Disciplinary preferences provide a plausible explanation for this. Political scientists
attention is naturally drawn toward political institutions rather than the world of professionals
and experts. Here, the increasing attention being paid by sociologists, well-schooled in the
power of professions (Abbott 1988), will be valuable to the epistemic communities approach.
3
For
example, Roths (2008a, 2008b) analysis of epistemic communities of embryologists and zebra-
sh experts, respectively, forms the basis for a discussion on the internal structure and politics of
these communities. Lorenz-Meyers (2010) recent work on the membership congurations
within communities, and experience of actually being a member, is similarly promising. By
exploring the internal workings of epistemic communities, analysts can uncover how experts
expand their political power and ability to inuence.
The epistemic communities framework was originally developed to explain the role of transna-
tional experts in fostering international policy coordination something reected in the pro-
nounced number of studies focussing on the EU (for example, Kaelberer 2003; van Waarden and
Drahos 2002; Zito 2001).
4
The bibliographic review also reveals, however, that these communities
are not restricted to inter-, trans- or supranational levels. Epistemic communities can be located
at any level of government. Indeed, they are commonly national entities, and policy transfer
concepts (see Chapter 17 of this volume) have usefully been deployed to explore what happens
to ideas as they move from an epistemic community in one jurisdiction to another (Albert and
Laberge 2007; Prince 2010; Melo 2004). Studies have also highlighted the more antagonistic
relationship that can develop between epistemic communities in dierent places. In her studies of
hormone growth promoters and the biotech milk yield enhancer bovine somatotrophin (rbST),
Dunlop illustrates how epistemic communities in the EU and US, oering contrasting interpreta-
tions of the same scientic evidence, were used to justify international policy divergence (2007,
2009, 2010). Harrisons cross-national study of dioxins in pulp mill euents and paper products
reports a similar role for experts in cross-national policy divergence (2002). This underlines the
fact that the concepts analytical leverage is founded on the potentially powerful role experts and
knowledge can play in overcoming collective action dilemmas in uncertain contexts regardless of
jurisdiction and government level. Empirical studies have also successfully applied epistemic
communities to more local settings for example exploring interagency cooperation in California
(Thomas 1997); forest policy change in British Columbia (Kamieniecki 2000); medical ethics in
the Czech Republic (Simek et al. 2010) and transport policy in Belgium (Albrechts, 2001).
The empirical literature also highlights research design issues associated with locating epistemic
communities in dynamic policy environments. Two main challenges are evident: how to explore
epistemic communities interactions with other actors in policy arenas, and designing research
that is able to capture the temporal dimension of epistemic communities inuence.
To understand how epistemic communities interact with other policy actors, we rst need some
background on what distinguishes epistemic communities from others in the policy process.
Their blend of beliefs and highly specialized expertise distinguish epistemic communities from
interest groups and policy networks (Haas 1992a: 22). This enables them to make legitimate claims
to being the main producers of knowledge in an issue area (Dunlop 2009). This specication of
dierence does not imply that Haas attempts to advance epistemic communities as morally
superior to other actors in the policy process (see the debate between Toke 1999 and Dunlop
2000). Rather, the aim is to record the view that expert groups main interactions are expected
to be with decision-makers and that they are not a brand of specialized interest groups with
non-material aims (Haas 1992a: 19). For Haas, the crucial claim to distinctiveness rests on ele-
ments (2) and (3) of their belief system which result in consensual knowledge. Haas consistently
Epistemic communities
233
implies the non-negotiable nature of these two elements without them, the epistemic commu-
nity ceases to function as an authoritative voice of advice. Accordingly, in the event of a serious
challenge to the causal world view of the community (2) which could not be settled internally
(3), the community would withhold policy advice: Unlike an interest group, if confronted
with anomalous data, they would retract their advice or suspend judgement (Haas 1990: 55).
But what of the real world of politics where constellations of political actors interact, argue
and bargain? Being apolitical (yet politically empowered) seems unfeasible. The emphasis on
consensual knowledge may overstate the inuence these expert enclaves alone can have. Interest
groups and rival scientic groups interact with epistemic communities learning from and arguing
with them. The need to explore epistemic communities propensity to build alliances was a
theme taken up by James Sebenius in the 1992 IO special edition. Using insights from nego-
tiation analysis, Sebenius argues that an epistemic communitysinuence may emanate from
bargaining with other actors in an attempt to convert their natural coalition of believers into a
winning coalition, pushing forward a shared policy enterprise (characteristic (4) of an epistemic
community) (Sebenius 1992: 325). Therefore, epistemic communities have to be politically proac-
tive players to convey their message, interacting with a multiplicity of other actors where it is to
be expected that inuence is variable and contingent as wider strategic games are played out. In
such a scenario, the full potential of consensual knowledge may only be realized through the
involvement of other, more politically astute, groups.
In the literature, this interaction is often captured by subsuming epistemic communities within
interest-based approaches. Most commonly, empirical studies which explore alliances between
epistemic communities and interest groups use the advocacy coalition framework (for example,
Dudley and Richardson 1996; Elliott and Schlaepfer 2001; Meijerink 2005). However, with the
interest-based approaches doing the analytical work, epistemic communities conceptual devel-
opment is stunted. Alliances with interest groups raise key issues that are still to be addressed. What
happens to the epistemic community itself as alliances stabilize? What aspect(s) of an epistemic
communitys belief system are most vulnerable to change, if any? Unlike Sabatiers advocacy
coalition framework approach, the epistemic communities framework does not explicitly explore
the weight of the beliefs relative to one another. Exploring the susceptibility of a belief system
to change would tell analysts a good deal about a communitys propensity towards coalition
building in a given policy area. Exploring the extent to which one element could dominate
another, and how this is inuenced by the membership of a community, could also help build
bridges with the emerging research on interest groups. For example, by delineating the relative
importance of normative and policy-oriented beliefs, synergies may be possible between epistemic
communities and advocacy networks (Keck and Sikkink 1998) and epistemic communities and
Communities of Practice (Wenger 1999).
While we have empirical studies of cooperation, there is little evidence that epistemic com-
munities are willing to engage in conict with interest groups. Rather, conict appears reserved
for other expert groups. For example, the epistemic battles between rival groups of experts,
anticipated by Haas (1990: 57, 1992b: 44), has been explored empirically by Youde (2007). In
his study of health policy in South Africa, Youde identies the emergence of both an epistemic
community and a counter-epistemic community oering fundamentally dierent understandings
of AIDS and radically dierent policy prescriptions.
This intervention is extremely valuable. In the two decades since the epistemic communities
concept was rst
introduced, communication technology has changed beyond all recognition
with the advent
of the Internet. Simultaneously, the technical policy dilemmas that decision-
makers encounter have increased in quantity and complexity most notably climate change.
The democratization of information (if not knowledge) and increased urgency of complex
Dunlop
234
policy-making has resulted in a huge expansion in the number and types of groups that classify
themselves as experts. These trends are reected in the increased willingness of scholars to talk
in terms of multiple epistemic communities (Stephens et al. 2011) that engage in contests of
credibility (Epstein 1996: 3). The prescience of the approach is also reected by the empirical
cases studies. The framework has been used to explore policy problems as diverse as agricultural
policy (for example, Coleman and Skogstad 1995); nancial policy (Rethel 2010); economics and
banking (for example, Ikenberry 1992); forestry (Shankland and Hasenclever 2011); defence and
security (Howorth 2004); health policy (for example, Ogden et al. 2003), and transport (for
example, Schot and Schipper 2011). Reecting the approachs empirical roots, environmental
case studies are by far the most common something which is set to continue (for example,
Haas 1990, 1992b; Peterson 1992). Nine of the 118 articles citing Haass 1992a introduction in
2010 and 2011 were directly related to climate change and sustainable development (for
example, Lovell and MacKenzie 2011).
While epistemic communities are discrete actors, they are located in dynamic policy envir-
onments. This dynamism requires not only that research is designed in ways which illuminate
how epistemic communities relate to other policy actors; we must also attend to the temporal
dimension of policy-making. A focus on the here and now of policy-making means that
analysis may miss epistemic communities inuence. There are three reasons for taking the long
view; the rst concerns the internal operation of an epistemic community. While we might expect
experts inuence to be biased towards the early stages of the policy process, the back story of
how a group of experts came together, and the process of knowledge creation, still matters.
Scientic consensus takes time to construct; knowledge is often incomplete and judgements of
cause and eect partial. If we focus only on what has occurred when the consensus has been
reached and the community has entered the political arena, we may miss earlier episodes of
political behaviour where the expert enclave has, for example, rened its position in order to
gain access to decision-makers (Dunlop 2007).
In the same vein, empirical studies are required to illuminate what happens to epistemic com-
munities over time, as they interact with decision-makers and other actors in the policy process.
This issue of time is again something which Haas acknowledges in pointing out that the
knowledge consensus represents a temporally bounded notion of truth (1992a: 23, emphasis added).
Over time, this particular truth will evolve, be challenged and altered, or debunked and replaced,
as new discoveries dictate. We need to empirically explore what happens to these communities
during this evolutionary process. Of specic interest is the impact that political exposure has on
an epistemic communitys belief system. Adler and Haas state that: [A]s epistemic communities
consolidate and expand their political and bureaucratic inuence internationally, additional ideas
may be incorporated into the core community beliefs (1992a: 374). Successful examination of
the stability and strength of the dierent elements of an epistemic communitys belief system
requires that the four elements characteristics are problematized clearly in empirical studies and
their importance relative to each other elucidated (Dunlop 2000).
A
second reason for
analysing epistemic communities over time concerns when epistemic
communities are located in the policy cycle. It is well established that experts are active in the
early agenda-setting and issue framing stages of policy-making and less visible as decisions are
being set and policy implemented. However, if we only front-load our attention to these early
stages, analysis may miss a reappearance or reincarnation of an epistemic community in the
policy evaluation and feedback stages.
Finally, the causal mechanism associated with the approach also requires that we take the
long view. Learning processes have their own temporal dimension with policy-oriented
learning and enlightenment happening over protracted periods of time (Sabatier 1988; Weiss
Epistemic communities
235
1979). And so, we must look at the moving picture rather than the snapshot (Pierson 1996).
Long after an epistemic community has left the political arena, its ideas may be inuencing
policy-making.
Theoretical challenges
While the epistemic communities framework is empirically well travelled, the analytical hor-
izons of the approach have not been broadened to the same extent. Despite being the con-
ceptual name to drop in studies of technical issues in political science and beyond, very little
work has been done to interrogate and develop the concept theoretically. The tendency in the
discipline to commit substantial time and resources to rening and reforming such conceptual
frameworks for example the last three decades renement of policy networks (for example
Thatcher 1998; see Chapter 12 of this volume) and the advocacy coalition framework (most
recently Weible et al. 2011; see Chapter 10 of this volume) has not been repeated in the case
of epistemic communities. Given the empirical, practical and disciplinary barriers outlined already,
such underdevelopment is perhaps unsurprising. This is not to say that the analytical challenges
associated with the approach are unknown, however. On the contrary, many of the articles
citing Haass work oer conceptual criticisms. But these are made in passing and have not been
related back to the framework itself. This section outlines some of the analytical gauntlets that
have been thrown down and proposes ways that these might be picked up by future scholars
focused on explanatory analysis of epistemic communities.
To understand how epistemic communities inuence decision-makers learning we must rst
clarify our dependent variable. Asking what is actually being explained in epistemic community
analysis is perhaps not as self-evident a question as it may seem. In his case studies, Haas uncovers
epistemic communities as the catalysts for international policy coordination (1990, 1992a). This
policy outcome should not however be the standard against which an epistemic communitys
inuence is judged. These cases show the maximum inuence experts can have; they are extreme
examples. If we look only for international policy coordination, the results are liable to disappoint.
Epistemic communities are rarely live actors at the decision-making or implementation stages
of the policy cycle. So, we must lower our expectations and give epistemic communities their
proper analytical place. What we are interested in is how epistemic communities help decision-
makers learn. Policy outputs should not be the primary focus as epistemic communities inuence
over those will usually be indirect.
So, what do decision-makers learn from epistemic communities? In his exposition of the epis-
temic communities framework, Haas provides a clear denition of learning. Learning is a pro-
cess of informing decision-makers beliefs about the four key components of complex technical
issues embodied by epistemic communities with particular attention drawn to epistemic com-
munities inuence on the substantive nature of policy arrangements and their more overtly
political role as the nonsystemic origins of state interests (1992a: 4). Experts potential to stimulate
learning is assured by the control they enjoy over the production of knowledge relating to an
issue (ibid.: 2) and the inuence they exert is a function of decision-makers uncertainty.
Despite this clarity and specicity, we still know relatively little about the possible forms of
learning that may arise between epistemic communities and decision-makers. The framework
emphasizes a form of learning that depicts control over knowledge as something which epis-
temic communities have and decision-makers, whose bounded rationality initiates their call for
advice, do not have (1992a: 1416). This denition of uncertainty is problematic, however.
Epistemic communities entry into the policy arena is a function of decision-makers technical
uncertainty, however by conating
this uncertainty with comprehensively bounded rationality
Dunlop
236
we are left with a single learning category where decision-makers experience extreme epistemic
deciencies which need to be lled. And so, despite disaggregating belief systems into individual
components in the denition of what an epistemic community actually is, the epistemic resources
experts pass on to decision-makers are portrayed as a unied good.
This decit model of learning (Dunlop 2009), where epistemic communities are required to
ll gaps in decision-makers knowledge, reects the empirical case which informed the original
development of the epistemic communities approach. Haass major study Saving the Mediterranean
(1990) illustrates the extreme level of inuence that epistemic communities can have. In this
case, the epistemic community had the power to make decision-makers cooperate and develop
policies in ways they would not otherwise have. Such ideal typical cases yield important
examples of what is possible, however they also highlight extreme phenomena. If it is to explain
the role of epistemic communities in who learns what, when, to whose benet and why (Adler
and Haas 1992: 370), the analytical framework must be able to account for the variety of these
actors learning interactions. While epistemic communities central role in information production
gives them the authoritative status to occupy this role, we cannot assume that they will be able
to exert control over every aspect of what is known about an issue or that the control they do
enjoy will be uniform across time and space. To understand the dierent roles epistemic com-
munities occupy in the policy process, we must have a clear, coherent and systematic way of
describing variation in this explanandum.
One promising way of characterizing the learning that epistemic communities can eect is to
focus upon the ways in which decision-makers preferences mediate the learning processes in
which they engage. This is something that Haas himself acknowledges, describing a scenario
where decision-makers rely on epistemic communities for only certain aspects of policy knowl-
edge (1992a: 15). Where decision-makers preferences are unclear or controversial, uncertainty
is generated and gaps appear into which epistemic communities can insinuate themselves. Learning
may also be dierentiated across time and space as well as knowledge components; epistemic
communities can be called in to provide one type of input and nd that the scope and intensity of
their inuence may increase, decrease or change in emphasis (ibid.: 16).
In recent research, a typology has been developed to capture the variety of ways in which
decision-makers actually learn from epistemic communities (Dunlop 2009). Using a exible de-
nition of uncertainty for example, Dunlop (ibid.) suggests that variety is best captured by dif-
ferentiating between the control enjoyed by decision-makers and epistemic communities over
the production of substantive knowledge or means that informs policy on the one hand and
the policy objectives or ends to which that knowledge is directed on the other. The four
components identied by Haas can be reclassied
quite simply into
the foci of means and ends
with shared normative beliefs (component 1) cause and eect postulates (component 2) and
intersubjective understandings of validity (component 3) making up the substantive means pro-
duced around an issue and the most overtly political component of epistemic communities the
common policy enterprise (component 4) equating to the end objectives. The implications of
this distinction for the types of epistemic community-decision-maker learning exchanges that may
prevail are elaborated using a typology of adult learning from the education literature which
delineates the four possible learning situations (see Dunlop 2009 for an exposition of the typology).
Dunlops empirical exploration of the typology provides grounds for optimism suggesting that
each of the types are readily distinguishable from one another and provide a parsimonious account
of learning exchanges and basis for ordering empirical ndings across cases and comparison within
them. Of course, further empirical assurances are required that the typology does not contain self-
contradictory ideas. Suce it to say that research needs to unpack the nature of uncertainty and
what it is in epistemic terms that decision-makers are open to learning from epistemic communities.
Epistemic communities
237
With regard to the independent variable, we can break down the explanatory challenges posed
by epistemic communities. Following Coleman (1986), explanation of epistemic communities
inuence in the policy process consists of unpacking three elements in turn: (a) the microfounda-
tions of the macro-level independent variable (i.e. epistemic communities and the learning they
eect); (b) the micro-micro causal logics that characterize the learning interactions between
epistemic communities and decision-makers (and other policy actors), and (c) the mechanisms that
turn learning at the micro level into macro outputs of the dependent variable (i.e. learning in
government and, ultimately, policy outputs). Against Colemans bathtub ideal of rigorous research,
the epistemic communities literature reveals the various conceptual challenges to be met.
a. Microfoundations of epistemic communities and learning: To uncover the microfoundations of
epistemic communities inuence in the policy process, we must focus on the conditions of
their emergence. Empirical studies reveal at least two distinct epistemic community types
each distinguished by the extent to which decision-makers exert control over their existence
(Dunlop, 2010). Epistemic communities were originally conceived as evolutionary entities;
self-regulating enclaves of experts that existed out there in the academic and research world
that entered the political arena by responding to decision-makers call for advice (Haas 1989,
1992a). In such ideal typical scenarios, decision-makers uncertainty is such that epistemic
communities are able to oer both substantive policy advice (means) and policy proposals (ends).
However, another type of expert enclave is apparent in the literature. Some epistemic
communities are what can be described as governmental’–where members have been
deliberately selected by decision-makers to justify a predetermined policy decision (Dunlop
2010) or depoliticize an emotive issue (Peterson 2001). For example, in Ikenberrys study of
Anglo-American post-war economic settlement (1992), an epistemic community was assembled
by decision-makers to provide technical and normative guidance to facilitate a move away
from policies based on unregulated free trade. A similar instance of decision-makers deli-
miting the policy ends is provided by Verdun in her study of the Delors Committee that was
appointed to provide the substantive epistemic means to supranational elites aiming to deli-
ver the policy end of Economic and Monetary Union (EMU) in the EU (1999). It is only
by identifying epistemic communities microfoundations, that the scope of decision-makers
epistemic needs, and the likely range of epistemic communities inuence, can be discerned.
b. Explaining learning interactions between epistemic communities and policy elites: On the micro-micro
interactions between epistemic communities and decision-makers, the causal mechanism
associated with the framework is obviously learning. However, learning as an explanation
takes many forms. Indeed, a closer look at the epistemic communities literature suggests that
learning is a master mechanism (see Hedström and Swedberg 1998 for a deeper discussion
of causal mechanisms) which can be unpacked into a variety of specic causal logics. The
ve causal pathways with most analytical potential are suggested and discussed in turn.
i Learning as instrumental: Haass epistemic communities framework, as it stands, implies two
causal rationales. The rst of these treats decision-maker learning as underpinned by the
Lasswellian desire to make better public policy.
Here, interactions between epistemic
commu
nities and decision-makers are guided by a functional logic where beliefs are updated
in a Bayesian manner (Radaelli 2009). Epistemic communities supply the policy-relevant
information required by decision-makers to update their beliefs. Public policy, in this view,
is a matter of trial-and-error and experts role is more overtly technical than political.
ii Learning as persuasion and socialization: Haas also emphasizes that the framework is under-
pinned by limited constructivism (1992a: 23) stressing the importance of persuasion
and reection in the redenition of decision-makers interests and identities (Checkel
Dunlop
238
2001; Jacobson 2000: 1601). In Haass Mediterranean study (1990) for example, the
epistemic community which grew from the United Nations Environment Programme
(UNEP) persuaded decision-makers across nations to internalize a new set of environmental
standards and common understanding of the problem. The international diusion of
new environmental norms resulted in eective policy coordination.
iii Learning as calculation: Moving beyond the causal logics originally envisaged for epistemic
communities, more overtly political learning styles may exist where interaction is underpinned
by a logic of consequence and behaviour a function of calculation. In such interest-driven
accounts, epistemic communities and decision-makers act in ways that maximize their utility
where their engagement in a learning relationship is a product of the sanctions and rewards
they perceive such behaviour will bring. The benet of this logic is that it enables a move
away from simply treating learning as something which is value driven, or based on tech-
nical rationale. Rather, decision-makers can control a policy domain or gain political advan-
tage by using and, perhaps sourcing, specialist knowledge in a strategic manner (Chwieroth
2007; Dunlop and James 2007; Kohler-Koch 2000; Niemann 1998). For example, principal-
agent modelling has been used to explore the role of epistemic communities is delivering
pre-determined policy choices in an ecient and credible manner (Dunlop 2010). We
should be clear, it is not simply decision-makers that can be treated as rational actors.
Epistemic communities belief systems suggest that while they do not have direct pecuniary
incentives, they are still interested parties. Because of their socio-political beliefs these are
experts who want rather than need to be in the policy arena. They are self-selecting policy
actors driven by normative and policy beliefs. Moreover, as creators of knowledge, they
are essentially residual claimants (Alchian and Demsetz 1972); long-term shareholders
in a product who may compete with other claim makers to control an epistemic eld.
iv Learning as legitimacy: The sociologies of science, knowledge and professions have obvious,
but rarely used, insights for epistemic communities. Specically, the logic of practice
thesis (Bourdieu 1990) can be used to illuminate the interaction between experts and
decision-makers as a game where action is informed by the cultural dispositions of the
two sets of actors involved. In relation to advisory games, epistemic communities as
symbols of authority and legitimacy has been criticized in the Science and Technology
Studies (STS) literature (Jasano 1996; Lidskog and Sundqvist 2002; Walker 2001) and
this eld oers important analytical resources for the framework. Epistemic communities
practices as authority claiming actors can be explored using Gieryns (1983) notions of
boundary work. In contrast to the logic of appropriateness, epistemic communities in
this view draw a rm line, a boundary, between themselves and the decision-makers they
advise. By emphasizing the dierences in their professional identities, epistemic com-
munities monopolize epistemic resources and aim to impose their view of the world by
dint of their epistemic authority. Decision-maker learning in this scenario is not about
uncovering what works, but rather is symbolic and legitimacy seeking.
v Learning as unreective: The idea of learning as unreective is more than a little contra-
dictory. But, we can imagine scenarios where learning from an epistemic community is
an automatic response from decision-makers. Following Hopfs thesis on the logic of
habit in international relations (2010), habitual behaviour ourishes in environments
where uncertainty is absent. Where an epistemic community has become institutiona-
lized, and has successfully attenuated uncertainty and advisors trustworthiness is assured
(ibid.: 16), decision-makers may be content to unquestioningly adopt its ideas thereafter.
The proposition that epistemic communities interpretations
could be adopted
whole-
sale through routinized behaviour of decision-makers is perhaps not as controversial as it
Epistemic communities
239
may at rst appear. Epistemic communities that have been institutionalized in bureaucracies
may command considerable resources institutional as well as epistemic (Finnemore
1993). This is especially plausible in technically complex policy domains where the
political stakes are relatively low or remain hidden.
Of course, if considered in isolation, each of these conceptual lenses may obscure as much
as they reveal. Certainly, mono-causal explanation will not take analysts very far in the
complex world of policy learning. Rather, these logics are better used in combination. For
example, in her study on hormone growth promoters, Dunlop (2010) found that explana-
tions emphasizing a calculative logic were important at the start of the relationship between
European Commission ocials and their epistemic community but gave way to learning
underpinned by socialization further down the line.
vi Relating the micro world of learning to the macro world of policy outputs: Finally, research must relate
the micro world of epistemic community-decision-makers interactions to the macro-level
world of government learning and policy outputs. The challenges posed by such aggrega-
tion are considerable. Analysts must capture how decision-maker learning becomes trans-
formed into learning at a systemic level. They must also pinpoint the source of those
lessons as being the epistemic community. Methodological choices may hold the key here.
The painstaking qualitative process-tracing originally advocated by Haas (1992a) remains
the most suitable method to uncover whether socially accepted ideas can actually be traced
back to a group of experts. Counterfactual analysis, also suggested by Haas, is a valuable yet
underused tool which can help to construct a rigorous account of learning that would not
have occurred in the absence of an expert enclave creating new policy relevant ideas.
Conclusions and future research agenda
The epistemic communities approach speaks directly to the complex challenges faced by decision-
makers in uncertain policy environments. Accordingly, the approach has proved valuable in
explaining the role of experts in a variety of political settings and has remarkable disciplinary
reach beyond its roots in IR. Yet arguably, we are still some way o the reective research
program envisaged two decades ago (Adler and Haas 1992).
Empirical research on epistemic communities has ensured that the term is now part of the
social science lexicon. To deepen our understanding, research is required that explores how epis-
temic communities emerge in the rst place and what happens to them as they interact with
decision-makers and other policy actors over time. Moving from exploratory to explanatory mode,
future research interrogating the causal mechanism of learning would be welcome. In particular,
following major analytical themes which have emerged in political science in the past few years,
the role of professional practice and habit in how decision-makers learn from epistemic communities
would represent important additions to the research agenda. Finally, with regard to methodol-
ogy, again epistemic communities should take inspiration from where analytical energies are being
deployed in the social sciences. Specically, it would be useful for scholars to invest research
time in two areas: the role of temporal variables in epistemic communities inuence and the
transformation of learning at the micro level to learning at the systemic level.
Acknowledgements
Claire A. Dunlop gratefully acknowledges the support of the Economic and Social Research Council
(grant R00429034387) and European Research Council, grant on Analysis of Learning in Regulatory
Governance, ALREG, available at: http://centres.exeter.ac.uk/ceg/research/ALREG/index.php.
Dunlop
240
Notes
1 The citation search involved two steps. The rst was to perform a citation search using the ISI social
sciences database this yielded 583 articles. The second was a manual search for works not cited in the
ISIa further 55 articles, books and book chapters citing Haas (1992a) were uncovered at this stage.
2 The ego-network analysis of the citation data presented in Figures 18.1 and 18.2 were conducted using
UCINET network analysis software (Borgatti et al. 1999).
3 There have been 45 research articles citing Haass 1992 IO introduction in journals classied under
Sociology by the Web of Science. Just over half of these have been published since 2006 (Web of
Science citation search 22 July 2011). Perhaps surprisingly, only 17 of these are published in journals
which identify as including Science and Technology Studies (STS).
4 It is instructive to note that the leading journal publishing work citing epistemic communities is the
Journal of European Public Policy (which recorded 40 of the 583 articles listed in the ISI).
Bibliography
Abbott, A. 1998. The System of Professions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Adler, E. and P.M. Haas. 1992. Conclusion: Epistemic communities, world order and the creation of a
reective research program, International Organisation 46(1): 36790.
Albert, M. and S. Laberge. 2007. The legitimation and dissemination processes of the innovation system
approach: The case of the Canadian and Quebec science and technology policy, Science Technology and
Human Values 32(2): 22149.
Albrechts, L. 2001. How to proceed from image and discourse to action: As applied to the Flemish diamond,
Urban Studies 38(4): 73345.
Alchian, A.A. and H. Demsetz. 1972. Production, information costs and economic organization, American
Economic Review 62, 77795.
Borgatti, S.P., M.G. Everett and L.C. Freeman. 1999. UCINET 6.0 Version 1.00. Natick, MA: Analytic
Technologies.
Bourdieu, P. 1990. Logic of Practice. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Checkel, J. 2001. Why comply? Social learning and European identity change, International Organization
55(3): 55388.
Chwieroth, J. 2007. Neoliberal economists and capital account liberalization in emerging markets, International
Organization 61(2): 44363.
Coleman, J.S. 1986. Social theory, social research, and a theory of action, American Journal of Sociology 91:
130935.
——and G. Skogstad. 1995. Neo-liberalism, policy networks, and policy change: Agricultural policy
reform in Australia and Canada, Australian Journal of Political Science 30(2): 24263.
Drake, W.J. and K. Nicolaïdis. 1992. Ideas, interests and institutionalisation: Trade in services and the
Uruguay Round, International
Organization 46: 1, 37100.
Dudley,
G. and J.J. Richardson. 1996. Why does policy change over time? Adversarial policy communities,
alternative policy arenas and British trunk roads policy, 19451995, Journal of European Public Policy 3(1):
6383.
Dunlop, C.A. 2000. Epistemic communities: A reply to toke, Politics 20(3): 137 44.
—— 2007. Up and down the pecking order, what matters and when in issue denition: the case of rbST
in the EU, Journal of European Public Policy 14(1): 3958.
—— 2009. Policy transfer as learning: Capturing variation in what decisionmakers learn from epistemic
communities, Policy Studies 30(3): 291313.
——. 2010. Epistemic communities and two goals of delegation , Science and Public Policy 37(3): 20517.
——and O. James. 2007. Principal-agent modelling and learning: The European commission, experts and
agricultural hormone growth promoters , Public Policy and Administration 22(4): 40322.
Elliott, C. and R. Schlaepfer. 2001. Understanding forest certication using the advocacy coalition framework,
Forest Policy and Economics 2(34): 25766.
Epstein, S. 1996. Impure Science: AIDS, Activism, and the Politics of Knowledge. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Fenno, R.F. 1986. Observation, context, and sequence in the study of politics, American Political Science
Review 80(1): 315.
Finlayson, A. 2004. Political
science, political ideas
and rhetoric, Economy and Society 33(4): 52849.
Epistemic communities
241
Finnemore, M. 1993. International organizations as teachers of norms: The United-Nations Educational
Scientic and Cultural Organization and Science Policy , International Organization 47(4): 56597.
Gieryn, T.F. 1983. Boundary-work and the demarcation of science from non-science: Strains and interests
in professional ideologies of scientists, American Sociological Review 48(6): 78195.
Haas, P.M. 1989. Do regimes matter? Epistemic communities and Mediterranean pollution control,
International Organization 43(3): 377403.
—— 1990. Saving the Mediterranean The Politics of International Environmental Co-operation. New York:
Columbia University Press.
—— 1992a. Introduction: Epistemic communities and international policy co-ordination, International
Organization 46(1): 136.
—— 1992b. Obtaining international environmental protection through epistemic consensus, in I.H.
Rowlands and M. Greene (eds) Global Environmental Change and International Relations. Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
—— 2011. Epistemic communities,inIPSA Encyclopedia of Political Science, New York: Sage.
Harrison, K.A. 2002. Ideas and environmental standard-setting: A comparative study of regulation of the
pulp and paper industry, Governance 15(1): 6596.
Hedström, P. and R. Swedberg (eds). 1998. Social Mechanisms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hopf, T. 2010. The logic of habit in international relations, European Journal of International Relations
16(4): 53961.
Howorth, J. 2004. Discourse, ideas, and epistemic communities in European security and defence policy,
West European Politics 27(2): 21134.
Ikenberry, G.J. 1992. A world economy restored: Expert consensus and the Anglo-American postwar
settlement in International
Organization 46: 1, 289322.
Jacobson,
H.K. 2000. International institutions and system transformation, Annual Review of Political Science
3: 14966.
Jasano, S. 1996. Science and norms in global environmental regimes, in F. Hampson Osler and J. Reppy
(eds). Earthly Goods: Environmental Change and Social Justice. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Kaelberer, M. 2003. Knowledge, power and monetary bargaining: Central bankers and the creation of
monetary union in Europe, Journal of European Public Policy 10(3): 365 79.
Kamieniecki, S. 2000. Testing alternative theories of agenda setting: Forest policy change in British
Columbia, Canada, Policy Studies Journal 28(1): 17689.
Keck, M. and K. Sikkink. 1998. Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
Kohler-Koch, B. 2000. Framing; the bottleneck of constructing legitimate institutions , Journal of European
Public Policy 7(4): 51331.
Lidskog, R. and G. Sundqvist. 2002. The role of science in environmental regimes: The case of LRTAP,
European Journal of International Relations 8(1): 77101.
Litn, K.T. 1994. Ozone Discourses: Science and Politics in Global Environmental Cooperation. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Lorenz, D. 2010. Possibilities of enacting and researching epistemic communities, Sociological Research
Online 15(2).
Lorenz-Meyer, Dagmar. 2010. Possibilities of enacting and researching epistemic communities, Sociological
Research Online 15(2). Available at: http://www.socresonline.org.uk/15/2/13.html.
Lovell, H. and D. MacKenzie. 2011. Accounting for carbon: The role of accounting professional organisations
in governing climate change, Antipode 43(3): 70430.
Meijerink, S. 2005. Understanding
policy stability and
change. The interplay of advocacy coalitions and
epistemic communities, windows of opportunity, and Dutch coastal ooding policy 19452003, Journal
of European Public Policy 2(6): 106077.
Melo, M.A. 2004. Institutional choice and the diusion of policy paradigms: Brazil and the second wave
of pension reform, International Political Science Review 25(3): 32041.
Mitchell, N.J., H. Jenkins-Smith, K. Herron and G. Whitten. 2007. Elite beliefs, epistemic communities
and the Atlantic divide: Scientists nuclear policy preferences in the United States and European Union,
British Journal of Political Science 37: 75364.
Niemann, A. 1998. The PHARE programme and the concept of spillover: Neofunctionalism in the
making, Journal of European Public Policy 5(3): 42846.
Ogden, J., G. Walt and L. Lush. 2003. The politics of branding in policy transfer: The case of DOTS
for tuberculosis control, Social Science and Medicine 57(1): 17988.
Dunlop
242
Peterson, J. 2001. The choice for EU theorists: Establishing a common framework for analysis, European
Journal of Political Theory 39(3): 289318.
Peterson, M.J. 1992. Whalers, cetologists, environmentalists and the international management of whaling,
International Organization 46(1): 14786.
Pierson, P. 1996. The path to European integration: A historical institutionalist analysis, Comparative
Political Studies 29(2): 12363.
Prince, R. 2010. Globalizing the creative industries concept: Travelling policy and transnational policy
communities, Journal of Arts Management Law and Society 40(2): 11939.
Radaelli, C.M. 1995. The role of knowledge in the policy process, Journal of European Public Policy 2(2): 15983.
—— 1997. The Politics of Corporate Taxation in the EU: Knowledge and International Policy Agendas. London:
Routledge.
—— 2009. Measuring policy learning: Regulatory impact assessment in Europe , Journal of European Public
Policy 16(8): 114564.
—— and K. OConnor. 2009. How bureaucratic elites imagine Europe: Towards convergence of governance
beliefs?, Journal of European Public Policy 16(7): 97189.
Rethel, L. 2010. The new nancial development paradigm and Asian bond markets, New Political Economy
15(4): 493517.
Roth, C. 2008a. Epistemic networks: Formalizing distributed cognition, Sociologie Du Travail 50(3): 35371.
—— 2008b. Co-evolution of authors and concepts in epistemic networks the zebrash community,
Revue
Francaise de Sociologie 49(3).
Sabatier,
P.A. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy oriented
learning therein, Policy Sciences 21: 12968.
Schmidt, V.A. 2010. Taking ideas and discourse seriously: Explaining change through discourse institutionalism
as the fourth new institutionalism”’, European Political Science Review 2(1): 125.
Schot, J. and F. Schipper. 2011. Experts and European transport integration, 19451958, Journal of European
Public Policy 18(2): 27493.
Sebenius, J.K. 1992. Challenging conventional explanations of international co-operation: Negotiation
analysis and the case of epistemic communities in International Organisation 46(1): 32365.
Shankland, A. and L. Hasenclever. 2011. Indigenous peoples and the regulation of REDD plus in Brazil:
Beyond the war of the worlds?, International Development Bulletin 42(3): 808.
Simek, J., L. Zamykalova and M. Mesanyova. 2010. Ethics committee or community? Examining the
identity of Czech ethics committees in the period of transition, Journal of Medical Ethics 36(9): 54852.
Stephens, J.C., A. Hansson, Y. Liu, H. de Coninck and S. Vajjhala. 2011. Characterizing the international
carbon capture and storage community, Global Environmental Change-Human and Policy Dimensions 21(2):
37990.
Thatcher, M. 1998. The development of policy network analyses, Journal of Theoretical Politics 10(4): 389416.
Thomas, C.W. 1997. Public management as interagency co-operation: Testing the epistemic community
theory at the domestic level, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 7(2): 22146.
Toke,
D. 1999. Epistemic communities
and environmental group,inPolitics 19(2): 97102.
van Waarden, F. and M. Drahos. 2002. Courts and (epistemic) communities in the convergence of
competition policies, Journal of European Public Policy 9(6): 91334.
Verdun, A. 1999. The role of the Delors Committee and EMU, Journal of European Public Policy 6(2): 30829.
Walker, K.J. 2001. Uncertainty, epistemic communities and public policy, in J. Handmer, T. Norton and
S. Dovers. (eds) Ecology, Uncertainty and Policy. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Weible, C.M., P.A. Sabatier, H.C. Jenkins-Smith, D. Nohrstedt, A.D. Henry and P. deLeon. 2011. A
quarter century of the advocacy coalition framework, Policy Studies Journal 39(3): 34960.
Weiss, C. 1979. The many meanings of research utilization, Public Administration 39: 42631.
Wenger, E. 1999. Communities of Practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wright, K. 1997. Knowledge and expertise in European conventional arms control negotiations: an
epistemic community?, The European Policy Process Occasional Papers, No. 41 Department of Government,
University of Essex.
Youde, J. 2007. AIDS, South Africa and the Politics of Knowledge. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Zelikow, P. 1994. Foreign policy engineering: From theory to practice and back again, International
Security 18(4): 14371.
Zito, A.R. 2001. Epistemic communities, European Union governance and the public voice, Science and
Public Policy 28(6): 46576.
Epistemic communities
243
19
Policy appraisal
John Turnpenny, Camilla Adelle and Andrew Jorda n
Introduction
For anyone interested in the role of knowledge in policy-making, these are fascinating times.
Terms like policy analysis, policy formulation, impact assessment and policy appraisal are fre-
quently used, and not just by academics: the media, government, non-governmental organisations,
interest groups and research funders are all visibly concerned with how evidence is collected,
marshalled, communicated, digested and used. One might be forgiven for using such terms inter-
changeably, or at least rather loosely, but they are quite distinct, and distinctive. This chapter is
specically about the role of policy appraisal in knowledge collection, review and utilisation
processes.
There are several important reasons why policy appraisal should interest public policy scho-
lars. First, it belongs to a family of other, perhaps, more familiar concepts. We argue policy
appraisal is a very specic type of policy analysis, a term which covers the use of analytical methods
formal or informal in any part of policy-making from agenda-setting to implementation.
So-called ex ante policy appraisal the focus of this chapter specically relates to policy for-
mulation: how policy options are formulated within government (Howlett 2011: 18). While
part of the process of formulation involves a choice among instruments for implementing policy
objectives, like regulation, taxes and voluntary agreements (Bardach 2005; Howlett and Ramesh
2003), the process of formulation itself involves activities such as appraising knowledge or evi-
dence, engaging in dialogue about the nature of policy problems and solutions, and identifying
and assessing the impacts of dierent policy options (Howlett 2011).
Second, policy appraisal is a symptom of broader changes in policy-making which began in
the latter part of the twentieth century. Many jurisdictions have since embarked on reform
programmes intended to better structure and manage their regulatory processes (Allio 2007).
This interest in Better Regulation was ignited in part by the need to cope with the increased
competition created by more globalised markets, as well as the international diusion of the
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Developments (OECD) core principles of regulatory
reform (ibid.). Radaelli (2007: 191) describes Better Regulation as a type of meta-governance
because of its emphasis on standards and rules which, instead of governing specic sectors or
economic actors, steer the process of rule formulation, adoption, enforcement, and evaluation.
244
As we will see below, policy appraisal has become an important enabler of Better Regulation
among other things, spreading rapidly throughout the OECD and beyond.
Third, having now secured this role, appraisal processes have themselves become important
new sites of political behaviour (Turnpenny et al. 2009). Thus, investigating how policy appraisal
systems are structured and operate in practice provides another way to study governance via its
policy instruments (see Hood 2007 and Lascoumes and Le Galès 2007 among others). While
the idea of policy appraisal owes a theoretical debt to the founding fathers of policy analysis
(e.g. Lasswell 1947; Simon 1976), paradoxically, contemporary policy analysts have been slow
to explore appraisals policy and political consequences. Appraisals are contested sources of
legitimacy, accountability and normative justication for public action. Accordingly, they inform
us of the theoretical presuppositions and legitimacy standards embedded in public policy (Lascoumes
and Le Galès 2007). Investigating the use of appraisal can also improve our understanding of the
administrative capacity and eectiveness of public policy (Chaker et al. 2006; Hahn and Tetlock
2008). There is great potential to inform political science discussion on capacity and imple-
mentation. Finally, as a highly visible form of evidence use, appraisal oers a fresh angle on some
rather old debates in public policy such as decision-making (Russel and Jordan 2009), policy
coordination (Schout and Jordan 2007), and the development and (non)-utilisation of evidence
in politics (Dowie 1996; Pawson 2002; Sanderson 2006). In fact, in this chapter we argue that
policy appraisal is a recent and more institutionalised manifestation of policy formulation activities
which have always been carried out in various forms.
This chapter provides an introduction to the principles and dynamic practices of policy apprai-
sal. We rst examine diering ideas about what appraisal is, or could be, starting from the most
basic denitions and how these have evolved over time as ever more ambitious expectations
have emerged as to what it can deliver in practice. We then discuss how policy appraisal has been
working in practice in dierent contexts particularly how it has become institutionalised in
many jurisdictions since the mid-1990s. These observations illustrate well the politicised nature
of knowledge use in policy-making and the obstacles to its institutionalisation. We then show
how several distinct types of research on these subjects have developed, sometimes in parallel
with practices, sometimes apart from them. The literatures on appraisal are advancing rapidly, but
we show that they often take us back to many fundamental debates in policy analysis, namely between
proponents of fairly linear models of knowledge transfer between experts and policy-makers,
and those adopting more post-positivist positions. In the nal section, we assess the relationship
between research and practice across dierent types of policy appraisal research, and question
some of the basic assumptions made about appraisal in the light of theory, research and practice.
Finally, we speculate on the possible future direction of policy appraisal research and practice.
What is policy appraisal?
Denitions of policy appraisal abound. One of the most widely cited is: [that] family of ex ante
techniques and procedures. that seek to inform decision makers by predicting and evaluating
the consequences of various activities according to certain conventions (Owens et al. 2004:
1944). Another, less well-known denition, is a test or judgment of some policy, with the aim
to inform the decision makers on the suitability, desirability, eectiveness or eciency of it (de
Ridder 2006: 21). Regardless of the denition, we are arguably living in an age of assessment
(Rayner 2003: 163). The assessment or appraisal of projects (e.g. through Environmental Impact
AssessmentEIA) has been routinely undertaken in many countries since the 1970s (Jay et al.
2007). This was followed by attempts to institute appraisal at the more strategic level of plans
and programmes (e.g. Strategic Environmental AssessmentSEA) (Bina 2007).
Policy appraisal
245
Put simply, policy appraisal is appraisal conducted at the policy level. It attempts to formalise
the decision-making process in a series of steps to be undertaken when developing a policy.
The end product is a report which describes the results of each step. The steps vary depending
on the jurisdiction applying the system (see the section How is policy appraisal practised?), but
at a general level they usually include: identifying the problem to be addressed by the proposed
policy; dening the objectives of the proposed policy; identifying the dierent policy options to
pursue these objectives; analysing the potential impacts of each option; comparing the options
by weighing up the negative and positive impacts for each; and setting out plans for monitoring
and evaluating the policy once it is implemented.
These are very similar to the standard steps in EIA and SEA (e.g. Barrow 1997). However,
the motives for appraising have varied enormously across jurisdictions and policy elds, from
environmental protection through to reducing regulatory burdens and promoting a neo-liberal
economic agenda (Kirkpatrick and Parker 2007; Jacob et al. 2007; Hertin et al. 2009b; OECD
2008). Dierent subtypes have emerged such as Regulatory Impact Assessment (RIA) (e.g. Radaelli
2004b) and Sustainability Impact Assessment (SIA) (e.g. Kirkpatrick and Lee 2001), each with a
slightly dierent conception of the basic steps outlined above. Appraisal systems in turn harness
a wide range of policy appraisal tools such as cost-benet analysis, scenario analysis and com-
puter modelling (Carley 1980; de Ridder et al. 2007; Nilsson et al. 2008). Until now, we have
mostly been concerned with textbook denitions and understanding of appraisal. In the next
section we turn to look at the very varied ways that policy appraisal has actually been practised
over the past 20 years or so.
How is policy appraisal practised?
Precursory forms of policy appraisal, which focused mainly on the assessment of economic and
administrative impacts of regulation, were introduced as early as 1966 (Denmark) and 1971
(USA) (OECD 2009). However, the practice spread only slowly at rst, with Finland and
Canada following in the 1970s and Australia, the UK, the Netherlands and Germany adopting
some form of policy appraisal in the mid-1980s. There was, however, a rapid rise in adoption in
the second half of the 1990s, following OECD recommendations on regulatory reform (OECD
1995), and again in the mid-2000s following the launch of the European Commissions Impact
Assessment system in 2003 (European Commission 2002). Better Regulation has ranked high
on the European Unions (EU) agenda for well over a decade now (Allio 2007), and the EU,
and especially the European Commission, was a highly visible adopter of policy appraisal, as part
of a number of measures designed to improve and streamline its decision-making processes in
order to improve the quality and coherence of the policy development process (European
Commission 2002: 2).
Many of the early policy appraisal systems were subsequently revised to include a wider range
of impacts. For example, the UK system introduced in 1986 as a Compliance Cost Assessment was
replaced in 1996 by a broader system of regulatory appraisal, but it did not appear in anything
near its current form of RIA until 1998. All 31 OCED countries had by 2008 either adopted,
or were in the process of adopting, policy appraisal (OECD 2009). A recent survey of 17 European
countries found that all of them had adopted some form of policy appraisal, although some coun-
tries were still in the early stages of implementation (Adelle et al. 2010). The most recent countries
to adopt policy appraisal have tended to be EU member states in Central and Eastern Europe
(CEE) such as Estonia and Lithuania (ibid.; De Francesco 2010), although there are some geo-
graphical exceptions such as Ireland which only introduced its system in 2005 (Adelle et al.
2010). There are also early CEE adopters like Hungary (1994) (see Staronova 2010). Recent
Turnpenny et al.
246
adoption appears to be one of the predictors of weak implementation of policy appraisal, with
many of the more sophisticated and robust systems being found in the older EU member states
(Adelle et al. 2010). In addition, policy appraisal is beginning to spread beyond the OECD and
EU (De Francesco 2010) and become a global norm (Jacobs 2006). Interest in policy appraisal
in middle- and lower-income countries is increasing, albeit from a relatively low base (Kirkpatrick
and Parker 2004; Kirkpatrick et al. 2004).
This widespread diusion of policy appraisal systems has not, however, led to a standard appraisal
approach. Radaelli (2005: 924) argues that it is an idea which has travelled lightly around the
world producing diusion without convergence. He claims that this has led to the introduc-
tion of a policy appraisal bottle which contains many dierent wines. Essentially most policy
appraisal systems (the bottle) draw on certain common elements: they are often but not always
supported by a legislative act making their application mandatory; they consist of similar pro-
cedural steps set out in ocial guidance documents (see above); they are undertaken by the
ocial responsible for policy development; and they result in a written document, which may
or may not be made public via a government website.
However, these common features disguise the many dierent ways policy appraisal is imple-
mented in practice (the wine). For example, in some cases, policy appraisal only exists on paper as
a tick-box exercise (Radaelli 2005). Radaelli attempted to account for this variety by exam-
ining how institutional and political context matters in the process of diusion. A number of
comparative surveys of policy appraisal practices around Europe have indeed revealed vast diversity
in the practice of policy appraisal. They have uncovered dierent institutional frameworks,
objectives, uses of policy appraisal tools, quality of reports, as well as the eects of cultures and
the place of appraisal within policy processes (e.g. Jacob et al. 2008; Adelle et al. 2010; Hertin et al.
2009a). These and other insights into the everyday practices of policy appraisal have emerged
from a rapidly developing academic literature, which we summarise in the next section.
Policy appraisal research
Policy appraisal research falls into dierent broad types. Some is strongly (although often implicitly)
premised on the positivist belief that more rational policy-making can be achieved by applying
analytical tools. The idea that appraisal exists to bring in evidence to counter interest-based policy-
making, to integrate cross-cutting issues, and to increase cooperation between dierent depart-
ments is widespread, not least in the guideline documents prepared for government ocials. It
is based on a rational model of linear knowledge transfer between experts and policy-makers.
Other research draws on a post-positivist epistemology, and emphasises the importance of
revealing, understanding and working with normative values in studying the relationship between
evidence and policy-making. Such an approach fundamentally challenges the underlying
assumption that policy appraisal is purely about informing (and thus improving) policy, and
hence challenges the straightforward denition of what policy appraisal is is it a tool, a method,
an instrument of public policy (e.g. Radaelli 2008: 6) or an administrative coordination mechan-
ism (Jordan and Schout 2006) for example? Policy appraisal can also, with varying degrees of
explicitness, be used to delay or dilute unwanted regulation, or to exert political control on
government departments and agencies.
Positivist approaches
Turnpenny et al. (2009) tried to make sense of these advances by subdividing the literature into
four main types. The rst two may be thought of as broadly positivist, while the third and
Policy appraisal
247
fourth are more post-positivist in their orienation. The rst type concerns the design of appraisal
systems themselves. This often highly technical literature is rooted in the environmental man-
agement, economics and policy analysis communities. It addresses the design of specic tools
and methods for policy appraisal such as Cost Benet Analysis, the so-called Standard Cost
Model, and more general tools such as computer models and scenarios (e.g. Quade 1989; Dunn
2004). It also includes attempts to inform the design of appraisal systems (e.g. Lee 2006; OECD
2008), and often takes the form of how to textbooks (e.g. Barrow 1997) and handbooks (e.g.
European Commission 2009), for which there is a steady demand amongst the practitioners
who perform appraisals. For useful overall reviews of this type of literature, see Eales et al. 2005;
Ness et al. 2007; de Ridder et al. 2007 and Tamborra 2002.
The second type of research concerns the assessment of the operation of policy appraisal designs in
practice, in individual jurisdictions and internationally (e.g. Lee and Kirkpatrick 2004; Renda
2006; Jacob et al. 2007; Hertin et al. 2009b; EEAC 2006). Initial attempts (e.g. Harrington et al.
2000) measured quality by comparing the contents of appraisal reports with ocial guidance.
Subsequent research extended this approach somewhat to emphasise aspects of the process of
appraisal using a more in-depth case study approach, often including interviews with those
involved (e.g. TEP 2007). This research has generated a fairly consistent picture of the empirical
reality of appraisal, namely that: there is a gap between the aims of appraisal and its imple-
mentation; the economic aspects of policy all too easily crowd out other (e.g. social and environ-
mental) aspects; appraisals tend to be performed at a relatively late stage in the policy process
and consequently have little or no inuence over the nal decisions made; consultation is often
limited to the usual suspects who have participated before or who have large resources; and
formal appraisal tools such as computer modelling are patchily used despite the strong political
invocation to use them. Most studies identify recommendations to policy-makers on how to
improve the quality of their appraisal systems. Many such recommendations focus on micro-
level constraints, such as calls for more training and guidance (EEAC 2006; DBR 2004; Jacobs
2006; NAO 2007; TEP 2007; Wilkinson et al. 2004). Another common recommendation is to
start the policy appraisal earlier in the policy process, when more options are likely to be open
(Renda 2006; TEP 2007; Wilkinson et al. 2004). Researchers such as Turnpenny et al. (2008) also
emphasised the need to address higher-level constraints through, for example: stronger political
leadership (Jacob et al. 2008; Russel and Jordan 2007); the creation of oversight and quality assur-
ance mechanisms (DBR 2004; TEP 2007; Torriti 2007; Wilkinson et al. 2004); and a greater
understanding, acceptance and use of appraisal tools (Jacob et al. 2008; Nilsson et al. 2008; de Ridder
et al. 2007; Turnpenny et al. 2008).
Post-positivist approaches
Research of the third and fourth types adopts a more post-positivist view. In the third type,
analysts have tried to go beyond calling for micro-level changes such as better training and political
support, and explored the wider political and institutional context in which appraisal systems
operate. Policy appraisal is, as all evidence use in policy-making is, a political activity (see, for
example, Hall (1989) on evidence generally, Richardson (2005) on EIA, and Turnpenny et al.
(2008) on policy appraisal). Such research searches for evidence that appraisal has led to policy
change via processes of learning, and attempts to understand what is aecting such processes,
such as the constraining eect of the institutional context in which appraisal takes place (Jacob et al.
2008; Russel and Jordan 2009; Thiel 2008; Turnpenny et al. 2008). For example, Thiel (2008)
revealed how appraisal in the European Commission is shaped by departmental cultures and
prior experiences of appraisal. There are a relatively small number of studies employing this type
Turnpenny et al.
248
of research (e.g. Cashmore et al. 2008; Hertin et al. 2009a; Hertin et al. 2009b; Jacob et al. 2008;
Nilsson 2006; Thiel and König 2008; Torriti 2007; Turnpenny et al. 2008). A distinction is
often made between single-loop (or instrumental) learning where knowledge directly informs
concrete decisions by providing specic information on the design of policies (Hertin et al.
2009a: 1187), and double-loop (or conceptual) learning where knowledge enlightens policy-
makers by slowly feeding new information, ideas and perspectives into the policy system (ibid.).
Clearly the former is more consistent with a positivist epistemology, whereas the latter is more
consistent with a post-positivist one. Much of this literature explicitly endorses more deliberative
approaches (e.g. Bond and Morrison-Saunders 2011; Cashmore et al. 2008; Owens et al. 2004).
However, a positivist epistemology continues to provide the foundation for most methodolo-
gical development (Bond and Morrison-Saunders 2011; Hertin et al. 2009a, 2009b). As a con-
sequence, while policy appraisal could potentially provide a new venue for conceptual learning,
it appears that this rarely occurs in practice (Hertin et al. 2009a: 1196).
The fourth type of research investigates the underlying motivations for appraising in the rst
place, such as to facilitate political control of bureaucracy (e.g. Radaelli and Meuwese 2010;
Radaelli 2008), following perceived best practice in other states (e.g. Radaelli 2005), and
attempts to modernise the state (Hood and Peters 2004; Radaelli and Meuwese 2010). Studies
of the diusion of policy appraisal practices across and within jurisdictions have emphasised how
dierent actors shape appraisal structures and practices to suit their preferences (Radaelli 2004a,
2004b, 2005). Research has also focused on the intended and unintended consequences of policy
appraisal. It treats appraisal as a good lens on the changing nature of the regulatory state in the EU
and its member states (Radaelli and Meuwese 2009: 651). In such accounts, the claim is that
politically contested questions (such as who is in charge of the law-making process?) are transferred
into more technocratic venues such as policy appraisal processes, where they can be more easily
resolved (Radaelli and Meuwese 2010: 143). Appraisal thus becomes a way to unite otherwise
incompatible political visions; in many respects, a form of politics by more technocratic means.
Policy appraisal research-practice relationships
There have been developments in both the research on, and practice of, policy appraisal, but to what
extent have research and practice actually informed each other? Susan Owens and her colleagues
(2004) expected the practices of, and the research on, appraisal to co-evolve in a steadily more
reexive, or mutually informing, direction. But while there are signs that policy appraisal research is
moving away from its positivist roots, both research and practice remain heavily informed by it.
According to Adelle et al. (2012), research on the design of appraisal systems continues apace.
Consequently, there are now myriad policy appraisal designs and tools that can be consulted.
However, the practices of policy appraisal appear to be informing such research only in a rather
general sense, namely through demands from policy-makers for policy appraisal tools, methods
and process designs. Consequently, there remains a gap between sophisticated tool knowledge
and pragmatic policy-making (de Ridder et al. 2007: 436). Thus, while both research and practice
still appear to be heavily informed by the positivist model, it is questionable if innovation in
both is proceeding in a mutually informative manner.
Regarding research on the assessment of the operation of policy appraisal, while at rst there was little
evidence that such research was producing changes in policy appraisal practices (e.g. Cecot et al.
2007; Renda 2006), the picture is now changing (e.g. European Court of Auditors 2010). There is
some evidence that as a direct consequence of research, policy appraisal systems in some jur-
isdictions have been revised to improve the impact of appraisals on political decision-making,
for example by setting up dedicated bodies to review the quality of appraisal and/or moving
Policy appraisal
249
responsibility for appraisal from specialised departments to the heart of government (Jacob et al.
2008: 11). However, such changes have not (yet) amounted to a serious reconsideration of the
theoretical underpinnings of appraisal practices or research. In mainly pursuing change at the
micro and occasionally meso levels, they essentially remain rooted in a positivist epistemology. At
present practitioners seem content to commission yet more research on the quality of the policy
appraisal systems in their jurisdictions (e.g. European Court of Auditors 2010; NAO 2009),
without really investigating some of the underlying contextual issues.
There is still relatively little post-positivist work. Perhaps this is not surprising considering the
diculties associated with studying learning processes over long time periods (Owens et al. 2004;
Radaelli 2009). Nonetheless, if research and practices were proceeding in parallel we would
expect to nd more evidence of policy appraisal practices being informed by post-positivistic
recommendations, such as more deliberative approaches. There is currently little evidence of
such innovative approaches within policy appraisal practice or research.
The role of appraisal in policy analysis
Another way to understand the current place of policy appraisal is to view it against the back-
drop of policy analysis more generally. Doing this reveals that appraisal raises some very old
questions. Modern policy analysis is usually held to date from the late 1940s, particularly forged
by the work of Lasswell, Simon and Lindblom. But each of these had very dierent ideas about the
nature and goals of policy, and hence disagreed about the form and function of policy analysis.
It is possible to divide the history of policy analysis into three broad waves. The rst wave,
from roughly the late 1940s to the late 1970s, corresponded to widespread use, and implicit
faith in, rationally based appraisal tools like cost-benet analysis, operations research and assessment
(Rossi et al. 2004; Wollmann 2007). But the limits to such tools soon became evident, and the
promise of analytically based answers to every policy question soon faded.
The second wave (Wollmann 2007) began as limits on the ability to predict every even-
tuality became clearer, and the politics surrounding use of analysis became more intense (Weiss
1979; Palumbo 1987). During the early 1980s, an anti-analytical mood of government coupled
with budgetary retrenchment pressure, particularly in the USA and the UK, resulted in a scaling
back of the policy units who once espoused analytical methods. But since the mid-1990s, there
has been a revival in the use of policy analytical tools in practical policy-making, including policy
appraisal. This shift corresponded with a drive to more evidence-based approach to policy-
making in an era of New Public Management (e.g. Radaelli 1995; Dowie 1996; Pawson 2002;
Sanderson 2006; Nutley et al. 2007). Critically and somewhat in tension with this third wave of
use there has been a blossoming of more sophisticated research on the discursive, argumentative
and political aspects of policy analysis (e.g. Majone 1989; Fischer 1995; John 1998). The tone of
this research has changed from discover and predict to a recognition of the power of language,
persuasion and argument ( John 1988: 154) the importance of revealing, understanding and
working with normative values expressed in a post-positivist epistemology (Fischer 1995). How-
ever, as we have seen, this post-positivist turn has made little impact so far on policy appraisal
research or practice. Policy appraisal is thus both a symptom of these long-term trends in policy
analysis, and a site of everyday politics around the use of knowledge in the policy process.
Conclusion
In this chapter we have shown that policy appraisal is an important aspect of policy analysis
which has spread rapidly and secured a high prole. It now appears in many dierent guises,
Turnpenny et al.
250
each with dierent aims. It is variously: a method or procedure for analysis; a policy instrument;
a site of political behaviour; and a technique for policy harmonisation across states. As it enjoys
its current and relatively rapid phase of proliferation, research on policy appraisal is moving
towards the mainstream of public policy research, on several dierent fronts. The broadly
positivist and broadly post-positivist approaches to understanding policy appraisal reect wider
debates within policy analysis and evidence use. But while policy appraisal has emerged as a
signicant part of the policy-making process in the last ten years or so, research and practice are
only weakly informed by post-positivist research developments elsewhere (Adelle et al. 2012).
This is partly because of the lack of a ready audience for such work. Many policy appraisal practi-
tioners have made a signicant political and/or resource commitment to forms of policy appraisal
informed by the rational model which they are reluctant to surrender. In part it is also due to
the nature of the post-positivist research, which questions the very purpose of doing appraisal.
What might this mean for the future of policy appraisal? In the second decade of the twenty-
rst century, perhaps another policy analysis wave is breaking. The tension between the broadly
positivist evidence-based policy underpinning of policy appraisal in practice, and the post-
positivist challenges to it, echo the transition from the rst to the second wave in the mid-late
1970s. Challenges to the evidence-based policy-making discourses of the early 2000s in the light
of economic crises and ideological retrenchment may have signicant implications for the future
direction of policy appraisal. Its continued rise, coupled with more political pressure, oers many
opportunities for research which examines underlying motivations for appraisal, and methods
for deducing this. Research could lead to a fuller understanding of when, why and how appraisal
practices depart from the positivist model, depending on the specic context(s) in which
appraisal is deployed. Work which seeks to mediate between the positivist and the post-positivist
approaches will also play a more signicant role. Policy appraisal researchers are well placed to
shape new developments. These are indeed fascinating times.
Bibliography
Adelle, C., A. Jordan, J. Turnpenny, S. Bartke, T. Bournaris, K. Jacob, H. Kuittinen, K. Mäkinen,
C. Moulogianni, T. Nõmmann, L.E. Larsen, K. Peterson, M. Perez Soba, L. Roupioz, B. Sánchez,
D. Wascher, and S. Weiland. 2010. A summary of user needs and expectations with regards to impact
assessment. Unpublished LIAISE project report prepared under contract from the European Commission.
Contract No. 243826.
——, A. Jordan and J.R. Turnpenny. 2012. Proceeding in parallel or drifting apart? A systematic review
of policy appraisal research and practices, Environment and Planning C 30(3): 400414.
Allio, L. 2007. Better regulation and impact assessment in the European Commission, in C. Kirkpatrick
and D. Parker (eds) Regulatory Impact Assessment: Towards Better Regulation? Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Bardach, E. 2005. A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Eective Problem-Solving.
Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Barrow, C.J. 1997. Environmental and Social Impact Assessment. London: Arnold.
Bina, O. 2007. A critical review of the dominant lines of argumentation on the need for strategic environmental
assessment, EIA Review 27: 585606.
Bond, A. and A. Morrison-Saunders. 2011. Re-evaluating sustainability assessment: Aligning the vision
and the practice, EIA Review 31(1): 17.
Carley, M. 1980. Rational Techniques in Policy Analysis. London: Heinemann.
Cashmore, M. 2004. The role of science in Environmental Impact Assessment: Process and procedure
versus purpose in the development of theory, EIA Review 24: 403 26.
——, A. Bond and D. Cobb. 2008. The role and functioning of environmental assessment: Theoretical
reections upon an empirical investigation of causation, Journal of Environmental Management 88:
123348.
Cecot, C., R.W. Hahn and A. Renda. 2007. A statistical analysis of the quality of impact assessment in the
European Union, AEI- Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory Studies. Working Paper 07-09.
Policy appraisal
251
Chaker, A., K. El-Fadl, L. Chamas and B. Hatjian. 2006. A review of strategic environmental assessment
in 12 selected countries, EIA Review 26(1): 1556.
DBR (EU Directors of Better Regulation Group). 2004. A comparative analysis of regulatory impact assessment
in ten EU countries , report prepared for the EU DBR Group, Dublin, May 2004 (accessed 15 August
2011). Available at: http://www.betterregulation.ie/eng/Publications/A_COMPARATIVE_ANALYSI
S_OF_REGULATORY_IMPACT_ASSESSMENT_IN_TEN_EU_COUNTRIES.html (accessed 15
August 2011).
De Francesco, F. 2010. The diusion process of regulatory impact analysis in EU and OECD member
states. PhD thesis, University of Exeter.
de Ridder, W. 2006. Tool Use in Integrated Assessment: Integration and Synthesis Report. Bilthoven: Netherlands
Environmental Assessment Agency.
——, J. Turnpenny, M. Nilsson and A. von Raggamby. 2007. A framework for tool selection and use in
integrated assessment for sustainable development, Journal of Environmental Assessment Policy and Management
9(4): 42341.
Dowie, J. 1996. ‘“Evidence-based, cost-eective and preference-driven medicine: decision analysis based
medical decision making is the pre-requisite, Journal of Health Services Research and Policy 1(2): 10413.
Dunn, W.N. 2004. Public Policy Analysis An Introduction, 3rd edn. Mahwah, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.
Eales, R., S. Smith, C. Twigger-Ross, W. Sheate, E. Özdemiroglu, C. Fry, P. Tomlinson and C. Foan.
2005. Emerging approaches to integrated appraisal in the UK, Impact Assessment and Project Appraisal
23(2): 11323.
EEAC (European Environment and Sustainable Development Advisory Councils). 2006. Impact assessment
of European Commission policies: Achievements and prospects, statement of the EEAC Working Group
on Governance, April.
European Commission. 2002. Impact assessment (COM (2002) 276), Commission of the European
Communities, Brussels.
—— 2009. Impact assessment guidance (SEC(2009)92), Commission of the European Communities, Brussels.
European Court of Auditors. 2010. Impact assessments in the EU institutions: Do they support decision-making?
Special Report No. 3, European Court of Auditors, Luxembourg.
Fischer,
F. 1995 Evaluating Public
Policy. Boulder, CO: Wadsworth.
Hahn, R.W. and P.C. Tetlock. 2008. Has economic analysis improved regulatory decisions?, Journal of
Economic Perspectives 22(1): 6784.
Hall, P.A. (ed.). 1989. The Political Power of Economic Ideas. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Harrington, W., R.D. Morgenstern and P. Nelson. 2000. On the accuracy of regulatory cost estimates,
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 19: 297322.
Hertin, J., J. Turnpenny, A. Jordan, M. Nilsson, D. Russel and B. Nykvist. 2009a. Rationalising the
policy mess? Ex ante assessment and the utilisation of knowledge in the policy process, Environment and
Planning A 41: 11851200
——, K. Jacob, U. Pesch and C. Pacchi. 2009b. The production and use of knowledge in regulatory
impact assessment: An empirical analysis, Forest Policy and Economics 11(56): 41321.
Hood, C. 2007. Intellectual obsolescence and intellectual makeovers: Reections on the tools of government
after two decades, Governance 20(1): 12744.
——and B.G. Peters. 2004. The middle aging of New Public Management: Into the age of paradox?,
Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 14: 26782
Howlett, M. 2011. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. London: Routledge.
——and M. Ramesh. 2003. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Jacob, K., J. Hertin and A. Volkery. 2007. Considering environmental aspects in integrated Impact
Assessment: Lessons learned and challenges ahead, in C. George and C. Kirkpatrick (eds) Impact
Assessment for a New Europe and Beyond. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
——, J. Hertin, P. Hjerp, C. Radaelli, A. Meuwese, O. Wolf, C. Pacchi, and K. Rennings. 2008. Improving
the practice of impact assessment, EVIA (Evaluating Integrated Impact Assessments) project report.
Project No. 028889, European Commission Sixth Framework Programme.
Jacobs, S.H. 2006. Regulatory impact analysis in regulatory process, method, and co-operation: Lessons
for Canada from international trends.
Policy Horizons Canada Working paper 026. Government of
Canada, Ottawa.
Jay, S.,
C. Jones, P. Slinn and C. Wood. 2007. Environmental impact assessment: Retrospect and prospect,
EIA Review 27: 287300.
Turnpenny et al.
252
John, P. 1998. Analysing Public Policy. London: Continuum.
Jordan, A. and A. Schout. 2006. The Coordination of the European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kirkpatrick, C. and N. Lee. 2001. Methodologies for sustainability impact assessments of proposals for
new trade agreements, Journal of Environmental Assessment, Policy and Management 3(3): 395412.
——and D. Parker (eds). 2007. Regulatory Impact Assessment: Towards Better Regulation? Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar Publishing.
——and D. Parker. 2004. Regulatory impact assessment and regulatory governance in developing countries,
Public Administration and Development 24(4): 33344.
——D. Parker and Y.-F. Zhang. 2004. Regulatory impact assessment in developing and transition
economies: A survey of current practice, Public Money and Management 24(5): 2916.
Lascoumes, P. and P. Le Galès. 2007. Introduction: Understanding public policy through its instruments:
From the nature of instruments to the sociology of public policy instrumentation, Governance 20(1): 121.
Lasswell, H.D. 1947. The Analysis of Political Behavior: An Empirical Approach. London: Routledge.
Lee, N. 2006. Bridging the gap between theory and practice in integrated assessment, EIA Review 26: 5778.
——and C. Kirkpatrick. 2004. A pilot study on the quality of European Commission extended impact
assessment. Draft For Consultation. Impact Assessment Research Centre, Institute for Development
Policy and Management, University of Manchester, 21 June.
Majone, G. 1989. Evidence, Argument and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
NAO (National Audit Oce). 2007. Evaluation of Regulatory Impact Assessments 200607. London: The
Stationery Oce.
—— 2009. Delivering High Quality Impact Assessments. London: The Stationery Oce.
Ness, B., E. Urbel-Piirsalu, S. Anderberg and L. Olsson. 2007. Categorising tools for sustainability assessment,
Ecological Economics 60: 498508.
Nilsson, M. 2006. The
role of assessments
and institutions for policy learning: A study on Swedish climate
and nuclear policy formation, Policy Sciences 38: 22549.
——, A. Jordan, J. Turnpenny, J. Hertin, B. Nykvist and D. Russel. 2008. The use and non-use of policy
appraisal in public policymaking: An analysis of three European countries and the European Union,
Policy Sciences 41(4): 33555.
Nutley, S.M., I. Walter and H.T.O. Davies. 2007. Using Evidence: How Research Can Inform Public Services.
Bristol: The Policy Press.
OECD (Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development). 1995. Recommendation of the Council
of the OECD on Improving the Quality of Government Regulation. Paris: OECD.
—— 2008. Building an Institutional Framework for Regulatory Impact Assessment: Guidance for Policy-makers.
Paris: OECD Publications.
—— 2009. Indicators of Regulatory Management Systems. Paris: OECD Publications.
Owens, S., T. Rayner and O. Bina. 2004. New agendas for appraisal: Reections on theory, practice and
research, Environment and Planning A 36: 194359.
Palumbo, D.J. 1987. Politics and evaluation, in D.J. Palumbo (ed.) The Politics of Program Evaluation.
Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1246.
Pawson, R. 2002. Evidence-based policy: In search of a method, Evaluation 8(2): 15781.
Quade, E.S. 1989. Analysis for Public Decisions , 3rd edn. Mahwah, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Radaelli, C. 1995. The role of knowledge in the policy process, Journal of European Public Policy 2: 15983
—— 2004a. Getting to grips with quality in the diusion of regulatory impact assessment in Europe,
Public Money and Management 5: 2716.
—— 2004b. The diusion of regulatory impact analysis: Best practice or lesson-drawing, European Journal
of
Political Research 43: 72347.
—— 2005. Diusion
without convergence: How political context shapes the adoption of regulatory
impact assessment, Journal of European Public Policy 12: 92443.
—— 2007. Whither better regulation for the Lisbon agenda?, Journal of European Public Policy 14(2): 190207.
—— 2008. Evidence-based policy and political control: What does Regulatory Impact Assessment tell us?,
paper for the European Consortium for Political Research Joint Sessions, workshop on The politics of
evidence-based policy-making, Rennes, 1116 April.
—— 2009. Measuring policy learning: Regulatory impact assessment in Europe , Journal of European Public
Policy 16: 114564.
——and A.C.M. Meuwese. 2009. Better regulation in Europe: Between public management and regulatory
reform, Public Administration 87: 63954.
Policy appraisal
253
——and A.C.M. Meuwese. 2010. Hard questions, hard solutions: Proceduralisation through impact
assessment in the EU, West European Politics 33: 13653.
Rayner, S. 2003. Democracy in the age of assessment: Reections on the roles of expertise and democracy in
the public sector decision making, Science and Public Policy 3: 16370.
Renda, A. 2006. Impact Assessment in the EU: The State of the Art and the Art of the State. Brussels: Centre for
Policy Studies.
Richardson, T. 2005. Environmental assessment and planning theory: Four short stories about power,
multiple rationality and ethics, EIA Review 25: 34165.
Rossi, P.H., M.W, Lipsey and H.E. Freeman. 2004. Evaluation: A Systematic Approach, 7th edn. Thousand
Oaks, CA: Sage.
Russel, D. and A. Jordan. 2007. Gearing-up governance for sustainable development: Patterns of policy
appraisal in UK central government, Journal of Environmental Planning and Management 50: 121.
——and A.J. Jordan. 2009. Joining up or pulling apart? The use of appraisal to coordinate policy-making
for sustainable development, Environment and Planning A 41(5): 120116.
Sanderson, I. 2006. Complexity, practical rationality and evidence-based policy making, Policy and
Politics 34(1): 11532.
Schout, A. and A. Jordan. 2007. What do new modes of governance demand of public administrations?,
paper presented at the Connex Workshop on Governing the European Union: Policy instruments in a
multi-level polity, Paris, 21 and 22 June. Sciences PoCentre détudes européennes.
Simon, H.A. 1976. Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision-making Processes in Administrative Organization,
3rd edn. London: Collier Macmillan.
Staronova, K. 2010. Regulatory impact assessment: Formal institutionalization and practice, Journal of
Public Policy 30(1):
11736.
Tamborra, M.
2002. Tools for Sustainability Impact Assessment of EU Policies: The Contribution of the EU Socio-economic
Research. Brussels: European Commission.
TEP (The Evaluation Partnership). 2007. Evaluation of the Commissions Impact Assessment system.
Final Report Submitted to Secretariat-General of the European Commission (Contract Number
SG-02/2006).
Thiel, A. 2008. Changing administrative culture and political debate? A review of impact assessment
practices in the European Commission, Zeitschrift für Umweltpolitik and Umweltrecht 31: 527.
——and B. König. 2008. An institutional analysis of the use of modelling tools within the European
Commission, in K. Helming and and H. Wiggering (eds) Sustainability Impact Assessment of Land Use
Policies. Heidelberg: Springer.
Torriti, J. 2007. Impact assessment in the EU: A tool for better regulation, less regulation, or less bad
regulation? Journal of Risk Research 10(2): 239 76.
Turnpenny, J., M. Nilsson, D. Russel, A. Jordan, J. Hertin and B. Nykvist. 2008. Why is integrating
policy assessment so hard? A comparative analysis of the institutional capacities and constraints, Journal of
Environmental Planning and Management 51(6): 75975.
——, C. Radaelli, A. Jordan and K. Jacob. 2009. The policy and politics of policy appraisal: Emerging
trends and new directions, Journal of European Public Policy 16: 64053.
Weiss, C. 1979. The many meanings of research utilization, Public Administration Review 39(5): 42631.
Wilkinson, D., M. Fergusson, C. Bowyer, J. Brown, A. Ladefoged, C. Monkhouse and A. Zdanowicz.
2004. Sustainable Development in the European Commissions Integrated Impact Assessments for 2003: Final
Report. London: Institute for European Environmental Policy.
Wollmann, H. 2007. Policy evaluation and evaluation research, in F. Fischer, G.J. Miller and M.S Sidney
(eds) Handbook of Public Policy Analysis: Theory, Politics and Methods. London: CRC Press, 393 402.
Turnpenny et al.
254
20
Policy analytical styles
Igor S. Mayer, C. Els van Daalen and Pieter W.G. Bots
Introduction: perspectives on policy analysis: a framework for
understanding and design
1
Policy analysis is a multifaceted eld in which a variety of dierent activities and ambitions have
found a place. Some policy analysts conduct quantitative or qualitative research while others recon-
struct and analyse political discourse or set up citizen forums. Some policy analysts are independent
researchers, some are process facilitators, while others act as political advisers (Dror 1967; Jenkins-
Smith 1982; Durning and Osuna 1994). The debate on the discipline for example, on its foun-
dations, underlying values and methods is conducted in a fragmented way (Dunn [1981] 1994;
Brewer and DeLeon 1983; Hogwood and Gunn 1984; Bobrow and Dryzek 1987; Wildavsky
1987; DeLeon 1988; MacRae and Whittington 1997; Hawkesworth 1988; House and Shull 1991;
Weimer and Vining 1992; Fischer and Forester 1993; White 1994; Radin 1997; Mayer 1997;
Hoppe 1998; Shulock 1999; Lynn 1999).
This is a pity, because it tends to sideline a reection on the relationship between applied research,
the use and development of methods in relation to policy advice and policy processes.
The variety and multifaceted nature of policy analysis makes it clear that there is no single, let
alone best, way of conducting policy analyses. The discipline consists of many dierent schools,
approaches, roles and methods. The observed diversity of policy analysis does give rise to numerous
questions. If we are unable to construct cohesion and unity behind this great diversity, we cannot
speak of a discipline. What relationship exists between the dierent schools and activities of policy
analysis? Do they exclude each other or are there in practice numerous hybrids and com-
binations? What conceptual framework do we have at our disposal if we need to demarcate the
discipline, design new methods and approaches, or evaluate projects? Can we enrich the metho-
dological toolbox by adding new methods? What is the relationship between policy analysis methods
and new insights from the policy sciences, such as interactive policy development and process man-
agement (Edelenbos 1999; de Bruijn et al. 2002)? These are important questions that we obviously
cannot answer in full and all at once, but for which we modestly hope to provide a framework.
Untangling and explaining
The great diversity of views, schools and methods easily causes confusion and gives rise to the
need for insight into the discipline for insiders and outsiders alike (Radin 1997; Lynn 1999).
255
Various attempts have been made to untangle and explain policy analysis as a methodical discipline.
Some well-known examples of models in which activities and methods are systematically rela-
ted can be found in Dunn (1994), Brewer and DeLeon (1983), Hogwood and Gunn (1984),
Bobrow and Dryzek (1987), Miser and Quade (1985), Patton and Sawicki (1986), Weimer and
Vining (1992) and Mayer (1997).
It is precisely because of the varied developments in policy analysis and the diuse image that
they create of the eld, that this chapter seeks to make the eld transparent and to structure it
with the help of a framework or conceptual model. Structuring will not take place by choosing
a specic author, perspective or school, but rather by displaying the variety of views of policy
analysis. It is not our intention to adopt a normative standpoint on what the most preferable form
or style of policy analysis should be. This chapter provides a framework for positioning the dier-
ent perspectives and for highlighting the implications of choosing a perspective when designing
or evaluating a policy analysis project.
The presented conceptual model therefore has three functions. First, structuring the eld into
activities and styles provides a greater insight into and overview of the diversity of policy analysis.
The model is a means to demarcate and understand the eld as a whole. Second, when designing a
particular policy analysis project, the analysts will select methods and tools they consider to be
appropriate. The model can support choosing existing methods and designing new methods. Third,
we believe that the quality of a policy analysis project can be judged from dierent perspectives.
The model helps to formulate the values pertaining to a perspective, values from which criteria
for the evaluation of a policy analysis project can be derived.
Research approach
In our attempt to (re)structure the dierent styles and construct a conceptual model, we reviewed
the authoritative literature on the development of policy analysis and policy analysis styles. This
review led to an important observation. All characterisations of policy analysis are inclusive of a
limited number of preferred styles but are also exclusive of other styles, either because these are
not considered at all or because they are criticised as not being (eective) policy analysis (e.g.
Lawlor 1996). From the present literature, a preliminary classication of policy analysis activities,
roles and values was constructed.
A set of interacting activities
Our strategy in developing the model has been to rst address the question: What general
activities do policy analysts perform when it comes to supporting policy and policy processes?
We identied six major clusters of activities. They are:
1 Research and analyse: this cluster of activities matches with a perspective on policy analysis as
knowledge generation. Knowledge institutions, such as statistical agencies, semi-scientic
research institutions, and research agencies, gather and analyse, on request and on their own
initiative, knowledge and information for policy purposes. It is possible that the political
agenda inuences their research priorities, but the results of their autonomous research activities
may also inuence the political agenda. Translation of the results of their research into a policy
design or recommendation is not a primary part of their task or mission. It is up to the political
system to identify consequences and draw conclusions from the best available knowledge.
2 Design and recommend: when sucient data and information have been gathered in earlier
research, a policy analysis will focus on translating the available knowledge into new
Mayer et al.
256
policy, either by making recommendations or by making a complete policy design. Recom-
mendations will typically be the result of comparing the eects of dierent policy alter-
natives and weighing the options based on various criteria. Policy analysts in this way
are supportive to the policy process by translating available knowledge into new policy
either by advising or by making (partial) policy designs in terms of actions-means-ends.A
complete policy design typically involves generating a set of alternative strategies that
each consists of several tactics aimed at achieving particular objectives or sub-goals (see
Walker 1988).
3 Clarify arguments and values: there will always be implicit normative and ethical
questions and opinions behind public policy. Prolonged conicts and social issues that
turn into stalemates often come about through fundamental normative and argu-
mentative dierences (van Eeten, 2001; Fischer and Forester 1993). Abortion, euthanasia
and drilling for natural gas in protected areas are examples of such issues. Policy analysis
may not only make instrumental recommendations for policy-making; it may also
analyse the values and argumentation systems that underpin social and political debate.
Moreover, policy analysis seeks to improve the quality of debate by identifying the one-
sided or limited nature of arguments or showing where blind spots exist in the debate
(Hoppe 1998).
4 Provide strategic advice: policy analysis will often be a strategic, client-oriented activity.
The substantive or procedural advice will be made dependent on the analysis of the eld
of forces that exist, namely the environment in which the client and his problem are
located. The policy analyst will advise the client on the most eective strategy for achieving
certain goals given a certain political constellation, namely the nature of the environment
in which the client operates, the likely countersteps of opponents, and so on.
5 Democratise: in the democratise cluster of activities, policy analysis does not have a value-
free orientation, but a normative and ethical objective: it should further equal access to,
and inuence on, the policy process for all stakeholders (DeLeon 1988, 1994; Lerner and
Lasswell 1951). Experts and elites are more likely to be involved and carry greater weight
than ordinary citizens and laymen (Fischer 1990). Policy analysis can try to correct this
inequality by calling attention to views and opinions typically overlooked in policy-making
and decision-making (Fischer 2000).
6 Mediate: policy analysts can play a role in enhancing the knowledge actors have about
their own position, about the actors room for manoeuvring, and in looking for possible
compromises and win-win options. In addition, they can be involved in designing the rules
and procedures for negotiating in a policy-making or decision-making process and mana-
ging the interaction and progress of that process. The mediation cluster comprises dierent
types of activities, with a focus on analysing contextual factors (e.g. dependency analysis,
transaction analysis), and designing, and possibly also facilitating, meetings in which dif-
ferent stakeholders and decision-makers consult and negotiate. The policy analyst can be
involved during the design of the negotiation process as well as its execution.
In real-life cases and projects, a policy analyst will combine one or more activities, albeit not
all at the same time. When more activities are combined, a policy analysis project will become
richer and more comprehensive, but also more complex.
The hexagon in Figure 20.1 is a diagrammatic representation of these six activities. The
theoretical foundation will be discussed later in this chapter, when we show the policy analysis
styles and values on which the clustering of activities has been based. In this section, we focus
on the six activities and illustrate these with the help of examples based on policy analyses.
Policy analytical styles
257
At the end of this section, we will look at the relations between the various activities in
more detail.
Policy analysis styles
It is the objective of our model to clarify and understand the discipline of policy analysis. Numerous
schools of thought, paradigms and models can be found in the policy analysis literature (Bobrow
and Dryzek 1987; DeLeon 1988; Hawkesworth 1988; House and Shull 1991; Mayer 1997). In this
chapter, we will refer to styles of policy analysis rather than to a paradigm, model or school. Based
on the schools discussed in the literature and the framework of our model, we have identied
six policy analysis styles. They are:
1 a rational style;
2 an argumentative style;
3 a client advice style;
4 a participatory style;
5 a process style;
6 an interactive style.
Figure 20.2 shows how these styles relate to the activities discussed above. Below, we will briey
discuss the styles in an archetypical manner. We will focus on the arguments that are used by
proponents of these styles.
The rational style
The rational style is shaped to a large degree by assumptions about knowledge and reality, and
by a relatively large distance between the object and subject of study: it is assumed that the
world is to a large extent empirically knowable and often measurable. Knowledge used for policy
must be capable of withstanding scientic scrutiny. The role of knowledge in policy is a positive
Figure 20.1 Policy analysis tasks
Source: Mayer et al.. 2004. Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for understanding and
design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991
Mayer et al.
258
one, namely a greater insight into causes, eects, nature and scale produces better policy (Weiss
and Bucuvalas 1980). Policy should come about preferably in neat phases, from preparation
to execution, with support through research in each phase. An example of this policy analysis
approach is the systems analysis method developed by the RAND Corporation (Quade 1989;
Miser and Quade 1985). The advice on policy regarding the Eastern Scheldt storm surge barrier
in the Netherlands was obtained using this method (Goeller et al. 1977). This style is discussed
in many general textbooks on methods of policy analysis (Patton and Sawicki 1986; MacRae
and Whittington 1997; House and Shull 1991).
Argumentative style
This style assumes that policy is made, defended and criticised through the medium of language.
The basic assumption of the argumentative style is therefore that when analysing policy, it is
important to devote attention to aspects related to the language game that takes place around a
policy problem or issue. Attention will shift to the debate and the place in the debate of arguments,
rhetoric, symbolism and stories (Fischer and Forester 1993; Fischer 1995; van Eeten 2001). Argu-
ments aim to have an eect on the public. The positions of parties and the argumentations in a
policy discourse are not always clear and unambiguous, however. Therefore, policy analysis will
make policy easier to understand by illustrating the argumentations and the quality thereof schema-
tically and making a judgement based on criteria such as justication, logic and richness (Dunn 1982,
1994). But the ambition of argumentative policy analysis is to use such an analysis to produce
recommendations and improvements in situations where parties have been talking at cross-purposes
for many years: a dialogue between the deaf (van Eeten 2001). The argumentative style assumes that
it can make the structure and progress of the discourse transparent by means of interpretive and
qualitative methods and techniques, and can also bring about improvements by identifying caveats
in the debate or searching for arguments and standpoints that can bridge the gap between oppo-
nents. This style of policy analysis centres on discourse and argumentation analyses so as to frame
the dierent standpoints of clusters of parties and, if possible, change and inuence them.
Figure 20.2 Policy analysis styles
Source: Mayer et al. (2004) Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for understanding and
design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991
Policy analytical styles
259
Client advice style
In a number of respects, the client advice style is based on assumptions that policy-making
occurs in a complex and rather chaotic arena. There are numerous players, with dierent interests
and strategies (de Bruijn and ten Heuvelhof 2000; de Bruijn et al. 2002). Therefore, it is wise to
gain insight into the various objectives, means and interests of the actors involved. For that
reason, the analysis of this complex environment is important and can be undertaken analyti-
cally and systematically by such means as stakeholder analyses, although intuition and soft
information denitely play a role. Besides knowledge and insights gained through research,
policy analysis is largely a question of politico-strategic insight and skills including client-
analyst communication. In addition to being a skill, methodical and explicit, policy analysis is
also an art in which tacit knowledge plays an important role (Wildavsky 1987). Depending on
orientation, the client advice style involves a more design-oriented approach or a strategic,
process-driven approach.
Participatory style
Participatory policy analysis views the relationship between research and advice on the one
hand and policy and politics on the other by looking at society critically (Fischer 1990, 2000).
Here it is assumed that not all sections of the population have ready access to policy systems.
Researchers, economic elites, institutionalised non-governmental organisations and politicians
dominate policy discussions and decisions about major social issues (Jasano 1990). Researchers,
stakeholders and policy-makers will even change roles and positions within one and the same
system. Certain subjects and also certain groups of actors are often excluded from the social
debate. This is referred to as the technocratic criticism of policy analysis (Fischer 1990). Participatory
policy analysis assumes that citizens can have a voice and be or become interested enough to
deliberate on substantive and politically dicult questions (Dryzek 1990; Fishkin 1991; Durning
1993; DeLeon 1994; Mayer 1997; Fischer 2000). The policy analyst can take on a facilitating role
in such a debate by promoting equality and openness in the design and by giving ordinary citizens
and laymen a role alongside others (Mayer 1997).
Process style
Just as in a game of chess, the parties that participate in a policy-making process will exhibit
strategic behaviour in the pursuit of their own objectives and achievement of the best possible
positions, even if such action runs counter to the public interest formulated in policy (de Bruijn
et al. 2002). It is perfectly understandable that, in controversial and complex issues, opponents
will underpin their case with conicting research reports. Impartial experts do not exist and a
solution by way of new reports and studies can aggravate the problem in a certain sense. In fact,
knowledge is (not much more than) negotiated knowledge. It is better to negotiate and reach
agreements about the use of the results of a study or jointly contracting research (de Bruijn et al.
2002). The process style of policy analysis is based on the assumption that substantive aspects of
a policy problem are, in fact, coordinate or perhaps even subordinate to the procedural aspects
of a policy problem. The analyst or process manager creates loose coupling of procedural
aspects and substantive aspects of a problem. Procedural aspects are understood to be the orga-
nisation of decision-making or the way in which parties jointly arrive at solutions to a problem.
To that end, agreements can be reached through mediation and negotiation. If the procedural
sides of a policy-making or decision-making process have been thought through properly, it
Mayer et al.
260
will greatly increase the likelihood of substantive problems being resolved. Substantive problems
can be made part of a process design, for example, by placing the dierent substantive aspects
on the agenda.
Interactive style
The interactive style of policy analysis assumes that individuals experts, analysts, clients, sta-
keholders and target groups have or may have diering views of the same policy problem.
An insight relevant to policy can be obtained by bringing about a confrontation and interaction
of dierent views. The interactive style has a strong socio-constructive foundation. Dierent
views of reality can be valid simultaneously. Through continuous interaction and interpretation
the hermeneutic circle’–it is possible to gain an insight (Guba and Lincoln 1989).
In an interactive style of policy analysis, target groups and stakeholders are usually invited to
structure problems or devise solutions in structured working meetings at which policy analysis
techniques may be used (Mason and Mitro 1981). This brings about a multiple interaction
whereby the views and insights of the analyst, the client and also the participants are enriched
(Edelenbos 1999). In other words, participants learn about their own views in relation to
those of others, and have an opportunity to rene those views. The selection of views is
obviously crucial. Political considerations the power to obstruct and enrichment argu-
ments what citizens really think may be interwoven. What matters is the quality of the
obtained insights in combination with the heterogeneity of opinions and interests. If policy
analysis concerns the redevelopment of a city square, for example, stakeholders such as local
residents and business people can be consulted by means of workshops about the problems they
experience with the present arrangement of the square and their wishes with regard to the new
plans. The interactive style assumes that a process like this is informative for decision-makers and
planners, is more likely to lead to acceptance and fullment of the plans, and can bring about all
kinds of positive eects among the participants (learning about each other and about policy
processes) (ibid.).
Denition of archetypal styles
Figure 20.3 shows the policy analysis styles placed in an archetypal way between the dierent
activities. This rightly suggests that a style balances on two important activities. This balance
does not necessarily need to be in equilibrium. Participatory policy analysis balances between
democratisation and clarication of values and arguments. The emphasis may be more on one
activity than on the other: citizens can be directly involved in discussions about genetic technology,
or the analyst may be mainly interested in the value systems, arguments and opinions of citizens
about the technology and may want to systematise them for the purpose of policy advice.
The argumentative style balances between research and analysis and clarication of values and
arguments. Some argumentative policy analysts attempt to improve the quality of policy by
testing the policy design as thoroughly as possible, or by building on consistency, validity and so
on, of the underlying arguments (Dunn 1994). This is based on the principle that claims must
be substantiated up by facts (backings). The formal logic is dominant in this setting. Others
reconstruct arguments, not in relation to scientic quality, but according to their variety and
richness. This allows greater scope for normative systems, religion and intuitive arguments
(Fischer 1995).
In a similar way, the rational style balances between researched analysis and advisory design;
the interactive style between democratisation ambitions and mediation activities; the client advice
Policy analytical styles
261
style between substantive design and strategic advice; and the process style between strategic advice
and mediation. The styles of policy analysis may thus have dierent manifestations and emphases.
A focus on a certain activity may result in a style leaning more towards one activity than to another.
Combining activities
In the preceding sections of this chapter, we have dierentiated between the policy analysis
styles by showing that they balance between two activities. It is also possible to let go of the
balance and to make combinations of activities that are not adjacent to one another. In other
words, a policy analytic arrangement will be made whereby two or more activities that are oppo-
site, rather than adjacent, to each other in the hexagon of Figure 20.1 can be combined. This
kind of combination or arrangement, symbolised by the dashed diagonals in the hexagon, is
achievable in two ways:
1 The activities can be carried out sequentially or separately, either in various parts of
one policy analysis project or in dierent complementary or competing projects; i.e. a
form of methodological triangulation of activities. As part of a policy analysis project
focusing on climate change, for example, rst research can be conducted by experts using
climate models (activity: research) and subsequently the perceptions and arguments of
ordinary citizens and laymen regarding climate change can be mapped out (activity: clarify
arguments).
2 The various activities can be integrated into one design or method. As part of a project
focusing on climate change, for example, climate models can be used to get various groups
Figure 20.3 The underlying values and criteria of policy analysis
Source: Mayer et al. (2004) Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for understanding and
design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991
Mayer et al.
262
of stakeholders, experts, politicians and so on to jointly generate and test policy proposals,
while obtaining feedback from representative citizen panels. Such a design would integrate
various activities: research, design, democratise and mediate.
Underlying values
Evaluation criteria
In addition to demarcating and understanding the eld of policy analysis and designing a policy
analysis project, our model has a third function: evaluation of policy analysis projects and
methods (Twaalfhoven 1999). The various activities and styles are based on underlying values
and orientations. The values determine in what way a policy analyst or others will view the
quality of the policy analysis study and the criteria that will be applied to examine it. These
criteria can be made explicit by addressing the following questions:
Rational style: what is good knowledge?
Argumentative style: what is good for the debate?
Client advice style: what is good for the client/problem owner?
Participatory style: what is good for democratic society?
Process style: what is good for the process?
Interactive style: what is good for mutual understanding?
Figure 20.3 shows that the activities in the top half of the hexagon are primarily object-oriented
activities: a system, a policy design, an argumentative analysis. The activities at the bottom are
subject-oriented activities. They focus primarily on the interaction between citizens, stakeholders,
the analyst and the client. Whereas the top-half activities are usually captured in a product e.g.
a report, a design, a computer model the eects of the bottom-half activities are usually cap-
tured in the quality of the process itself: increased support base, mutual understanding, citizen-
ship, learning. The distinction objectsubject translates into the types of evaluation criteria to
be applied. Object-oriented policy analysts will judge the quality of a policy analysis by its sci-
entic rigor or the substantive insights it has yielded. Subject-oriented policy analysts will base
their judgement on the contribution of the orchestrated interaction between stakeholders to the
decision-making process. The turning point between object and subject-oriented activities lies
with clarication of values and arguments and provision of strategic advice . These can be either
object-oriented and/or subject-oriented.
Figure 20.3 also shows that the activities on the left-hand side are judged by idealistic and
generic criteria for good policy analysis, such as validity, reliability, consistency, fairness, equality
or openness. The activities on the right-hand side of the hexagon are judged by pragmatic and
particular criteria, such as workability, usability, opportunity, feasibility or acceptance.
These criteria for evaluating the quality of a policy analysis project or method are summarised
in Box 20.1 and appear in the corners of the hexagon in Figure 20.3.
The role of the policy analyst
As the presented model is based on activities, styles and their associated values, it also generates
and organises the positive and negative images, the metaphors, of the policy analyst (Dror 1967;
Jenkins-Smith 1982; Durning and Osuna 1994). Some policy analysts allow themselves to be
guided mainly by their wish to conduct objective scientic research; these are the objective
Policy analytical styles
263
technicians. In contrast, others seek interaction with their client; these are the client advisers or
counsellors. Some advocate a clear standpoint such as a more stringent environmental policy;
these are the issue activists. How the role of a policy analyst is perceived depends on ones own
values and position in a policy process. A skilful strategic advisor, for example, may be highly
appreciated by his/her client, but portrayed as a hired gun by his/her clients opponents. In
Table 20.1, positive and negative images of the role of the policy analysts are depicted for each
activity.
Box 20.1 Translation of values into quality criteria
Research and analyse
Policy analysis will be judged by substantive (scientic) quality criteria, such as validity and
reliability, the use and integration of state-of-the-art knowledge, the quality of data gathering
and the formal argumentation and validation of conclusions.
Design and recommend
Policy analysis will be judged by instrumental criteria of policy relevance, such as usability
and accessibility for policy-makers, action orientation and utilisation, presentation and
communication of advice, weighing up of alternatives, clear choices and so on.
Clarify values and arguments
Policy analysis will be judged by quality of argumentation and debate criteria such as formal
logic (consistency), informal logic (rhetoric and sophism), and quality of the debate in terms
such as richness, layering and openness of arguments.
Advise strategically
Policy analysis will be judged by pragmatic and political effectiveness criteria, such as the
workability of advice, political cleverness and proactive thinking, greater insight (for the
client) in the complex environments (political and strategic dynamics, forces and powers),
targeting and achievement of goals.
Democratise
Policy analysis will be judged by democratic legitimacy criteria, such as openness and
transparency of the policy-making process, representation and equality of participants and
interests, absence of manipulation and so on.
Mediate
Policy analysis will be judged by external acceptance and learning criteria, such as the agree-
ment that mutually independent actors reach on the process and/or content, support for
and commitment to the negotiating process and solutions, learning about other problem
perceptions and solutions.
Mayer et al.
264
Perspectives on the eld of policy analysis
Figure 20.4 presents the complete conceptual model in which policy analysis activities are related
to underlying styles and values and the policy analysts roles. The gure enables us to demarcate
all manifestations and varieties of policy analysis and also to develop new approaches and methods.
Methods developed mainly within one style of policy analysis can be combined with insights
from another style and adapted to new activities. Below, we will briey recapitulate the functions
of the model, namely demarcate, design and evaluate.
Reection on policy analysis
Policy analysis is characterised by ambitions but also by ambivalences. Various approaches criti-
cise each other and it is very dicult to dene and describe what policy analysis is. The added
value of our model is that it shows why policy analysis is ambivalent and elusive, namely because
the proponents and opponents reason from dierent points of departure, about what they are
doing, why they are doing it, and the limitations or conversely the richness of the discipline. It
is not our intention in this chapter to adopt a position on our preferred form of policy analysis,
even if we were to have one. Depending on ones own position, one may accept the wide picture
of policy analysis as depicted in our model, but it is likely that many will argue that certain styles
or activities are not (proper) policy analysis (e.g. Lawlor 1996): for those critics, the hexagon
may turn into a straight line, a triangle or a square. The problem, of course, is that there will be
no disciplinary consensus on what activities and styles to cut from the hexagon and on what grounds.
For every policy analytic style there are both proponents and critics. Given the actual and desirable
development of the various denitions of policy analysis, we are of the opinion that it is better
to dene the discipline too widely than too narrowly. The integrated conceptual model oers
full scope without losing the unity of the policy analysis and causing the disintegration of the eld.
The model oers the possibility to examine policy analyses already performed and to relate these to
each other. The model seeks to provide a foothold, or a framework, for demarcating the wide
eld of work.
Table 20.1 Positive and negative images of the policy analyst
Activity Positive role image Negative role image
Research and analyse Independent scientist;
objective researcher.
A-moral researcher;
technocrat.
Design and recommend Independent expert;
engineer; impartial adviser.
Desk expert;
back seat driver.
Clarify values and arguments Logician or ethicist;
narrator.
Linguistic purist;
journalist.
Advise strategically Involved client adviser;
client counsellor; policy
entrepreneur
Hired gun
Democratise Democratic (issue) advocate. Missionary;
utopian.
Mediate Facilitator; mediator;
process manager.
Manipulator;
relativist.
Source: Mayer et al. (2004). Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for understanding and design, International
Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991
Policy analytical styles
265
Design of a policy analysis
The model provides an overview of the wealth of possibilities of policy analysis studies and the
interrelationships between them, and can be of help in reecting consciously and creatively on
the design of a policy analysis. As a rule, policy analysis projects require a customised design. It is
possible, however, to fall back on standard methods of policy analysis, although the choice and
combination of methods will depend on the problem under examination. The model denitely
does not seek to prescribe instrumentally how a policy analysis should be designed. The oppo-
site is the case, because we advocate creativity and innovation in designing approaches, actions
and methods. Innovative combinations of researching, designing, recommending, mediating, argu-
mentation and democratisation can be made. If desired, a rational style of policy analysis may be
combined, for example, with a process style. This would interweave analytical or scientic study
in mediation processes between parties (de Bruijn et al. 2002).
We consider the design of policy analysis to include the development of new methods of
policy analysis so as to allow a good integration of sub-activities. In point of fact, the history of
policy analysis is characterised by the repeated application of creative and intelligent combinations
of methods; methods that originated in one domain are translated into applications for other
domains. The, by now, classical Delphi and scenario methods came about as methods for studying
the future, but are currently used for strategic advice, mediation and even democratisation in
policy Delphis, interactive scenario methods and scenario workshops (Mayer 1997). Cross-impact
techniques and stakeholder analysis techniques, which came about as methods for advising clients,
now have principally interactive applications and are used for mediation. Consensus conferences
Figure 20.4 Overview of the complete hexagon model of policy analysis
Source: Mayer et al. (2004). Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for understanding and
design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991
Mayer et al.
266
that came about as a method for study and mediation between leading experts in medical sci-
entic controversies have been transformed into methods for democratising and for public
participation (Mayer 1997; Fischer 2000).
Evaluation of a policy analysis
Each policy analysis activity is based (implicitly) on values concerning the quality and purposes
of the policy analysis. Therefore, policy analysis projects can be examined from dierent per-
spectives. This may lead to dierent opinions about success or failure, quality or shortcomings.
A substantively thorough and valid study can be unusable for a client. A brilliant and workable
compromise that breaks a stalemate may be based on negotiated nonsense (van de Riet 2003) or
may violate or manipulate the interests of legitimate participants. Conicts like these are almost
inherent in every evaluation of sizeable policy analysis projects. In the design and evaluation,
the policy analyst attempts to cope as well as possible with these tensions and dilemmas, either
by making choices or by nding new routes.
Conclusion
In this chapter we have presented a model for policy analysis based on six archetypal policy
analysis activities. This subdivision makes it possible to relate various policy analysis styles found
in the literature to each other and to analyse the characteristics of and dierences between the
styles. Additionally, the activities provide pointers for evaluating policy analyses. By explicitly
identifying which activities are being pursued with the policy analysis, it is possible to use that
information as a basis for identifying success criteria for the policy analysis. The developed fra-
mework seeks to map out transparently the enormous variety of dierent types of policy ana-
lyses and to allow them to be viewed in relation to each other. The model can also be used to
design policy analysis studies. By making explicit which activities are relevant in a particular policy
analysis, a conscious choice can be made for a certain policy analysis style and the policy analysis
methods can be selected in a well-founded way for the contribution made by the method or
technique to the activities that must be carried out.
While the developed framework provides pointers for reection, design and evaluation, it is
not intended to be a rigid, prescriptive model. Rather, the intention is for the policy analyst to
be consciously working on the goal of the analysis in relation to the policy-making process and
to produce his own policy analysis design and evaluation.
Note
1 This chapter is a condensed and slightly adapted version of a journal article previously published as: I.S.
Mayer; P.W.G. Bots and C.E. van Daalen. (2004). Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for
understanding and design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(2): 16991. The
material has been reused with permission of the copyright owner.
Bibliography
Bobrow, D. and J. Dryzek. 1987. Policy Analysis by Design . Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Brewer, G. and P. DeLeon. 1983. The Foundations of Policy Analysis. Homewood, IL: Dorsey.
de Bruijn, J. and E. ten Heuvelhof. 2000. Networks and Decision-Making. Utrecht: Lemma.
——, E. ten Heuvelhof and R. in t Veld. 2002. Process Management, Why Project Management Fails in
Complex Decision-Making Processes. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Policy analytical styles
267
DeLeon, P. 1988. Advice and Consent: The Development of the Policy Sciences. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
—— 1994. Democracy and the policy sciences: Aspirations and operations, Policy Studies Journal 22: 20012.
Dror, Y. 1967. Policy analysts: A new professional role in government service, Public Administration
Review 27(3): 198.
Dryzek, J. 1990. Discursive Democracy; Politics, Policy and Political Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Dunn, W. [1981]1994. Public Policy Analysis: An Introduction, 1st and 2nd edns. Englewood Clis, NJ:
Prentice Hall.
—— 1982. Reforms as arguments, Knowledge, Creation, Diusion, Utilization 3(3): 293326.
Durning, D. 1993. Participatory policy analysis in a social service agency: A case study, Journal of Policy
Analysis and Management 12(2): 297322.
——and W. Osuna. 1994. Policy analysts, roles and value orientations: An empirical investigation using
Q methodology, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 13(44): 62957.
Edelenbos, J. 1999. Design and management of participatory public policy making, Public Management
1(4): 56978.
—— 2000. Process in Shape. PhD thesis. Lemma: Utrecht.
Fischer, F. 1990. Technocracy and the Politics of Expertise. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
—— 1995. Evaluating Public Policy. Chicago: Nelson-Hall.
—— 2000. Citizens, Experts and the Environment. The Politics of Local Knowledge. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
——and J. Forester (eds). 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Fishkin, J. 1991. Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reform. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Goeller, B., A. Abrahamse, B.H. Bigelow, J.G. Bolten, D.M. De Ferranti, J.C. DeHaven, T.F. Kirkwood,
R. Petruschell. 1977. Protecting an Estuary from Floods: A Policy Analysis of the Oosterscheld,
vol. 1. Santa
Monica,
CA: Summary Report, prepared for the Netherlands Rijkswaterstaat.
Guba, E. and Y. Lincoln. 1989. Fourth Generation Evaluation. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Hawkesworth, M. 1988. Theoretical Issues in Policy Analysis. Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press.
Hogwood, B. and L. Gunn. 1984. Policy Analysis for the Real World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hoppe, R. 1998. Policy analysis, science, and politics: From speaking truth to power to making sense
together”’, Science and Public Policy 26(3): 201 10.
House, P. and R. Shull. 1991. The Practice of Policy Analysis; Forty Years of Art and Technology. Washington,
DC: Compass.
Jasano, S. 1990. The Fifth Branch. Science Advisors as Policymakers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Jenkins-Smith, H. 1982. Professional roles of policy analysts, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 2(1):
88100.
Lawlor, E. 1996. Book review of The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning, F. Fischer and
J. Forester. (eds) Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 15(1): 11046.
Lerner, D. and Lasswell, H. (eds). 1951. The Policy Sciences, Recent Developments in Scope and Methods.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Lynn, L. 1999. A place at the table: Policy analysis, its postpositive critics, and the future of practice,
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 18(3): 41124.
MacRae, D. and D. Whittington. 1997. Expert Advice for Policy Choice: Analysis and Discourse. Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press.
Mason, R. and I. Mitro. 1981. Challenging Strategic Planning Assumptions. Theory, Cases and Techniques.
New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Mayer, I. 1997. Debating Technologies: A Methodological Contribution to the Design and Evaluation of Participatory
Policy Analysis. Tilburg: Tilburg University Press.
——, C. Els van Daalen and Pieter W.G. Bots. 2004. Perspectives on policy analysis: A framework for
understanding and design, International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 4(1): 16991.
Miser, Hugh J. and E.S Quade. 1985. Handbook of Systems Analysis. New York: North-Holland.
——and E. Quade. 1988. Handbook of Systems Analysis: Craft Issues and Procedural Choices. Chichester: John
Wiley
& Sons.
Mayer et al.
268
Patton, C. and D. Sawicki. 1986. Basic Methods of Policy Analysis and Planning. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice
Hall.
Quade, E. 1975. Analysis for Public Decisions. New York: Elsevier.
Radin, B. 1997. Presidential address: The evolution of the policy analysis eld: \from conversation to
conversations, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 16(2): 20418.
Shulock, N. 1999. The paradox of policy analysis: If it is not used, why do we produce so much of it?,
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 18(2): 22644.
Twaalfhoven, P. 1999. The Success of Policy Analysis Studies: An Actor Perspective. Delft: Eburon.
van De Riet, O. 2003. Policy analysis in Multi-Actor Settings: Navigating between Negotiated Nonsense and
Superuous Knowledge. Delft: Eburon.
van Eeten, M. 2001. Recasting intractable policy issues: The wider implications of the Netherlands civil
aviation controversy, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 20(3): 391414.
Walker, W. 1988. Generating and screening alternatives, in H. Miser and E. Quade (eds) Handbook of
Systems Analysis: Craft Issues and Procedural Choices. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.
Weimer, D. and A. Vining, A. 1992. Policy Analysis: Concepts and Practice. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Weiss, C. and M. Bucuvalas. 1980. Social Science Research and Decision-Making. New York: Columbia
University Press.
White, L. 1994. Policy analysis as discourse, Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 13(3): 50625.
Wildavsky, A. 1987. Speaking Truth to Power: The Art and Craft of Policy Analysis. New Brunswick, NJ:
Transaction Books.
Policy analytical styles
269
Part VI
Understanding the
decision-making process
21
Bounded rationality and
public policy decision-making
Bryan D. Jones and H.F. Thomas III
Underlying most approaches to the study of policy processes is a model of human choice.
1
This model
rests upon critical aspects of the cognitive and emotional architectures of decision-makers. The parti-
cular aspects of human psychology that informs the major approaches in policy studies dier, but all
share the common focus of requiring some assumptions about human nature. The Advocacy Coalition
Framework is based on an analysis of the attitudes, beliefs and values of coalition participants. Punc-
tuated Equilibrium Theory is based on shifts in the focus of collective attention, which requires an
individual choice model based on attention and short-term memory. The Institutional Analysis and
Development Framework centers on rational action by strategic actors, but with an understanding
of the limits of full rationality and a focus on the abilities of citizens in smaller associations to focus
on collective rather than individual benets. In each case, some elements of cognitive processing
beyond the maximization of goals assumed in the model of instrumental rationality, which is used
in economics and in public choice and neo-institutional analyses in political science, are present.
It is not much of a stretch to argue that the model underlying virtually all studies of policy
processes is bounded rationality. In this model, humans pursue goals, but they often fall prey to
mistakes in doing so. These mistakes are not simple, but complex results of human cognitive
architectures, and because the environments human decision-makers face is complex. Because
they are fundamentally related to human psychology, they are liable to be repeated. This approach
has the benet of keeping the traditional role of strategic action in the picture, but allows for
major deviations from optimum strategies.
In this chapter we review the genesis and development of bounded rationality and show how it has
inuenced the study of policy processes. Further, this chapter reviews the general research on bounded
rationality relevant to the policy-making process, focusing specically on bounded rationality as a
microfoundational underpinning for the study of public policy. We show how bounded rationality is
a superior microfoundation for most aspects of public policy, most particularly the prioritization of
policy problems, and show how the theory of preferences can be reconciled with bounded rationality.
Genesis and development of bounded rationality
Most scholars studying politics and government care little about the ne details of the specics of
human cognition; we are quite content to leave that to biologists, psychologists, and cognitive
273
scientists. What we cannot escape, however, is the need for some rm foundation capable of
linking human behavior to policy processes. That foundation must fulll three criteria: rst, it
must do no harm (it should not mislead); second, it must allow us to move between individual-
level processes and organizational processes in a more or less seamless manner; and third, it
should be ecient, in that it does not drag in specics of human behavior that are not needed
to understand the policymaking process.
As we show below, the model of bounded rationality, as initially articulated by Herbert A.
Simon and expanded by Simon, organizational theorists such as James A. March, and cognitive
scientists, especially Allen Newell, does that, and that foundation has been available since 1958.
Simon made the rst bold step toward the development of a model of decision-making
capable of aiding the understanding of collective choice in organizations with the publication of
Administrative Behavior (Simon 1945). Simon admits that the model articulated there consisted
largely of residual categories, and the positive characterization of the process of choice is very
incomplete (Simon 1977: xxix). By 1958, however, all the elements for producing an orga-
nizational and policy science based on a positive model of choice were in place. The basic elements
of that model have been conrmed and reconrmed by cognitive scientists in the laboratory
and by students of organizations and policy processes in the eld. Yet the approach, rather than
serving as the undisputed decisional foundation for modern social science, has engendered much
confusion and controversy. In political science, much time was spent ghting Simons approach
as too scientic for the humanistic study of politics; later the public choice approach simply
ignored the model. Economists went on counting angels on the heads of neoclassical pins
(Simon 1999: 113).
It is no accident that the behavioral model of choice came more or less directly from the beha-
vioral discipline of political science. Simon gives great credit to his participation as a student in
Charles Merriams behavioral revolution at the University of Chicagos Department of Political
Science in the 1930s (Simon 1996a: Chapter 4). The scientic tenets of political behavioralism
were strong on observation and quantication and not so strong on theory; the movement had
a clearly inductive avor. It demanded real-world observationMerriam wanted to make a
dierence in the conduct of public policy as well as in the conduct of scientic inquiry.
The tenets of bounded rationality
Simon developed bounded rationality as a critique of fully rational decision-making; what Simon
later termed the behavioral theory of choice was an attempt to state the positive aspects of a
theory of human choice based on scientic principles of observation and experiment rather than
the postulation and deduction characteristic of theoretical economics. We rst review the princi-
ples of bounded rationality, and then turn to the modern conceptions of the behavioral theory
of choice. The tenets of bounded rationality can be summarized in four straightforward prin-
ciples. While research in many elds of social science has advanced our understanding over the
years, the basic formulation occurred in Administrative Behavior (Simon 1945).
Principle of intended rationality. Simons model is enshrined in the crucial principle of intended
rationality. That is, it starts with the notion that people are goal-oriented, but often fail to accom-
plish this intention because of the interaction between aspects of their cognitive architectures
and the fundamental complexity of the environment they face (Simon 1977: xxvii; March
1994). Intellectually, this notion did not begin with Simon; it probably began with Vilfredo
Pareto. In Mind and Society he distinguished logical, illogical, and non-logical behavior (Pareto
1935).
2
Logical behavior is rational choice; it is ends-means reasoning where means are appro-
priate to goals. Illogical behavior is behavior not rooted in ends-means thinking; Pareto thought
Jones and Thomas
274
little human behavior (at least of interest to a social scientist) was illogical. Non-logical thought
involved sentiments and residues that could interfere with logical thinking. In a way, then,
we might term the principle of intended rationality the Pareto-Simon Principle.
The principle of intended rationality implies that we look at the goal-directed behavior of
people, and investigate the manner in which their cognitive and emotional constitutions con-
comitantly promote and interfere with goal-directed behavior. It implies, of course, that Ration-
ality does not determine behavior Instead, behavior is determined by the irrational and
nonrational elements that bound the area of rationality (Simon 1945: 241).
Bounded rationality is not simply a lack of calculational ability (see Lupia et al. 2000: 9).
Simon, March, and Newell all stressed that calculations were a minimal part of the diculty,
easily solved via notepads, calculating machines, or a bureau of accountants. Simon does write
extensively, however, about attention, emotion, habit, and memory, exploring the functionality
and dysfunctionality of these aspects of the architecture of human cognition. And it is true that
a prime component of the behavioral model of choice is diculty in planning and executing
long behavior sequences in complex environments (Jones 2001: 61). But this aspect of the
model should not be confused with calculational diculties.
Principle of adaptation. The principle of adaptation stems most directly from the studies of Allen
Newell and Herbert Simon in human problem-solving, and is best stated in Simons The Sciences
of the Articial (1996b). The claim is that most human behavior is explained by the nature of the
task environment. Given enough time, human thought takes on the shape of the tasks facing
itthat is, human thought is adaptive and basically rational. Simon put it this way: There are
only a few intrinsic characteristics of the inner environment of thinking beings that limit the
adaptation of thought to the shape of the problem environment. All else in thinking and problem-
solving behavior is learned and is subject to improvement (Simon 1996b: 54). From this
principle comes the inference that, in general, the more time one spends on a problem, the
more likely the decision-makers understanding of the problem will approximate the actual task
environment, and the limitations of human cognitive architecture fades (Newell 1990).
Psychologists stress the distinction between central and peripheral mental processing (Fiske
and Taylor 1991: 47580). Kuklinski and Quirk put it this way:
In central processing, used when attention and motivation are high, people employ more
mental resources, think more systematically, and allow data to shape inferences. In peripheral
processing, used when attention and motivation are low, they employ fewer resources, rely
on simple heuristics, and use top-down, stereotypic inferences.
(2000: 163)
Principle of uncertainty: One of the major contributions of decision theory has been to under-
stand uncertainty in light of the calculus of probabilities. We speak of expected utility and
think of outcomes as following a probability distribution. Unfortunately this does not tell the
full story of uncertainty in human decision-making. Students of human choice in real-world or
in laboratory situations again and again nd that people have great diculties in working with
probabilities, assessing risk, and making inferences where uncertainty is involved. Indeed, a whole
eld of endeavor has emerged that studies the factors responsible for perceptions of risk; clearly
these perceptions are not just rooted in nature but also involve human psychology.
An underlying tenet of bounded rationality from its early years centered on how human cog-
nitive architecture interacted with an uncertain world; bounded rationalists saw uncertainty as
far more fundamental to choice than the probability calculus implied (March 1994). If ones
understanding of the causal factors involved in a problem is hazy or ambiguous, then the
Bounded rationality
275
uncertainty is not contained, but reverberates through the entire thought process. If one is uncertain
about how to specify outcomes, then one must also be uncertain about how to specify ones
utility function. Simon termed this diculty the design problem to denote that the fundamental
nature of specifying a problem-space within which to solve problems.
Principle of trade-os. People have a very dicult time with trading o one goal against another
in a choice (Slovak 1990; Tetlock 2000). The classical economic model depicts trade-osas
smooth indierence curves, and modern rational choice theory oers little new in the theore-
tical study of trade-os. The rst behavioral tool for understanding trade-os was Simons notion
of satiscing. His idea that administrative man”—an individual in an organizationchooses
alternatives that are good enough has led critics to claim that the notion is just a poverty-
stricken version of maximization (Lupia et al. 2000: 9). However, if one adds information and
decision-making cost constraints to choice, this will not cause bounded rationality to dissolve
into maximizing behavior. Satiscing describes the cognitive diculties people have with trade-
os. Because of the operation of limited attention spans, people work on goals sequentially. As a
consequence, trade-os among goals is very dicult. The response, argues Simon, is for people
to set aspiration levels on the goals they wish to achieve. If a choice is good enough (that
is, if it exceeds aspiration levels) on all goals, then it is chosen.
Other models of choice among multiple goals have been developed, including the lexicographic
strategy (choose the strategy that maximizes gain on the most salient goal and ignore the rest) and
elimination by aspects (use a lexicographic strategy unless there is a tie among alternatives; then
and only then use a second goal to break the tie). In an important particular, people have consider-
able diculty in trading o benets against losses, something that standard utility maximization
theory treats as straightforward (Kahneman and Tversky 1979).
The behavioral theory of choice
While great strides have been made in recent years by psychologists and behavioral economists
studying choices in the controlled arrangements of the laboratory, only serious eld study can
indicate how real choices are made in the structured yet dynamic environments of real choice
situations. Bounded rationality and the behavioral theory of choice came from organization theory;
indeed, March (1994) once noted that breakthroughs in the study of human cognition were
likely to come from a study of organizations. Laboratory ndings of systematic violations of
principles of behavior based on expected utility calculation are dramatic and widespread (Camerer
1998; Camerer and Thaler 1995; Thaler 1991, 1992), yet this says little about choice in the eld
where behavior can be adaptive and responsive to multiple feedback streams (Laitin 1999). As a
consequence of the single-minded focus on experimental design and rejecting various tenets of
expected utility, behavioral economists have termed their own literature the anomalies litera-
ture (Thaler 1988, 1992). Several political scientists have criticized experimental psychology
and the behavioral economics literature for its seeming ad hoc nature, building ndings experi-
mental eect by experimental eect. David Laitin (1999) notes that in everyday actions people
are adaptive, avoiding many of the traps set for them in experiments.
Much recent debate has centered on the viability of expected utility theory given the laboratory
ndings. This debate is to a large extent misplaced, because since the late 1950s a full model of
choice, the behavioral model of choice, has been available. It avoids the anomalies problem,
is parsimonious, and yields more accurate predictions on aggregate choices such as we observe
in studying policy processes than does comprehensive rationality.
Bounded rationality points to the limits of rational adaptation; behavioral choice theory
provides a body of literature that shows how human choice works. As we noted above, bounded
Jones and Thomas
276
rationality and the associated behavioral theory of choice are open-ended; we do not know
everything about human choice and we learn more every year. But we know a lot, and we
know enough to specify the outlines of what aspects of human cognition must be incorporated
to formulate a general theory of human choice. We would cite the following:
1 Long-term memory: humans learn by encoding experience (direct or secondary) into rules
that specify action to be taken in response to categories of stimuli.
2 Short-term memory: human cognitive capacities include a front end that extracts features
from the world around them, categorizes them as relevant or irrelevant (in the former
case, they become stimuli) and prioritizes them.
3 Emotions set priorities: in an initial encounter with a choice situation, the major mechanism
for weighting the relevance of stimuli is emotion.
4 Central versus peripheral processing: when attention and emotion are aroused, information
processing shifts toward problem analysis and search. When they are not, the decision-maker
relies on prepackaged solutions.
5 The preparation-search trade-o: if the front-end system indicates a need for action, humans can
take two paths: draw upon previously prepared and stored rules specifying how to respond
to the category that the stimulus has been placed in, or search for new responses.
6 Identication: People identify emotionally with the previously prepared solutions that they
have encoded in memory. They tend to become emotionally attached to their current reper-
toire of encoded solutions, even as the problems they face evolve. As a consequence, reliance
on prepared solutions dominates search.
Heuristics
Heuristic decision-making plays a key role in most of the basic theories of policy processes. The
notion was a critical component of the problem-solving studies of Newell and Simon (1972).
Heuristics, or shortcuts, are strategies that people employ to cope with the bounds of their
cognitive architectures. Jon Bendor (2010: 1) notes that political science harbors two orienta-
tions toward heuristics. On the one hand some political scientists report that decision-makers
often manage to do reasonably well’—even in complex tasksdespite their cognitive limitations.
He puts Lindbloms theory of muddling through (1959) and Wildavskys (1964) budgetary
studies in this category. On the other hand, in the work of other political scientists, the emphasis
is on how people make mistakes even in simple tasks, an orientation common in much of
psychology (where the terms heuristics and biases often go together), and in studies of voting
behavior in political science. Newell and Simon saw that both facets were operative at once. For
example, in their experiments, when people found that a problem-solving strategy would not
work, they found another through trial and error search. In contrast, when presented with a
problem logically similar to the one they just addressed, many went back to the failed rst-choice
strategy of the earlier problem.
A critical component of the problem-solving approach of Newell and Simon is the separation
of problem from solution spaces (Newell 1990). Most decision-making occurs without much
analysis of the problem-space. Decision-makers assume that they know the dimensions of a
problem and apply a known solution from memory. Basically, decision-makers can either search
memory for a prepackaged solution, or they can engage in search for new solutions. Because it
is less costly to use a prepackaged solution from memory, this is the route most typically taken.
The separation of problem-space and solution-space is a fundamental component of the
policy process eld. The garbage can theory of organizational decision-making rests on this
Bounded rationality
277
distinction (Cohen et al. 1972), as does the work of Kingdon (1984) on agenda-setting and
public policy. In these studies, solutions and problems are not linked causally, but are unied by
collective attention. When a problem emerges, solutions are likely to be attached without prior
analysis of the problem-space.
Fernandes and Simon (1999) applied the process-tracing methodology initially developed by
Newell and Simon (1972) in their problem-solving experiments to the complex and ill-structured
problems characteristic of policy issues. Fernandes and Simon wondered if the professional iden-
tications among doctors led to dierent problem-solving strategies. They found a heavy reli-
ance on what they termed a Know ! Recommend strategy among many participants that
hindered their use of information in problem-solving.
Ill-structured problems lend themselves to the application of prepackaged solution sets that
participants bring to the problem-solving enterprise. These prepackaged solution sets (Jones
and Bachelor 1993) can derive from ideology, or professional identication, or current organi-
zational practices. Whatever its source, it suggests a major limitation in one of the fundamental
principles of bounded rationality: what we termed the principle of adaptation above. But it oper-
ates away from comprehensive rationality, and it cannot be construed as some sort of heuristic
shortcut for limiting search costs. It may be in moderation, but current studies suggest that it is
overused to the point of interfering with adaptation. This is an important nding capable of
being linked to collective decision-making (see Brown 2001).
The Know ! Recommend strategy has powerful implications for public policy. In many cases
in which attention and emotion are aroused, people may insist on rigidly reaching for old solutions
to problems, regardless of their applicability to the current issue. Hinich and Munger (1994)
note that ideologies organize the political (and policy) world, so it is not surprising that solutions
more amenable to a particular ideological world view are viewed as appropriate, even when
evidence shows them to have failed in the past. Jones and Williams (2008), who studied tax
policies, and Schrad (2010), who studied alcohol control, show in two very dierent policy-
making situations the role of bad policy ideas in leading to policy failures. Bad policy ideas are
dened as those resulting in a policy that isnt working, hasnt ever worked, and runs the risk
of causing great damage (Schrad 2010: 208). Yet, the committed activists in both cases rushed
to claim eects for policies that had already been discredited.
This commitment to prior solutions, based on cognitive and emotional identication, pro-
vide an important limit to the principle of adaptation. In such cases, much central processing
eort is expended, but most of it goes to justifying previously employed solutions a condition
known as motivated reasoning (Kunda 1990; Lodge and Taber 2000).
Organizations
The six aspects of human cognition, and their inuences on heuristic decision-making, obviously
do not deal with every aspect of human behavior that could inuence the policy process, but
they cover much ground, and lay the basis for a general behavioral theory of choice in organizations
and institutions. Most importantly, they form a basis for scaling up the behavior of humans to
organizations and policy processes. One of the continuing challenges for those scholars working
in the bounded rationality tradition is the movement from models of human decision-making
to those characterizing organizations and interactions of organizations in policy-making systems.
While organizations clearly free humans by extending their capacities to achieve goals, being
human inventions they also fall prey to aspects of human cognitive architecture in predictable
ways. Major aspects of the behavioral theory of organization parallel major facets of the behavioral
theory of human choice:
Jones and Thomas
278
1 Organizational memory: organizations encode experience into rules, routines, and standard
operating procedures that specify action to be taken in response to categories of stimuli.
2 Agenda-setting: organizational capacities include a front end that extracts features from the
world, categorizes them as relevant or irrelevant (in the former case, they become stimuli)
and prioritizes them. Agenda-setting in organizations parallels the short-term and attention
bottleneck (Simons term) aicting human cognition.
3 Parallel processing: a major way that organizations expand human capacities is the ability to
process information in parallel. By decentralizing and delegating, organizations can process
multiple streams of input simultaneously (Simon 1983; Jones 1994). This organizational
strategy presupposes considerable peripheral processing relying on preprogrammed solutions.
4 Serial processing: the search for new solutions is activated only when previously prepared
solutions encoded in organizational routines are judged to be inadequate. Then organizations
move from peripheral to central processing (or from parallel processing to serial processing).
5 Emotional contagion: in policy-making, emotional commitment and contagion are crucial
elements in mobilizing for major initiatives. Moving from parallel to serial processing is
invariably accompanied by emotional arousal by participants (Jones 1994).
6 Identication: people identify emotionally as well as cognitively with the organizations they
participate in, or even parts of an organization, which Simon termed sub-goal identication.
Organizational identication is a great resource for leaders. Patriotism or religious zeal or
even pride in performing their jobs can push people to actions that would be unthinkable
in a calm cost-benet analysis. But it also can make it dicult for leaders to shift strategies
when they nd it necessary to do so.
The relationships between organizational decision-making and individual decision-making
are not metaphorical; they are causal (Jones 2001). One cannot really understand how organi-
zations operate without a strong sense of how individuals process information and make decisions.
As a consequence, a rm scientic foundation for policy studies must be rooted in a behavioral
approach to organizations (see Green and Thompson 2001).
Information-processing
A political science relying on behavioral choice theory will invariably be drawn toward the
study of information-processing and problem-solving. It will be less focused on questions of
preferences and equilibria. The nature of the behavioral assumptions inuences the choice of
topics for study. It is not that preferences and equilibria are not interesting subjects, well worthy
of study. It is that they have been attended to far out of proportion to their explanatory power.
The focus on equilibrium processes has as its underpinning a narrow conception of choice,
based on the notion of xed preferences that lead actors to choose strategies that maximize
those preferences. It is often found in modern studies of legislatures and public agencies. Early
students of public administration were concerned with how organizations and democracy were
intermeshed, whether a pluralism of interests generated by Roosevelts alphabet soup of reg-
ulatory agencies could t with a single overhead control model of democracy. However, much
recent scholarship has relied heavily on the principal agent approach, in which the issue for a
principal, such as collectively acting legislature, involves controlling the actions of a delegate,
such as a bureaucratic agency, which receives delegated authority. This has resulted in a public
administration that has overly focused on the single issue of controland control solely through
formal incentives (primarily punishment). The rich insights of behavioral choice have devolved
into a discredited Skinnerian psychologythe incentive controls the behavior. It is ironic that
Bounded rationality
279
Skinners study of pigeons and mice and the comprehensive rationality of economics both lead
to the same impoverished model of human choice: only formal incentives matter.
The adoption of an overly limited model of human behavior has led to inadequate devel-
opment of other aspects of bureaucratic behavior. Models based on principal agency have pro-
blems in conrmation (see, for example, Brehm and Gates 1997; Balla 1998; Carpenter 1996;
Balla and Wright 2001). Brehm and Gates (1997: 578) comment that the primary contribution
is our nding of the overwhelming importance of attributes of the organizational culture in
determining subordinates levels of compliance. Miller (1992) has shown the critical importance
of organizational culture as well.
In addition, public bureaucracies are important in the process of providing and interpreting
information for the legislative branch. Because the environment of policy-making is both
uncertain and ambiguous, delegating information processing to public agencies is common
and necessary in legislatures. One cannot control what one does not understand (Workman
et al. 2009).
Attention-driven choice in public policy
The basis for the behavioral model of choice is the processing of information. Information is not
predened or packaged; rather it is often vague, ambiguous, and most importantly, is generated
from multiple sources. The receiver of the information is as important as the sender (Jones 2001:
Chapter 4). In modern complex environments, neither individuals nor organizations respond
simply to stimuli. They must attend, prioritize, and select an appropriate response. As a consequence,
there is no clear, one-to-one mapping between potential stimuli or events and actions.
A major key to understanding information-processing in people and in organizations is the
allocation of attention. In his study of municipal budgeting, John Crecine (1969) noted that city
agencies developed attention rules that indicated what aspects of the environment ought to be
monitored for indicators of change that could need addressing. These rules did not tell the
agency what to do; only what to attend to. Similarly Jones (1980) found in a study of Chicago
building code enforcement that informal norms generally supplanted the complexities of the code,
but that supervisors occasionally sent out signals to eld inspectors that all violations were to be
recorded in potentially hot cases. Dierential code enforcement resulted as a consequence of
these attention rules. Research by Armstrong et al. (2003) indicates that media attention to disease
is not simply related to mortality and morbidity of disease, and this attention seems to mediate
output indicators, such as investment in cures and related science.
Attention is dierent from any other resource type variable because one cannot allocate it
proportionally to ones priorities at any one instance. Attention is selective; select one aspect of
an environment for study and inattention must be paid to the rest of the environment. Attention is
partially under the control of a decision-maker, but cognitively we possess no comprehensive
system for monitoring when enough attention has been devoted to a topic. As a consequence,
shifts in attentiveness are in large part hostage to emotional arousal. Because attention shifts are
governed by emotion, they are unavoidably disjointed. Since, in many cases, the devotion of other
resources follows attention, past decisions are a residue of past allocations of attention. They
may or may not be consistentgreat inconsistencies in choices are a result of attention.
The allocation of attention strongly aects the manner in which individuals or organizations
prioritize problems for action. Because attention is disjointed and episodic, so is problem-
prioritization. Because problems are prioritized in policy-making systems through attention, and
attention is disjointed, policy-making is disjointed and episodic, not necessarily related to the
severity of indicators. Similarly attention to solutions given that a problem has been prioritized
Jones and Thomas
280
is governed by attentionoftentimes directed at solutions that have been used before, even
when they have been unsuccessful in the past (Jones and Williams 2008; Schrad 2010).
Disproportionate information-processing and institutional friction
So far, we have addressed the scaling up of the model of bounded rationality to the level of the
single organization. Now we will need to address full policy-making systemsthose composed
of interacting organizations. The key to this scaling up is the notion of disproportionate information-
processing (Jones 2001). A policy-making system may be considered fully adaptive to the extent
that it responds appropriately to the information coming in from its environment. Yet systems
comprised of boundedly rational decision-makers are not capable of responding proportionately
a direct implication of attention-driven choice and other mechanisms rooted in bounded
rationality (Jones and Baumgartner 2005). The result is episodic policy-making as policy-makers
shift from addressing one set of problems to a dierent set.
Research focusing on explaining the episodic nature of policy change over time cites two
mechanisms: institutional friction and positive feedback. Disproportionate information-processing
in policy-making systems stems from a continual interaction between the conservative forces of
policy stasis governed by negative feedback processes and the cascades of policy action governed
by a collective sense of urgency among policy-makers. Jones and Baumgartner (2005) examine
how government attends to, interprets, and prioritizes diverse incoming information streams
within a boundedly rational framework. In their approach, human cognitive processing interacts
with policy-making institutions to determine responses to incoming information.
In the model, institutional friction results from the interaction of two kinds of costs: decision
costs, which are those imposed by the operation of institutional rules (such as those required by
the constitutional system of divided powers in American federal government) and cognitive costs
associated with boundedly rational decision-makers operating in a complex and changing
environment (Jones et al. 2003; Jones and Baumgartner 2005). Baumgartner et al. further dene
the mechanism:
Institutional friction in the form of sunk costs, long-term budgetary commitments, identi-
cation with means rather than ends, and bureaucratic inertia makes it hard for govern-
ments to reduce attention to issues that are improving just as it inhibits them from paying
attention to problems that are just emerging.
(2009: 608)
Empirical results in the US and elsewhere show that increased friction from these sources lead
to more pronounced patterns of overreaction and underattention in policy-making. If friction is
understood as strong resistance to change over time (and not as the static concept of gridlock),
major shifts in policy can occur when it is overcome (Jones and Baumgartner 2005). This generally
occurs when errors accumulate”—that is, when the system is far enough out of balance with
its environment that it lurches forward.
Disproportionate information-processing and positive feedback
The friction approach to incorporating disproportionate information processing into a model of
policy change is essentially passivepressures build up and cause attention to shift from one
problem to another, which is then addressed. This resistance is in part a function of cognitive
limitations and heuristic decision-making, so it incorporates elements of bounded rationality. A
Bounded rationality
281
second aspect of disproportionality, based on positive feedback, is active. Positive feedback
operates to amplify a process rather than to damp it down (as is the case for negative feedback
processes). Positive feedback mechanisms can lead to contagion eects and the breakdowns of
control mechanisms, and are well known in both natural and social sciences.
Well-ordered and equilibrium processes always involve negative feedback systems. The wisdom
of crowds argument (Surowiecki 2004) claims that decisions or judgments made through the
aggregation of individual choices often leads to accurate and rational conclusions. So it seems
that rational decisions in systems stem from averaging out the individual errors. The theory is
based on independent decision-making, each actor making his or her own judgment. Unfor-
tunately, communication and interaction among individuals can easily lead to the rapid break-
down of the theory, as mimicking can bias outcomes. Experimental evidence in sociology conrms
this argument, suggesting that the breakdown of the wisdom of crowds eect can be undermined
through social inuence among actors (Lorenz et al. 2010).
A weight-guessing game, perhaps involving a carnival crowd oering suggestions on a
particular hogs size, oers an illustrative example. Here, the independence of individuals and a
lack of communication would likely yield a close prediction of the hogs actual size at the
average (Galton 1907). Yet if carnival attendees are allowed to communicate and discuss
their potential guesses while they examine the hog and place their bets, a bounded ration-
ality microfoundation would predict considerable deviation from the actual weight of the
hog as cue-taking and information cascades ensue. A propensity to mimic neighbors and
authority gures, take cues to reduce decisions costs, and the cascade of information (say from
one side of the hog to the other) would generate a set of guesses subject to uctuation, bias, and
inaccuracy.
This ampli cation mechanism is found in political bandwagons, in fads of fashion, and in
nancial markets, bubbles and crashes (Mackay 1841). Shiller (2005) discusses the psychology of
herding, or irrational exuberance, among investors whereby price increases beget further price
increases in a consecutive loop of speculative condence. Sornette (2004) and Youssefmir et al.
(1998) focus on how unchecked feedback can generate asset-pricing bubbles and cause their
subsequent collapse. Beyond nance, examples of positive feedback and cascades abound, and
include: city growth (Gabaix 1999), the superstardom of pop musicians (Chung and Cox 1994),
fashion trends and cultural change (Bikhchandani et al. 1992), website links (Barbási 2002),
restaurant popularity (Becker 1991), standing ovations (Miller and Page 2004), and credit for
scientic ndings (Merton 1968), among others.
3
Political scientists address feedback mechanisms in research spanning the discipline (see Baum-
gartner and Jones 2002 for a review). For example, scholars of the news media (Boydstun 2008),
interest group behavior (Baumgartner and Leech 2001; Leech et al. 2005; Halpin 2011), agenda-
setting (Baumgartner and Jones 1993), state-level diusion of innovations (Boushey 2011),
decision-making in Congress (Kingdon 1977; Matthews and Stimson 1975), presidential primaries
(Bartels 1988), collective action (Lohmann 1994) and social movements (Chong 1991) all discuss
the amplifying role of positive feedback in terms of cue-taking, bandwagons, cascades, contagion,
and momentum related to various political phenomena.
4
Linking these two mechanisms of positive feedback and institutional friction, Jones and
Baumgartner (2005) argue that cascades may be critically important to our understanding of
policy outcomes. They describe a gap between a distribution of real-world budget outlays and
another predicted by their friction model, and conclude that friction alone does not fully
explain budget distributions. They see positive feedback as a likely candidate for the dierence,
and suggest that it may turn out that cascades are the key to understanding how friction is
overcome in policy systems (ibid. 139).
Jones and Thomas
282
Bounded rationality and stochastic processes
In rational models of action, people act proportionately to the information they receive. They
attend to everything simultaneously and make trade-oseortlessly. They avoid punctuated
outputs except where inputs are disjointed and episodic, or where rules do not allow for the
easy adjustment of outputs to inputs. Organizations composed of rational participants respond
directly and eciently to information discounted by costs. Organizations composed of bound-
edly rational participants cannot avoid punctuated outputs, because they cannot adjust their
behaviors to incoming information of any degree of complexity.
Bounded rationality and behavioral choice lead to predictions about policy outcomes that
imply that organizational outputs will be disjointed and episodic regardless of rst, the input
stream and second, the cost structure of the organization. It is clear that decision costs in the policy-
making process can cause disjoint outputs. For example, in the American system of separated
powers, considerable changes in the preferences of policy-makers can occur without producing
policy change because of the need to assemble majorities in all responsible branches (Hammond
and Miller 1987). If we were able to discount these decision costs bounded rationality implies
that disjointed and episodic behavior would still occur. Examination of a number of dierent
distributions of outcomes from political institutions and the policy-making process in the US,
nds that, regardless of the institutional cost structure, outputs are punctuated (Jones et al. 2003;
Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
Because of the disproportionate information processing described above, the traditional
approaches to analysis based on point prediction and regression analysis can be misleading. It is
too dicult (and perhaps meaningless) to try to tie a particular event of ow of information to a
particular outcome. Students of organizational processes have begun to make use of stochastic
process approaches, in which eorts are made to understand the processes underlying an entire
distribution of outputs rather than a particular response to a policy innovation or other change
(Padgett 1980, 1981; Jones et al. 2003). Disproportionate information processing implies lepto-
kurtic (fat-tailed) distributions of output changes (such as annual changes in a governments
budget) regardless of the input distribution. Because of the phenomenon of disproportionate
information-processing, decision-makers are forever underreacting to stimuli that require action,
and overreacting with cascading behavior when the problem is fully recognized (Jones 2001;
Jones et al. 2003). The underreacting results in the slender peak of the leptokurtic distribution,
while the fat tails indicate the rapid changes that occur in the overreacting stage.
Concluding comments
Psychologists, neuroscientists, behavioral economists, and students of political behavior have
accumulated a great amount of information since the studies of Newell and Simon 40 years ago. Not
only have these studies shown where failures in human rationality exist, they have also found
adaptive capacities in human action, even in complex modern environments (Gigerenzer and
Goldstein 1996; Gigerenzer 2001). In general, while the tenets of cognitive rationality have been
repeatedly undermined by these studies, those of bounded rationality have fared much better.
Policymaking systems are comprised of multiple organizations, each of which incorporates
numerous human actors. In order to serve as a microfoundation for understanding policy pro-
cess, we need to avoid getting overly consumed by the details of human cognition (see Bendor
2010: 447 for a discussion). What are the important elements of a microfoundation for the
study of policy processes, one rooted in the scientic and empirical ndings on human cognation
and information-processing?
Bounded rationality
283
In this chapter we have discussed those elements of human cognition that we see as critical
for policy process scholars to understand, and shown how those elements may be scaled up to
the levels of the organization and the policy-making system. While models of strategic inter-
action among rational actors are (relatively) easy to scale up, the same cannot be said for a more
realistic empirically based cognitive foundation. As a consequence, less eort has been expended
in achieving this scaling up than we think desirable.
Notes
1 This chapter draws heavily on Jones (2003).
2 Our thanks to Fred Thompson for drawing this link.
3 See Schelling 1978 for an early overview as well as Miller and Page 2007 for a recent review of positive
feedback in complex adaptive systems.
4 See also Pierson (2000) for a discussion of increasing returns in political processes.
Bibliography
Alt, James E., Margaret Levi and Elinor Ostrom. 1999. Competition and Cooperation: Conversations With
Nobelists About Economics and Political Science. New York, Russell Sage Foundation.
Armstrong, Elizabeth M., Dan Carpenter and Marie E. Hojnacki. 2003. Whose deaths matter? Attention to
disease in the public arena, paper presented at the Conference on the Politics of Biomedical Research,
Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Aairs. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University, March.
Balla, Steven J. 1998. Administrative procedures and political control of the bureaucracy, American Political
Science Review 92: 66373.
——and John R. Wright. 2001. Interest groups, advisory committees, and congressional oversight,
American Journal of Political Science 45: 79981.
Barabási, Albert-László. 2002. Linked. New York: Penguin.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
——and Bryan D. Jones, eds. 2002. Policy Dynamics. Chicago: University Press of Chicago.
——and Beth L. Leech. 2001. Issue niches and policy bandwagons: Patterns of interest group involvement
in national politics, Journal of Politics 63: 1191 213.
——, Christian Breunig, Christoer Green-Pedersen, Bryan D. Jones, Peter B. Mortensen, Michiel
Nuytemans and Stefaan Walgrave. 2009. Punctuated equilibrium in comparative perspective, American
Journal of Political Science 53(3): 60320.
Becker, Gary S. 1991. A note on restaurant pricing and other examples of social inuence on price,
Journal of Political Economy 99: 110916.
Bendor, Jonathan. 2010. Bounded Rationality and Politics. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Bikhchandani, Sushil, David Hirshleifer and Ivo Welch. 1992. A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and
cultural change as informational cascades, Journal of Political Economy 100: 9921026.
Boushey, Graeme. 2011. Policy Diusion Dynamics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Boydstun, Amber E. 2008. How policy issues become front-page news,
PhD dissertation, Penn State University.
Brehm, John and
Scott Gates. 1993. Donut shops and speed traps: Evaluating models of supervision on
police behavior, American Journal of Political Science 37: 55581.
—— 1997. Working, Shirking, and Sabotage. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Brown, Steven R. 2001. Structural and functional information: A cautionary note to Fernandes and Simon,
paper presented at the annual meeting of the Society for the Policy Sciences New Haven, Connecticut.
Camerer, Colin F. 1998. Behavioral economics and nonrational organizational decision making in Jennifer
J. Halpern and Robert N. Stern (eds) Debating Rationality. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
——and Richard F. Thaler. 1995. Ultimat ums, dictators and manners, Journal of Economic Perspectives 9: 20919.
Carpenter, Daniel. 1996. Adaptive signal processing, hierarchy, and budgetary control in federal regulation,
American Political Science Review 90: 283302.
Chong, Dennis. 1991. Collective Action and the Civil Rights Movement. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Chung, Kee H. and Raymond A.K. Cox. 1994. A stochastic model of superstardom: An application of
the Yule distribution, Review of Economics and Statistics 76(4): 7715.
Jones and Thomas
284
Cohen, Michael D., James G. March and Johann P. Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational
choice, Administrative Science Quarterly 17: 125.
Crecine, John. 1969. Government Problem-Solving. Chicago: Rand-McNally.
Fernandes, Ronald and Herbert A. Simon. 1999. A study of how individuals solve complex and ill-structured
problems, Policy Sciences 32: 22545.
Fiske, Susan and Shelly Taylor. 1991. Social Cognition. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Galton, Francis. 1907. Vox populi, Nature 75: 4501.
Gabaix, X. 1999. Zipfs Law and the growth of cities, American Economic Review 89(2): 12932.
Gigerenzer, Gerd. 2001. The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
——and Daniel G. Goldstein. 1996. Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality,
Psychological Review 103: 65069.
Granovetter, M.S. 1973. The strength of weak ties, American Journal of Sociology 78(6): 136080.
—— 1978. Threshold models of collective behavior, American Journal of Sociology 83(6): 1420.
Green, Mart T. and Fred Thompson. 2001. Organizational process models of budgeting, in John Bartle
(ed.) Research in Public Administration: Evolving Theories of Budgeting. San Francisco: JAI Press.
Halpin. D. 2011. Organized interests and cascades of attention: Unpacking policy bandwagon
dynamics, Governance, 24(2); 20530.
Hammond, Thomas and Gary J. Miller. 1987. The core of the constitution, American Political Science
Review 81: 115574.
Hinich,
Melvin and Michael
Munger. 1994. Ideology and the Theory of Political Choice. Ann Arbor, MI:
University of Michigan Press.
Jones, Bryan D. 1980. Service Delivery in the City: Citizen Demand and Bureaucratic Response. New York: Longman.
—— 1994. Reconceiving Decision-Making in Democratic Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—— 2001. Politics and the Architecture of Choice. Chicago: University of Chicago.
—— 2003. Bounded rationality and political science: Lessons from public administration and public
policy, Journal of Public Administration and Theory 13(4): 395412.
——and Lynn W. Bachelor. 1993. The Sustaining Hand: Community Leadership and Corporate Power. Lawrence,
KS: University Press of Kansas.
——and Frank R. Baumgartner. 2005. The Politics of Attention: How Government Prioritizes Problems. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
——and Walter Williams. 2008. The Politics of Bad Ideas. New York: Pearson Longman.
——, Tracy Sulkin and Heather Larsen. 2003. Punctuations in political institutions, American Political
Science Review 97: 15169.
——, Heather Larsen-Price and John Wilkerson. 2009. Representation and American governing institutions,
Journal of Politics 71: 27790.
Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision-making under risk,
Econometrica 47: 26391.
Kingdon, John W. 1977. Models of legislative voting, The Journal of Politics, 39(3): 56395.
—— 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Kuklinski, James and Paul Quirk. 2000. Reconsidering the rational public: Cognition, heuristics and mass
opinion, in Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins and Samuel L. Popkin (eds) Elements of Reason.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kunda, Ziva. 1990. The case for motivated reasoning, Psychological Bulletin 108: 48098.
Laitin,
David. 1999. Identity choice
under conditions of uncertainty: reections on Seltens dualist meth-
odology, in James Alt, Margaret Levi and Elinor Ostrom (eds) Competition and Cooperation: Conversations with
Nobelists about Economics and Political Science. New York: Russell Sage.
Leech, Beth L., Frank R. Baumgartner, Timothy La Pira and Nicolas A. Semanko. 2005. Drawing lob-
byists to Washington: Government activity and interest-group mobilization, Political Research Quarterly
58(1) (March): 1930.
Lindblom, Charles E. 1959. The science of muddling through”’, Public Administration Review 19(2): 7988.
Lodge, Milton and Charles Taber. 2000. Three steps toward a theory of motivated political reasoning,in
Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins and Samuel L. Popkin (eds) Elements of Reason. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 183213.
Lohmann, Susanne. 1994. The dynamics of informational cascades: The Monday demonstrations in
Leipzig, East Germany, 19891991, World Politics 47: 42101
Lorenz, Jan, Hekio Rauhut, Frank Schweitzer, and Dirk Helbing. 2010. How social movements can
undermine the wisdom of crowd eect, PNAS 108(22): 90209025.
Bounded rationality
285
Lupia, Arthur, Mathew D. McCubbins and Samuel L. Popkin. 2000. Beyond rationality: Reason and the
study of politics, in Arthur Lupia, Mathew D. McCubbins and Samuel L. Popkin (eds) Elements of
Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mackay, Charles. 1841. Extraordinary Popular Delusions and the Madness of Crowds . New York: Broadway.
March, James 1994. A Primer on Decision-Making. New York: The Free Press.
——and Herbert A. Simon. 1958. Organizations. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Matthews, D.R. and James A. Stimson. 1975. Yeas and nays: Normal decision-making in the US House
of Representatives, New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Merton, Robert K. 1968. The Matthew eect in science, Science 159: 5663.
Miller, G.J. 1992. Managerian Dilemmas: The Political Economy of Hierarchy. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 216333.
Miller, John H. and Scott E. Page. 2004. The standing ovation problem, Complexity 9: 816.
——and Scott E. Page. 2007. Complex Adaptive Systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Mladenka, Kenneth. 1978. Rules, service equity and distributional decisions, Social Science Quarterly
59: 192202.
Newell, Allen.1990. Unied Theories of Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
——and Herbert A. Simon. 1972. Human Problem Solving. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Padgett, John F. 1980. Bounded rationality in budgetary research, American Political Science Review 74: 35472.
—— 1981. Hierarchy and ecological control in federal budgetary decision making, American Journal of
Sociology 87: 75128.
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1935. Mind and Society. New York: Kessinger Publishing.
Pierson, Paul. 2000. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, The
American Political
Science Review 94(2): 25167.
Robinson,
Scott. 2003. Punctuated equilibrium, bureaucratization, and budgetary changes in schools,
paper presented at the Midwest Political Science Association, Chicago, April 46.
Schelling, Thomas. C. 1978. Micromotives and Macrobehaviour, New York: Norton.
Schrad, Mark Lawrence. 2010. The Political Power of Bad Ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shiller, R.J. 2005. Irrational Exuberance. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Simon, Herbert A. 1945. Administrative Behavior. New York: Macmillan.
—— 1977. The logic of heuristic decision-making, in R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds) Models of
Discovery. Boston: D. Reidel.
—— 1983. Reason in Human Aairs. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
—— 1996a. Models of My Life, MIT edn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
—— 1996b. The Sciences of the Articial, 3rd edn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
—— 1999. The potlatch between political science and economics, in James Alt, Margaret Levi and
Elinor Ostrom (eds) Conict and Cooperation: Conversations with Nobelists about Economics and Political Science.
New York: Russel Sage.
Slovak, Paul. 1990. Choice, in Daniel N. Osherson and Edward E. Smith (eds) Thinking: An Invitation to
Cognitive Science, vol. 3. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Sornette, D. 2004. Why Stock Markets Crash. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Surowiecki, James. 2004. The Wisdom of Crowds. New York: Doubleday.
Thaler, Richard H. 1991. Quasi Rational Economics. New York: Russell Sage.
—— 1988. Anomalies: the ultimatum game, Journal of Economic Perspectives 2: 195206.
—— 1992. The Winners Curse: Paradoxes and Anomalies of Economic Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Tetlock, Philip. 2000. Coping with trade-os: Psychological constraints and political implications,i
n
Arthur Lupia, Mathew
D. McCubbins and Samuel L. Popkin (eds) Elements of Reason. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
True, James L. 2000. Avalanches and incrementalism: Making policy and budgets in the United States,
American Review of Public Administration 30: 318.
——, Bryan D. Jones and Frank R. Baumgartner. 1999. Punctuated equilibrium theory, in Paul Sabatier
(ed.) Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Tversky, Amos. 1972. Elimination by aspects: A theory of choice, Psychological Review 79: 28199.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1964. The Politics of the Budgetary Process. Boston: Little, Brown.
Workman, Samuel, Bryan D. Jones and Ashley E. Jochim. 2009. Information processing and policy
dynamics, Policy Studies Journal 37(1): 7592.
Youssefmir, Michael, Bernadro A. Huberman, and Tad Hogg. 1998. Bubbles and market crashes, Computational
Economics 12(2): 97114.
Jones and Thomas
286
22
Incrementalism
Michael Hayes
Incrementalism is a pluralistic process of policy-making involving mutual adjustment among multi-
ple actors who typically disagree on objectives and start o from very dierent conceptions of the
problem at hand. Incomplete knowledge and time constraints limit attention to alternatives dier-
ing only marginally (incrementally) from previous policies. The necessity for bargaining and com-
promise virtually assures incremental outcomes. Major policy change will occur gradually, if at all, as
experience with policies generates demands for modication or expansion in subsequent policy cycles.
Charles Lindblom advanced incrementalism as both an explanatory and a prescriptive model
of the policy process (Dahl and Lindblom 1953; Lindblom 1959, 1965, 1979; Braybrooke and
Lindblom 1963). In his view, incrementalism provides the best explanation of the policy process
because it is the best way to make policy, allowing policy-makers to proceed when the rational-
comprehensive ideal has broken down.
The rst section of this chapter will review how rational decision-making breaks down in
most cases and how incrementalism departs from the rational method on all points. The second
section will identify some circumstances under which nonincremental policy change may occur.
The third section will explore whether incrementalism really is the best way to make public
policies, as Lindblom asserts.
Incrementalism as an alternative to the rational ideal
Ideally, policies would result from a rational analysis culminating in a value-maximizing choice
after a thorough examination of all relevant alternatives. Unfortunately, this almost never happens,
for a variety of reasons.
The breakdown of rationality: For decisions to be made rationally, public problems must be
perceived and dened accurately. In reality, there is no guarantee that problems will be perceived
at all and almost no likelihood that they will be dened the same way by all participants. Items
will reach the agenda because they have attracted political support from organized interests or
the mass public, not because they have been rationally or scientically identied.
Moreover, policy-makers must agree on objectives. This means more than just sharing the
same broad goals. All involved must also share the same priorities, ranking goals in the same way
and agreeing on exactly how to allocate nite resources. This condition is almost never satised.
287
Third, policy-makers must estimate accurately the consequences of all alternatives. Policy-makers
are almost never able to do this. On the contrary, the question of what consequences will follow
from various alternatives is almost always vigorously contested.
Clearly, rational decision-making is unattainable most of the time. Where there is no agreement
on objectives, it is impossible to say which values should be maximized. Where the knowledge
base is inadequate, there is no way to say which alternatives have the best consequences.
Incrementalism rejects the very idea of policies as the product of decisions. According to
Lindblom, policies are not the products of rational choice but rather the political resultants of par-
tisan mutual adjustment among various actors possessing dierent information, adhering to dierent
values, and driven by dierent individual or group interests (Lindblom 1965).
The advantages of incrementalism: by contrast, incrementalism requires neither comprehensive infor-
mation nor agreement among policy-makers on objectives. It permits action where the rational
ideal oers no guidance to policy-makers.
For example, policy-makers almost never face a given problem (Lindblom 1980: 24). Rather,
problems are brought to government through a process Lindblom terms the social fragmentation of
analysis (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963: 1046). No single actor possesses comprehensive infor-
mation on the problem. Rather, each brings to the table some portion of the knowledge that is
required to analyze the problem. The dispersal of essential knowledge throughout the system
makes some form of social fragmentation of analysis inevitable. No policy-maker could accu-
rately specify the varying value preferences of dierent individuals or assess the impact of policy
proposals on dierent groups without some input from these groups. Because disagreements can
be accommodated through bargaining, problems may be, and often are, acted on without ever
being fully dened.
Incrementalism avoids the need to secure agreement on objectives by focusing on concrete
problems to be alleviated (for example, unemployment) rather than on abstract ideals to be
attained (a self-actualized citizenry). The process moves away from problems rather than toward
ideals, which can never be specied with sucient precision to permit rational analysis. Lindblom
terms this element of the model remediality (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963, 1024).
Ends and means are typically considered simultaneously because dierent alternatives embody
dierent trade-os among values. When policy-makers choose one of several alternatives, they
are also choosing which trade-os should be made among values. In practice, ends and means
cannot be separated as called for by the rational model, with a decision on values preceding any
decision on alternatives. Any decision among alternatives is inherently and necessarily a decision
about values. Lindblom terms this element of the model the adjustment of objectives to policies
(Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963: 938).
Time constraints preclude a comprehensive examination of all alternative solutions. Policy-
makers must somehow limit their attention to a manageable number of options. In practice,
they accomplish this by limiting their focus to incremental alternatives (Braybrooke and Lindblom
1963: 8890). Major policy departures are unlikely to be enacted. Established policies acquire
powerful supporters opposed to any signicant changes in policy. Thus prolonged consideration
of nonincremental policy proposals is likely to be a waste of time. Moreover, policy-makers build
up a reservoir of knowledge through experience with existing policies that they will be reluc-
tant to throw away by moving in an entirely dierent direction. It makes more sense to build
on past policy than to begin again from the ground up.
Policy-makers further reduce the costs of analysis by focusing on the increments by which
various proposals dier from one another and from past policies. Lindblom terms this process
margin-dependent choice (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963: 838). In the budgetary process, for
example, legislators normally make no attempt to evaluate federal policies comprehensively.
Hayes
288
Rather, they focus on the increments by which spending will go up or down for various pro-
grams under dierent proposals. Focusing on the margins permits an intelligent comparison of
proposals where a comprehensive analysis of the various competing policies would be infeasible
(Wildavsky 1992: 823).
Finally, the policy process is serial, or repetitive (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963: 99102).
Because policies can be modied in subsequent policy cycles, unanticipated consequences do
not pose a serious problem for incrementalism. They merely generate new problems to be dealt
with at a later date. Problems are considered unsolved as long as some publics continue to express
dissatisfaction with existing policies. By the same token, a policy may be regarded as solved
when it nally disappears from the agenda, crowded o by other problems now considered
more pressing (Wildavsky 1974: 60).
Preconditions for nonincremental change
While Lindblom is correct that policy-making will be incremental most of the time, research
suggests that nonincremental policy change may occur in response to crises, an aroused mass public
opinion, or the attainment of the conditions for rational decision-making. These three favorable
circumstances will be covered in turn below.
Crises as a source of nonincremental change: Lindblom identied conditions for nonincremental
change in a volume he coauthored with David Braybrooke (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963:
6679). He characterized problems as falling within four quadrants dened by two continuous
dimensions. The rst dimension measured the policy-makers understanding of the problem at
hand; the second measured the degree of change a proposal would make from previous policy.
The four quadrants are shown below (see Table 22.1):
Within this scheme, rational decision-making is conned to a relatively small number of
cases, primarily technical decisions made by professionals in the middle levels of the
bureaucracye.g. high understanding of problems is limited to policy alternatives that are
incremental in scope. There will be, in Lindbloms view, no cases in which nonincremental
policy proposals are well understood. Most policy-making will occur within the realm of
normal incrementalism, where understanding is low and policy-makers conne themselves to
incremental proposals.
Nonincremental policy change is possible in the remaining quadrant, which Braybrooke and
Lindblom term the realm of wars, revolutions, and grand opportunities. On a less sweeping
level, policy-makers may opt for nonincremental change any time a particular policy is judged
to be broken beyond repair. Under such circumstances a calculated risk is warranted, and
Table 22.1 Four quadrants of policy change
Incremental Nonincremental
High understanding Rational decision-making
is possible for small,
technical problems
This quadrant is empty;
no cases occur here
Low understanding The realm of normal
incrementalism;
most cases t here
Nonincremental change
possible here;
realm of wars, crises, and grand
opportunities
Source: Hayes (1992) Incrementalism and Public Policy, New York: Longman
Incrementalism
289
policy-makers may opt for major policy change even though all involved recognize the limits of
their inability to predict the consequences of their actions (Dahl and Lindblom 1953: 85).
Aroused mass public opinion as a catalyst for nonincremental change: Charles O. Joness case study of
the Clean Air Amendments of 1970 showed that nonincremental policy outcomes can result
where mass public opinion is aroused on an issue, forcing policy-makers to satisfy a pre-formed
majority. Although incrementalism provided a good description of policy-making on the air
pollution issue from 19411967, the increased salience of the issue in 1970 produced a very dif-
ferent kind of policy process, necessitating the development of an alternative model to describe
events (Jones 1974, 1975).
Under normal majority-building incrementalism, as understood by Jones, mass public opinion
is typically inattentive and ill-informed. Policy development takes place within policy commu-
nities, consisting of congressional committees or subcommittees with jurisdiction over the issue,
executive agencies with responsibility for administering laws within the issue area, and clientele
groups with a stake in the policies developed by these policy communities. As bills work their way
through multiple veto points, the need for bargaining and compromise virtually guarantees that
proposals will emerge weaker than they were initially. Jones terms this process tapering demands
from the optimal down to the acceptable.
Majority-building incrementalism could not explain air pollution policy-making in 1970,
however. Public opinion polls pointed to a dramatic rise in public concern over the pollution
issue, and the sharp rise in issue salience triggered the formation of many new interest groups
representing environmental interests. This public pressure for dramatic federal action constituted
a kind of pre-formed majority, obviating the normal need for tapering down. Policy-makers
who had shown little interest in the issue before (including the president) now saw it as having
electoral potential. This expanded circle of policy-makers scrambled to satisfy the highly aroused,
pre-formed majority, and air pollution legislation grew steadily stronger as it moved through
the House and Senate through a process Jones termed policy escalation.
The end result, according to Jones, was a nonincremental policy change: Congress gave the
federal government sweeping new authority and set technology-forcing, health-based air quality
standards. However, the strong new law was not the product of any expansion in the scientic
knowledge base available to policy-makers but rather was driven primarily by the need to
appease an aroused mass public. For this reason, Jones characterized the 1970 policy outcome as
legislating beyond capability.
Attainment of the conditions for rational decision-making: throughout all his works on increment-
alism, Lindblom identied two preconditions for rational decision-making: agreement among
participants on objectives and the possession of a knowledge base sucient to permit accurate
estimation of the consequences associated with various alternatives. In Lindbloms view, incre-
mentalism describes how policy is made under normal circumstances because these two conditions
are almost never met.
While Lindblom is doubtless correct in asserting that these two conditions are not satised for
most policy problems, the failure to meet these two conditions should not be taken for granted.
For example, participants may agree on values without engaging in a comprehensive review of
alternative value mixes. The attainment of consensus on objectives changes the policy process sig-
nicantly even where it results from the failure of policy-makers to examine any other goals or
the inability of interests with contrary values to mobilize. In the same way, policy-makers may
understand some problems better than others, or at least think that they do. While a complete
understanding of cause-and-eect relationships is almost never attained, there are nevertheless issues
for which participants have achieved a consensus on basic facts. Robert Rothstein has termed
this condition consensual knowledge:
Hayes
290
a body of belief about cause-eect and ends-means relationships among variables (activities,
aspirations, values, demands) that is widely accepted by the relevant actors, irrespective of
the absolute or nal truth of these beliefs.
(1984: 736)
As with consensual objectives, the policy process is fundamentally altered whenever policy-
makers agree on how the world works for a given issue whether this shared understanding of
cause-and-eect relationships is ultimately vindicated or disconrmed.
Combining these two dimensions produces a typology of four quadrants that diers sig-
nicantly from the one advanced earlier by Braybrooke and Lindblom. It should be noted that
where issues t within the typology is properly determined by their placement on the under-
lying dimensions and not by the names attached to the categories. Thus initial placement of a
particular issue within one of the four cells in no way precludes its movement over time into
one of the other cells. Issues will move from one category to another whenever the degree of
agreement on values or the adequacy of the knowledge base is aected by events.
Where conict over objectives is combined with an inadequate knowledge base that leads to
disagreement over policy consequences (conictual knowledge), as in cell A, incrementalism is
virtually inevitable. The policy process will exhibit all the characteristics of normal increment-
alism and policy outcomes will necessarily be incremental. Lindblom is almost surely right in
assuming that this will be the normal case.
By contrast, cell B consists of what might be termed pure problems of value conict. Here
the knowledge base is not the problem and policy-makers exhibit what Rothstein called con-
sensual knowledge. While policy outcomes are likely to be incremental at best in this cell, the
process by which these outcomes are determined will be much more conictual than Lindblom
envisioned for normal incrementalism. Within normal incrementalism, problems are complex
and the self-interest of various participants will be poorly understood, thus tempering conict to at
least some extent. By contrast, where problems are well understood, the clarity of the stakes for all
involved will intensify conict. For example, social security is a dicult issue for policy-makers
precisely because all reforms have immediate and readily understood redistributive consequences.
The ght is over who will bear the costs of repairing the system.
The policy process will be dierent again for pure problems of knowledge base (cell C). Here, a
consensus on objectives exists and rational policy-making is precluded only by an inadequate
understanding of the problem. Policy-making here will monitor information from the envir-
onment and adapt to changing circumstances through feedback. Macroeconomic policy-making
provides a good example here,
Finally, where consensual knowledge is combined with consensual objectives, as in cell D,
rational decision-making is attainable. While many of the issues for which these two conditions
Table 22.2 A typology of decision environments
Conictual objectives Consensual objectives
Conictual or contested knowledge (A) Realm of
normal incrementalism
(C) Pure problems of
knowledge base
Consensual knowledge (B) Pure problems of
value conict
(D) Realm of rational
decision-making
Source: Hayes (2001) The Limits of Policy Change: Incrementalism, Worldview and the Rule of Law. Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press
Incrementalism
291
are satised may involve relatively small technical or administrative problems, as Lindblom has
suggested (Braybrooke and Lindblom 1963: 6179), nonincremental policy departures are also
possible here. Where policy-makers agree on objectives and share a consensual knowledge base,
there is nothing to preclude large change if large change seems warranted.
The life cycle of policies: when are the conditions for rational decision-making most likely to be met?
All policies go through a predictable life cycle, and the preconditions for rational decision-making
are most likely to be attained late in the life cycle of policies.
Lindblom saw policy-makers as typically building on past policies. This presumes the exis-
tence of past policies to build on. Most policy problems have in fact been around for many
years, taxing the capacities of policy-makers and resisting any nal solution. However, all policies
began as brand new policies at some point in time. Building on the earlier research of Lawrence
D. Brown (1983), we may call legislative enactments establishing a new federal responsibility
federal role breakthrough policies. This is the rst stage in the life cycle of policies.
Over time, policy communities develop around these new programs. Congressional committees
are assigned responsibility for legislative oversight, executive agencies are given statutory authority
to administer the new law, and aected interest groups establish close ties with these legislators
and administrators. Because new policies are unlikely to be well-understood or to generate con-
sensual goals, policy-making will typically exhibit characteristics of normal incrementalism for
many years. Brown termed policies aimed at reforming or improving government programs
already in existence rationalizing policies. Because such rationalizing policies tend to exhibit
the characteristics of normal incrementalism for many years, we may call this second stage of the
life cycle the stage of incremental rationalizing policies.
For many policies, this will be the nal stage in the life cycle. For at least some policies, how-
ever, workable solutions to problems may emerge after many years. As policy-makers come to
understand problems better over time through accumulated experience with policy imple-
mentation, a consensus on both objectives and knowledge base may develop. Where this occurs,
the conditions for rationality are met, permitting the development of what we may term ratio-
nalizing breakthroughs. Such initiatives are rationalizing policies because they seek to reform existing
government programs, but they also constitute breakthrough policies of a very special sort
inasmuch as they represent a dramatic shift in thinking and policy design that permits eective
action in addressing enduring problems.
Thus the conditions for rational policy-making are more likely to emerge at the end of the
life cycle than the beginning. While nonincremental policy change may result from crisis con-
ditions or in response to an aroused mass public opinion, it will be most eective and lasting
where it constitutes a rationalizing breakthrough in the nal stage in the life cycle of an issue.
Policies do not reach this nal stage without going through the two prior stages, however.
There are no shortcuts to rational decision-making.
Can incrementalism be trusted to yield good policies?
Is incrementalism the best way to make policies, as Lindblom asserts? There will never be complete
agreement on this point because attitudes toward incrementalism depend on underlying assump-
tions about human nature and what it is possible to achieve through analysis. In this regard,
Hayek (1948), Sowell (1987), and Spicer (1995) identied two distinct worldviews, which may
be termed rationalist and anti-rationalist (see also Hayes 2001: 750).
Rationalists reject Lindbloms thesis that rational-comprehensive analysis is unattainable. They
are optimistic about human nature and believe that all social problems can be solved through
the exercise of reason. By contrast, anti-rationalists are pessimistic about human nature and see
Hayes
292
distinct limits on what can be achieved through human reason (Hayes 2001: 811). Where ration-
alists see solutions as emerging from analysis, anti-rationalists see good public policies as emer-
ging from a policy process that is pluralistic and typically conictual. In Sowells terms (1987),
rationalists believe in articulated rationality while anti-rationalists believe in systemic rationality.
Wildavsky (1979) makes this same distinction, characterizing the alternatives as intellectual cogitation
vs. social interaction.
Rationalists reject incrementalism for a variety of reasons. They dislike the muddled com-
promises that emerge from pluralistic political processes, eschew piecemeal and gradual social
reforms in favor of sweeping policy proposals, and decisively reject any strategy for building on
a status quo they view as inherently awed. By contrast, anti-rationalists embrace incremental-
ism, accepting incrementalisms core tenet that good policies are more likely to result from
pluralistic processes and endorsing incrementalisms stress on learning through seriality.
Critics have advanced a variety of indictments against incrementalism (see the various authors
reviewed in Weiss and Woodhouse 1992: 25268). While some of these indictments are essen-
tially rationalist in orientation, others are anti-rationalist, accepting the need for policy-making
through social interaction but pointing to inherent aws in the policy process. By and large, the
rationalist critiques can be easily dismissed; the anti-rationalist critiques are more compelling.
Rationalist indictments: here there are four main criticisms: (1) that incrementalism is insu-
ciently goal-oriented; (2) that it is hostile to analysis; (3) that it is inherently reactive rather than
proactive; and (4) that it cannot anticipate sleeper eects.
1 Critics of incrementalism want policy-making to be purposive, or goal-oriented. This criti-
cism assumes it is actually possible to identify agreed upon ends. For example, Dryzek
(1987: 424) denes the concept of instrumental rationality as the capacity to devise, select,
and eect good means to claried ends (emphasis added). By contrast, Lindblom sees
multiple and conicting objectives as the normal case. While participants may agree on the
desirability of all the ends, agreement on objectives implies agreement on prioritiesa
much higher standard to satisfy.
In this vein, rationalists and anti-rationalists tend to dier in their handling of trade-os
(Sowell 1995: 13542). Anti-rationalists recognize that desired goals are often in conict
and cannot be satised simultaneously. On the contrary, to gain more of one value, you
must give up some of the other. Understood in this way, agreement on objectives implies
a consensus among participants on exactly how to make these trade-os, a consensus that
is typically unattainable. By contrast, rationalists tend to focus on one goal at a time,
ignoring or denying the existence of trade-o relationships with other goals. Any attempt
at rational analysis that achieves agreement on objectives by focusing on a single goal may
facilitate coherent, purposeful decision-making but only at the expense of neglecting
alternative values that do not go away just because they are ignored.
2 A related criticism charges that incrementalism is hostile to analysis. This charge misrepresents
how incrementalism works. Anti-rationalists, including Lindblom, expect participants to
employ analysis both in pursuing their self-interest and in attempting to identify workable
solutions to public problems. Anti-rationalists see distinct limits on the ability of any one actor
to formulate comprehensive, workable solutions to public problems. Those limits ow out of
inherent limitations on mans cognitive capacities and the dispersion of pertinent information
throughout the population. Accordingly, good policies are more likely to emerge from the
interplay of multiple actors, each of whom can be expected to marshal the best arguments they
can in defense of their positions. Policy-making by social interaction (systemic rationality)
is not just a balance of power among participants; it is also a competition among ideas.
Incrementalism
293
3 The third criticism holds that incrementalism is inherently reactive rather than proactive.
According to Lindblom, policy-making is reactive by necessity. Where values are multiple
and in conict with one another, as is usually the case, proactive policy-making is virtually
impossible. Fortunately, policy-makers do not need to secure agreement on goals. To the
contrary, they can consider ends and means together through the adjustment of objectives
to policies. Because dierent options embody dierent value trade-os, to choose one alter-
native over others is to choose a value trade-o, and conict over which option to choose
represents a conict over value trade-os. Policy-making is meliorative as a consequence,
moving away from concrete problems rather than toward abstract ideals.
4 The nal rationalist critique stresses the the inability of incrementalism to deal with what are
called sleeper eects. These are negative policy consequences that remain invisible through
many policy cycles only to show up suddenly at a point when it has become dicult, if not
impossible, to change course. A contemporary example would be global warming; here
reliance on fossil fuels as an energy source has created a greenhouse eect. The consequences
of this greenhouse eect for climate change only began to be understood by scientists
when an irreversible threshold was about to be crossed.
Although sleeper eects clearly pose a serious problem for incrementalism, it is not clear how
late-blooming negative consequences could be identied earlier through eorts at rational-
comprehensive analysis (Weiss and Woodhouse 1992: 265). Indeed, it is hard to see how any
decision-making method could anticipate policy consequences which are beyond the available
knowledge base by denition. In theory, at least, sleeper eects should pose less of a threat to a
process in which policy changes occur gradually, in small steps. If sleeper eects can be likened to
lemmings running o a cli (Dryzek 1983), it would seem better to approach the cli at reduced
speed. In the case of global warming, the science has taken decades to develop, and under-
standing is still incomplete. How would nonincremental policy-making magically solve the
problem of an inadequate knowledge base?
The rationalist critiques just reviewed all treat incrementalism as a strategy for policy-making
that can be chosen or discarded at will. However, policy-making is not pluralistic and con-
ictual because participants have chosen incrementalism over rationality as a strategy for policy-
making. Rather, it is pluralistic and conictual because one or more of the conditions for
rational decision-making have broken down, as is the case in three of the four quadrants identied
earlier.
Anti-rationalist criticisms: anti-rationalist critiques acknowledge the superiority of policy-making
by social interaction but point to inherent aws in the policy process. Here the main criticism is
that incrementalism is inherently conservative, rst because it encourages policy-makers to focus
exclusively on small increments, and second because the interplay of multiple interests will
necessarily favor organized elites (especially corporations) with disproportionate political power.
First, critics indict incrementalism for rejecting fundamental changes in the status quo and
focusing instead on gradual policy change through incremental steps (Weiss and Woodhouse 1992:
2602). This argument ignores the potential for continual improvement in policies through
modication in subsequent policy cycles. Seriality allows policy-makers to converge on a solution
through trial and error. While any given outcome may be incremental, signicant policy change
is possible through an accumulation of small changes over time. In fact, signicant change may
occur sooner through a rapid succession of small steps than through an occasional nonincremental
policy
change (Lindblom 1979:
5201).
If signicant change is clearly possible through seriality, can incrementalism be legitimately
charged with a conservative bias? Admittedly, it makes a degree of sense to view rationalists as
Hayes
294
liberals because of their optimistic view of what it is possible to achieve through politics. Similarly,
anti-rationalists might be characterized as conservative to the extent that they are more skeptical
regarding what it is possible to achieve through politics. Sowell (1995) characterizes the two
worldviews in precisely this way.
This simple, dichotomous distinction is misleading, however, as incrementalism may be employed
to pursue liberal policies. As Karl Popper observed:
This method [incrementalism, or piecemeal social engineering in Poppers terms] can be
used in order to search for, and ght against, the greatest and most urgent evils of
society, rather than to seek, and to ght for, some ultimate good But a systematic ght
against denite wrongs, against concrete forms of injustice or exploitation, and avoidable
suering such as poverty or unemployment, is a very dierent thing from the attempt to
realize a distant ideal blueprint of society.
(1994: 912)
Clearly, the fact that incrementalism is meliorative rather than utopian, and that it pursues policy
change through seriality rather than once-and-for-all solutions, does not make the strategy inher-
ently conservative. In this regard, Hayes (2001) distinguishes between rationalist liberals (which
he terms utopian visionaries) and anti-rationalist (or meliorative) liberals, as well as between
nostalgic (rationalist) and adaptive (anti-rationalist) conservatives. Within this scheme, both
Lindblom and Popper would qualify as meliorative liberals (ibid.: 2841).
Second, incrementalism has also been characterized as conservative because the interplay of
multiple interests will tend to favor organized elites with disproportionate power (Weiss and
Woodhouse 1992: 2602). Two conditions in particular must be met for incrementalism to
yield good public policies. First, all aected interests must succeed in mobilizing. Lindblom was
overly optimistic on this point in his early writings, assuming that every important social interest
would have its watchdog (Lindblom 1959: 85). The free rider problem prevents many groups
from organizing at all, however (Olson 1970), creating a systemic bias in favor of small groups
over large diuse groups like consumers or taxpayers. Inasmuch as membership groups face a
free rider problem that never goes away, they will be at a disadvantage vis-à-vis institutions, which
are already organized for other purposes and thus face no free rider problem. Finally, groups
mobilizing auent constituencies will have an advantage over groups attempting to mobilize
the poor inasmuch as the auent can more easily aord membership dues (on these points, see
the sources cited in Hayes 2001: Chapter 4).
The second condition that must be met for incrementalism to operate eciently is a rough
equality in power across groups. Just as economic markets work badly whenever some rms
have market power, incrementalism works badly whenever some actors possess disproportionate
political power. Lindblom (1977, 1982) argued that corporations will occupy a privileged
position within capitalist societies. Because corporations can deliver or withhold prosperity, they
have unparalleled legitimacy to the extent that policy-makers equate the class interest of busi-
ness with the public interest (Miliband 1969). This legitimacy gives corporations both a veto
power over policies that threaten them and a form of indirect inuence (control without trying),
as corporations receive favorable tax or regulatory benets from policy-makers that they have
not actively sought.
Lindblom is not advancing a power elite thesis here; rather, he sees the policy process as
pluralistic but skewed toward the interests of corporations. His primary concern is that business
power hampers the proper operation of incrementalism, keeping some items o the agenda
entirely and channeling disproportionate benets to business groups. Although this concern is
Incrementalism
295
valid, disproportionate business power would plague any policy-making method: [I]t is the socio-
political power structure that favors organized elites, not incrementalism or any other decision
strategy (Weiss and Woodhouse 1992: 262).
While corporations may occupy a privileged position in capitalist societies, Lindbloms ana-
lysis is overstated. Business groups do not win all the time, and their ability to block policies
they oppose is overrated (Hayes 2006: 6379). While business groups do win more than any
other group in contemporary American politics, they also suer defeats, and there are many
issues on which they take no position at all. The larger question is whether the American system
features dispersed or cumulative inequalities (Dahl 2005). In a system of dispersed inequalities,
the money or manpower of some groups might be oset by the legitimacy or expertise of other
groups. In a system of cumulative inequalities, by contrast, some groups will rank high on all or
most dimensions of inuence while others will rank low across the board. Right now, corpora-
tions possess vast wealth and unparalleled legitimacy. They also have an advantage in expertise
on technical regulatory issues, and, with their ability to deliver or withhold prosperity, they
occupy a strategic position within the economy.
While this business advantage in resources may seem insurmountable, it is worth recalling
that Dahl (2005) found a surprising evolution in New Haven over time from a system of cumu-
lative inequalities to one of dispersed inequalities. This occurred through the natural develop-
ment of new sources of power that none of the original power-holders could have anticipated
and which they were powerless to block. Policy-makers bent on dispersing inequalities could
take action both to facilitate mobilization of previously unorganized interests and to ameliorate
inequality in tangible resources across groups through a system of public nancing for congres-
sional campaigns (Hayes 2001: 1626). Although such reforms would mitigate the problem of
cumulative inequalities, they would not eliminate completely the privileged position corporations
will always occupy within any capitalist societya problem that would plague any decision-making
method, as noted above.
Special problems plaguing incrementalism in the American context: two additional anti-rationalist
critiques may be oered that would apply with special force in the United States. The rst stems
from our system of checks-and-balances. The second ows out of the potential for divided
government in an era of polarized political parties.
First, in Lindbloms view (and mine), there is no viable alternative to incrementalism under
most circumstances. The question is not whether policy-making should be incremental, but rather
whether incrementalism is functioning eciently. Lindblom is right that more can be achieved
through a rapid succession of small steps than through an occasional major policy change.
However, aspects of the political system may preclude revisiting policies on a regular basis, thus
preventing the kind of rapid succession of small steps Lindblom envisions. Under such circum-
stances, incrementalism can be properly accused of a conservative bias. Lindblom (1979) believes
our system of checks-and-balances impedes the proper operation of incrementalism in precisely
this way by making it extremely dicult to pass any kind of legislation. Too often, incrementalism
in the United States features small policy changes a generation or more apart. This problem has
become especially acute in recent years with the development of the party libuster and the 60-vote
Senate (more on this below).
Second, for any system of policy-making through social interaction to function properly, all
aected interests must be eectively represented. We have already seen how unrealistic this is.
The development in recent years of a system of polarized parties makes the representation of a
broad range of interests even more problematic. While our contemporary parties help voters
hold politicians accountable by functioning as responsible parties, they also hamper the eective
operation of incrementalism. To the extent that each party represents a narrow range of
Hayes
296
interests, unied government could produce a policy equilibrium that is necessarily incomplete,
representing only the range of views held by members of the majority party.
Seen in this light, divided government might seem to force consideration of a more complete
range of viewpoints by giving eective leverage to both parties. Where the two parties are as
polarized as ours are today, however, they are more likely to be completely opposed on most
major issues, making gridlock more likely than cooperation. This tendency toward gridlock may
be reinforced by electoral incentives, as neither party wants to cooperate on issues that might
otherwise be used against the other party in the next election. In a world of polarized parties,
then, unied government may be a necessary condition for passing controversial legislation. As
we have seen in recent years, the 60-vote Senate gives the minority party some leverage even
under conditions of unied government.
Under such circumstances, incremental policy changes a generation apart may be all we can
hope for. While meliorative liberals like Lindblom would view this as the worst of all policy-making
worlds, it is not inconsistent with the vision of the framers. While the checks-and-balances built
into the constitution may foster incrementalism, they were never intended to foster ecient
policy-making via a rapid succession of small steps.
In conclusion, incrementalism is clearly not a utopian method of policy-making. While the
rationalist critiques are rooted in a misunderstanding of how the policy process operates, the anti-
rationalist critiques point to real problems with the method. It must be noted, however, that
Lindblom never characterizes incrementalism as functioning to yield optimal policies in every
instance. Rather, he argues that incrementalism will outperform misguided eorts to employ
rational-comprehensive analysis. Indeed, as noted in an earlier section of this chapter, once
rationality breaks down, there is no longer any criterion for determining whether policy out-
comes are good or bad. One can only hope that good policy processes will yield good policy
outcomes, at least most of the time. Ultimately, Lindbloms case for incrementalism as a policy-
making method is meliorative rather than utopian. While corporate power and the failure of
some interests to mobilize make for a rigged competition (Weiss and Woodhouse 1992: 262),
incrementalismhowever imperfectis still the only viable way to make policy when the
conditions for rationality break down.
Bibliography
Braybrooke, David, and Charles E. Lindblom. 1963. A Strategy of Decision: Policy Evaluation as a Social
Process. New York: Free Press of Glencoe.
Brown, Lawrence D. 1983. New Policies, New Politics: Governments Response to Governments Growth.
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Dahl, Robert A. 2005. Who Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City, 2nd edn. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
——and Charles E. Lindblom. 1953. Politics, Economics, and Welfare: Planning and Politico-Economic Systems
Resolved into Basic Social Processes. New York: Harper & Row, Harper Torchbooks.
Dryzek, John S. 1983. Present choices, future consequences: A case for thinking strategically, World
Futures 19: 119.
—— 1987. Complexity and rationality in public life, Political Studies 35: 424 42.
Hayek, Friedrich. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hayes, Michael T. 1992. Incrementalism and Public Policy. New York: Longman.
—— 2001. The Limits of Policy Change: Incrementalism, Worldview, and the Rule of Law. Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press.
—— 2006. Incrementalism and Public Policy. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Jones, Charles O. 1974. Speculative augmentation in federal air pollution policy-making, Journal of Politics
36(May): 43864.
—— 1975. Clean Air: The Policies and Politics of Pollution Control. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Incrementalism
297
Lindblom, Charles E. 1959. The science of muddling through, Public Administration Review 19 (Spring):
7988.
—— 1965. The Intelligence of Democracy: Decision-Making Through Mutual Adjustment. New York: Free Press.
—— 1977 Politics and Markets: The Worlds Political Economic Systems. New York: Basic Books.
—— 1979. Still muddling, not yet through, Public Administration Review 39(6): 517 26.
—— 1980. The Policy-Making Process, 2nd edn. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
—— 1982. The market as prison, Journal of Politics 44: 32436.
Miliband, Ralph. 1969. The State in Capitalist Society. New York: Basic Books/Harper Colophon Books.
Olson, Mancur, Jr. 1970. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups. New York:
Schocken Books.
Popper, Karl. 1994. The Poverty of Historicism. London and New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Rothstein, Robert L. 1984. Consensual knowledge and international collaboration: Some lessons from the
commodity negotiations, International Organization 38: 73362.
Sowell, Thomas. 1987. A Conict of Visions: Ideological Origins of Political Struggles. New York: William
Morrow, Quill Books.
—— 1995. The Vision of the Anointed: Self-Congratulation as a Basis for Social Policy. New York: Basic Books.
Spicer, Michael. 1995. The Founders, the Constitution, and Public Administration. Washington, DC: Georgetown
University Press.
Weiss, Andrew and Woodhouse, Edward. 1992. Reframing incrementalism: A constructive response to
the critics, Policy Sciences 25: 25573.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1974. The Politics of the Budgetary Process. Boston: Little, Brown.
—— 1979. Speaking Truth to Power: The Art and Craft of Policy Analysis. Boston: Little, Brown.
—— 1992. The New Politics of the Budgetary Process, 2nd edn. New York: HarperCollins.
Hayes
298
23
Models for research into
decision-making processes
On phases, streams, rounds and tracks
of decision-making
1
Geert R. Teisman and Arwin van Buuren
Models for the reconstruction of decision-making
Public administration scholars agree that decision-making has become more complex. Several
reasons can be identied for this increased complexity. Two important ones are increased uncer-
tainty about the dynamics and interdependencies in global networks and the power-sharing
characteristics or that network society. In networks, local circumstances can change quickly
due to networks dynamics. At the same time, decisions are taken in a society where nobody is
in charge (Bryson and Crosby 1992; Kickert et al. 1997). These two system changes do make
public decision-making complex. Situations can change quickly and any decision taken interacts
with decisions taken by others.
This chapter is based on the assumption of increased complexity. As such, it ts in with many
others. Often the focus is on the consequences of and challenges for governments or govern-
ance systems. Complexity is clearly taken into account in the wider discussion on governance in
networks. This was already the case before 2000 (for example: in Germany Marin and Mayntz 1991
and Scharpf 1997; in France Crozier and Friedberg 1980; in Great Britain Rhodes 1996b; and
in the United States E. Ostrom 1990; Smith 1998). After 2000, many other publications have ela-
borated the complexity-government/governance relation (Strand 2002; Teisman and Klijn
2002; Duit and Galaz 2006; Wagenaar 2007; Gerrits 2008, Teisman et al. 2009).
Complexity, however, also raises questions for researchers of complexity. What kinds of models
can researchers in decision-making apply to describe, analyse and evaluate decision-making and
how do these models deal with complexity? Attention was paid to this topic by Mintzberg
(1973), Kingdon (1984), Butler (1991) and Teisman ([1992, 1995] 1998). They generated images
of decision-making as phases, as streams and as rounds. After 2000, van Buuren and Gerrits (2008)
and Haynes (2008) contributed to the thinking about this topic by introducing concepts as
tracks and traces as well as timelines and rates of change to indicate dynamics in processes. These
authors pay special attention to the compounded, erratic and unpredictable characteristics of
299
decision-making processes. By looking at processes they focus far less on the decision and more
on the emergence of outcomes from a variety of more or less coupled decisions of a variety of
actors. To indicate this conguration of ecology of decisions as an important object of study
Teisman, van Buuren and Gerrits (2009: 23149) introduce the concept of process systems.
This concept underlines the embeddedness of individuals and their decisions in groups of indi-
viduals and their decisions into an organizational and institutional context where many more (in
terms of content unrelated) decisions are taken that can emerge into important ones for the
progress in decision-making on the level of individuals and groups.
This chapter focuses on the question of how to depict decision-making which evolves in
complex network structures. We will concentrate on the characterization of successive decision-
making activities and of concurrent decision-making activities. We will also discuss the assumed
relations between the activities, in sequential as well as parallel combinations. The following
research questions can be formulated:
1 Which assumptions are made with respect to chains of activities in decision-making processes?
We will analyse dierent criteria used to distinguish between strands of activities, typolo-
gies of decision-making as a whole and elements of this process, and signs of progress in
decision-making.
2 What sorts of assumptions are made with respect to simultaneous activities in decision-
making processes? Specically, we will distinguish here between (more or less relevant)
actors, the relationship between problems and solutions, and the content of decision-making
in terms of ambitions, frames and facts.
To analyse decision-making, the researcher needs to make a reconstruction of the study
object. Such a reconstruction will be selective in nature. Observation is not simply an eort to
learn what is going on. Rather it is a process where observations are made to conform to sets of
assumptions (Edelman 1971). The gathering and classication of empirical observations into
meaningful information is based on the a priori images of decision-making used. We cannot
depict decision-making without making assumptions about its appearance. Various terms are
used to describe such a set of assumptions: model, image, metaphor, referential framework or
methodology. In this chapter the term model will be used. Models help us to understand
decision-making in distinctive yet partial ways (Morgan 1997: 4).
Four models will be discussed in this chapter. Two of these are generally accepted and
respected, namely the so-called phase model and the stream model. The phase model is the most
common approach, both in science (e.g. Anderson 1979; Bryson and Crosby 1992) and in policy
practice (procedures are often based on the concept of phasing). Decision-making is represented
in terms of a number of distinct stages (Mintzberg 1976). Phase models distinguish between (at
least) policy formation, policy adoption and policy implementation. Each phase has its specic
characteristics and participants. Ministries, for instance, are often divided into departments that
are responsible for policy formation and others responsible for implementation.
The stream model depicts decision-making as a combination of three separate concurrent
streams (Kingdon 1984). One stream consists of problems, another of policies/solutions, and a
third one of politics/participants. Like the phases, streams have their own characteristics, but
they exist side by side. A decision results out of the coincidence of streams.
The third model, the round model, has become more and more accepted as a conceptual
approach to analyse decision-making in the context of complex networks (van Bueren et al. 2003;
Howlett 2010). In this so-called rounds model decision-making is assumed to consist of dierent
decision-making rounds. In all sets of rounds, the interaction between dierent actors results in
Teisman and van Buuren
300
one or more denitions of problems and solutions. In addition to Teisman (2000) we will present a
fourth approach of complex decision-making, elaborated by van Buuren (2006) based upon the
assumption that we can interpret decision-making as three co-evolving tracks: of fact-nding,
framing and will-forming (cf. van Buuren and Gerrits 2008; van Herk et al. 2011).
In the round model the interaction between varieties of actors is the primary focus of the
researchers. All participants can score points in each round, in terms of a leading denition of
the problem and the (preferred) solution. By doing so, they dene the beginning of a next
round. But at the same time each new round can change the direction of the match: new players
can appear, and in some cases the rules of the game can even be changed. The rounds model
was developed during years of research in the eld of urban and infrastructural planning. The
rst author was fascinated by the long duration of decision-making processes and by the changes
in course these processes often take. Another remarkable result of his research was that the
actors involved in decision-making often did not agree on the classication of a certain stage in
the process, in terms of formation, adoption and implementation. Although he was able to identify
several ocial decisions taken by ministers, Parliament, Parliamentary committees, etc., none of
these decisions could be clearly depicted as the moment of adoption. Some of the ocial decisions
were followed by actions which could not possibly be seen as the implementation of these
decisions. This brought the rst author to a fascinating conclusion: in complex decision-making
results are achieved without the existence of the decision that marks the switch from the pre-
paration phase into the implementation phase. Furthermore, the distinction between what the
problem is and what the solutions are proved to be more complicated than assumed in the stream
model. What was a solution for one actor could easily be a problem for another. Participants
bring along closely intertwined problems and solutions.
In order to understand these dynamics and variety in perceptions, Teisman gradually altered
his conceptual denition of decision-making. Due to the fact that the central decision could not
be found, he began to collect all the decisions that were taken in a certain case. Second, he no
longer assumed that the decisions were arranged on the basis of an a priori order and hierarchy.
On the contrary, it was the task of research to clarify the empirical relation between decisions.
In order to do so, decision-making was redened as an intertwined clew of a series of decisions
taken by various parties, leading to a new analytical model. Progress is described in terms of
successive rounds.
The second author (2006) took this insight as point of departure to answer the question: but
how can we understand the evolution of the content of decision-making processes when it comes
to the issues at stake? What are the various elements which constitute the content of decision-
making? And how do they inuence each other? To answer this question there are numerous
points of departure to be chosen. Many authors (implicitly or explicitly) depart from a distinc-
tion between elements of ambition, interest and stake, versus elements of knowledge, analysis
and information. This distinction can be traced back to Lindblom and Woodhouse (1992) who
distinguish between activities to gather information and activities to exert inuence, and to Heclo
(1974) who uses the concepts of powering and puzzling to depict the same phenomena.
More recently, much literature has appeared which deals with a third element, the role of
interpretation and thus of frames or belief systems in decision-making processes (Feldman 1989;
Schön and Rein 1993; Fischer 2003; Sabatier 1999). Frames are the normative and subjective
perceptions of actors within decision-making processes. Frames are important in decision-making
because they determine which knowledge questions are taken into account, but also which
ambitions are seen as tting in a specic problem context.
Each actor brings in his own facts, frames and ambitions within a decision-making process
and negotiates with other actors to agree about them. These elements evolve in a dynamic and
Research models
301
erratic way and inuence each other. Decisions can be seen as temporal selections of facts,
frames and ambitions. This temporal equilibrium can be easily challenged when the content of
its constituting tracks changes.
The tracks model (elaborated in Figure 23.1) is based upon the assumption that it is helpful to
describe the evolution in these three tracks separately, to be able to explain (the consequences
of) their mutual interaction and their inuence on the decisions realized.
After having examined all four models, they will be compared with each other. A four-fold
analysis of decision-making about the Betuwe freight railway line will be carried out, and nally
we shall draw some conclusions regarding the added value of the tracks and rounds models
compared to the phase and streams model.
Concepts within and principles of the phase model
In policy process analyses policy can be understood and examined as a combination of several
processes, which are interrelated but can still be conceived as distinct components that are deter-
minants of government actions (Sato 1999). The phase model assumes that decision-making is
the succession of dierent situations in the formulation, adoption, implementation and eva-
luation of a policy (Bryson and Crosby 1992: 5766)
2
. Often formation is divided into a phase
of problem denition and a phase wherein solutions are presented. The rst stage of the tradi-
tional policy process, problem denition, involves the emergence and recognition of some pro-
blem or crisis. In the second stage a policy to address specic problems is formulated by various
governmental and non-governmental actors such as legislators, executive branch ocials, the
courts, citizens and special interest groups. Special policy proposals are adopted in the third stage.
The fourth stage is policy implementation, wherein the adopted alternatives are executed by
administrative units. Finally, in the policy evaluation stage, policy-makers determine whether
the policy has achieved its goals (Altman and Petkus 1994).
Policy formulation is described as the collecting and analysing of information and the for-
mulating of advice regarding the policy to be followed. Parts of this phase include recognition,
diagnosis, search for information, design and evaluation of the dierent alternatives that are designed.
Policy adoption involves the taking of decisions about the contents of a policy. During imple-
mentation the chosen means are applied: Decision-making is a sequence of steps which, if
followed, should lead to the best solution; that is, to action which optimises the decision makers
utility (Butler 1991: 434).
Analysts using the phase model are aware of the fact that reality does not reect the assumption
of the model: Planning in shared-power situations hardly ever follows a rigidly structured sequence
from developing problem denitions and solutions to adopting and implementing proposals.
Figure 23.1 A depiction of four models for the analysis of decision-making processes
Source: Teisman (2000) Models for research into decision-making processes: On phases, streams
and decision-making rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756
Teisman and van Buuren
302
Serious diculties arise when people try to impose this rigidly sequential approach on situations
in which no one is in charge (Bryson and Crosby 1992: xiv). Nonetheless, to be steadily
eective, it is essential to have an organised approach of some sort (ibid.: xiv). Several scientists
reach the same conclusion (Hoogerwerf 1982; Mintzberg et al. 1976). They are aware that empiri-
cism deviates from this, but feel it is worthwhile to reconstruct policy-making as though it was
taking place in phases. The phase metaphor allows scientists to develop dierent theories regarding
the various stages. To reconstruct the policy formation phase, concepts such as problem de-
nition, generating alternative solutions and policy design are used. To analyse the adoption
of policies, analysts look for the central decision which demarcates the transition from formation
to implementation. During this phase, the policy proposal needs to be determined that is opti-
mally suited to achieve the set objectives. Many parties are involved in this phase, but in the end
only one or two actors determine which means are used to achieve the objectives. During the
implementation phase, the researcher focuses on how chosen means were used and how any
opposition was handled.
Problems preceding the search for and choice of solutions
Scientists using the phase model assume that decision-making is problem-oriented (Scharpf
1997). There is, or at least there should be, one actor whose decision supersedes those of others
and who therefore determines the problem and the policy. We therefore dene public policy
as substantive decisions, commitments, and actions made by those who hold or aect govern-
ment positions of authority, as they are interpreted by various stakeholders (Bryson and Crosby
1992: 63). Even though Bryson and Crosby (ibid.: 159) agree with Rittel and Webber (1973)
that public problems are wicked in the sense that they have no denite formulation, cannot be
solved immediately and are unique, they still assume that problems do exist and should be known
before a search for solutions can begin. Developing a problem denition to guide action is
seen as the rst and most important phase in decision-making, which should be carried out before
the adoption of a policy by the policy-maker can take place. Bryson and Crosby also assume that a
solution can be formulated at a single point and place (see Figure 23.2). It is on these points that
the stream and rounds models use dierent assumptions.
Concepts within and principles of the stream model
Some researchers assume that the horizontal division of activities is a more crucial distinction to
analyse processes than the vertical division used in the phase model. In their view, the analysis of
the various phases does not result in specic theories on policy formation, policy adoption and
implementation. Based on this point of view, the so-called stream model was developed in 1972
by Cohen et al. In 1984 Kingdon elaborated this model further. His model was based on the
idea that policy-making consists of three streams: problems, solutions/policies and politics. As
opposed to the phase model, here decision-making is dissociated from a specic participant. The
idea is that decision-making consists mainly of a stream in which problems are discussed, a stream
in which solutions are discussed and a stream consisting of things such as the attitude of the public,
campaigns by pressure groups, and ideological contributions (Kingdon 1984: 152). Politicians
can determine the problems and solutions they wished to concentrate on. For this reason, they
are likely to rush from one combination of problem and solution to another. As a result of this,
the level of participation in decision-making is likely to vary strongly. This is partly because
these processes develop unpredictably (March and Olsen 1976: 1023). Thus, the temporal
sequence of the phase model is replaced by the postulate of simultaneousness (Koppenjan 1993: 26).
Research models
303
The three streams exist simultaneously. They are largely independent of one another, and each
develops according to its own dynamics and rules (Kingdon 1984: 20). There are three separate
worlds where specic products are developed and transformed into their own dynamics and there-
fore are not linked in any temporal sequence. While there are indeed dierent processes, they
do not necessarily follow one another through time in any regular pattern (Kingdon 1984: 83).
Actors with solutions in the policy stream are looking for problems and political commitment,
while politicians are looking for both solutions and problems with which they can score. According
to this conceptual model, major policy changes are likely to occur only if the three streams
become linked. Such linkages can occur especially if there is a favourable momentum, a so-called
policy window (Kingdon 1984: 174; Anglund 1999). The researcher can make decision-making
transparent by investigating to what extent links are forged and why they are forged. Thus
decision-making is not primarily separated into vertical strands, in the sense of consecutive steps
over time, but rather in horizontal strands, in the sense of streams existing simultaneously side
by side (see Figure 23.3).
The rounds model of decision-making: interacting decisions
In the rounds model, actors are once again the focal point of analysis. The assumption here is
that solutions/policy and problems are relevant to a policy process, insofar as they are presented
by an actor during this process (Scharpf et al. 1978; Teisman 1998) In contrast to the phase model,
here the researcher assumes that problems and solutions are not linked to a single actor (policy-
maker) and are therefore not xed at the single moment at which the policy is adopted. Many
actors are involved in decision-making, and they will introduce their own perceptions of
Figure 23.2 The concept of decision-making used in the phase model
Source: Teisman (2000) Models for research into decision-making processes: On phases, streams
and decision-making rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756
Teisman and van Buuren
304
relevant problems, possible solutions and political judgement. In order to understand decision-
making, the researcher focuses on the variety of actors, objectives and solutions, their dynamics
as well as the interaction between these elements. Complex decision-making involves many
policy-makers who take decisions.
The rounds model can be seen as an interactive approach (Scharpf 1997). Policies, in terms of
the actual interventions that take place in society, do not stem from an intended course of
action formulated by one actor, but result from of a series of decisions taken by dierent actors
(see Figure 23.3, from Teisman 2000).
Political scientists should be interested in the fact that many or most of the well-
designed policy proposals will never get a chance to become eective. The reason is that
public policy is not usually produced by a unitary actor with adequate control over all required
action resources and a single-minded concern for the public interest. Rather it is likely to
result from the strategic interaction among several or many policy actors, each with its own
understanding of the nature of the problem and the feasibility of particular solutions, each
with its own individual and institutional self-interest and its own normative preferences,
and each with its own capabilities or action resources that may be employed to aect the
outcome.
(Scharpf 1997: 11)
Figure 23.3 The concept of decision-making used in the stream model
Source: Teisman (2000) Models for research into decision-making processes: On phases, streams
and decision-making rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756
Research models
305
The focus, therefore, should be on the interaction among purposeful actors. To gain insight
into policy-making, the researcher depicts which actors are participating at what time. Actors
are units capable of developing a recognisable course of action (individuals, groups or collective/
corporate entities).
To separate strands of decision-making, the train of thought of the phase model is combined
with that of the stream model. On the one hand, a vertical classication of decision-making is
made, by looking at series of decisions that were taken in that time. On the other hand a horizontal
classication is applied by looking at interactions concerning the same subject, even if actors are
unaware of each others decisions at the moment they take these decisions. The division into
time periods diers from that of the phase model in a number of respects. It is not the feature of
the time period as such (i.e. this is preparation and this is implementation) that is being deter-
mined, but rather the starting and concluding points of a certain period. Such a period is called
a decision-making round. The researcher demarcates decision-making rounds by determining
the most crucial decisions of decision-making in retrospect. This concerns particularly the choice
of decisions that in a later period of decision-making serve as an important point of reference
for the behaviour of the actors that are present at the time (Teisman 1998).
The application of the rounds model yields a picture of decision-making, particularly focusing on
the ability of parties to handle their dependency on other parties in interaction (see Figure 23.4).
The tracks model of decision-making: looking at the ingredients of
interaction processes
The rounds model gives us an impression of how we can understand the intermittent development
of decision-making processes and the way in which consecutive decisions emerge. It explains
Figure 23.4 The concept of decision-making used in the rounds model
Source: Teisman (2000) Models for research into decision-making processes: On phases, streams
and decision-making rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756
Teisman and van Buuren
306
how strategies of individual actors result in collective outcomes. At the same time, it has less
relevance for the content of a decision-making process, an element which is quite central to
Kingdons streams model and is also important in the phase model when it comes to the
rational approach of policy-making and the central role of policy analysis (Quade 1972).
The tracks model emerged out of the recognition that decision-making has to do with three
ingredients brought in by participants (cf. van Buuren and Gerrits 2008). First of all, they bring
in their ambitions, based upon their material interests or normative goals. They participate because
they have something to win or lose. But second, these actors also have the opportunity to
mobilize factual evidence in favour of their ambitions (Sabatier 1988). They criticize evidence
when this is not in accordance with their point of view. Due to the fragmentation within the
knowledge domain, they do have many opportunities to mobilize counter-evidence to attack
the evidence used by formal policy initiators. But third, implicitly or explicitly, all participants in
decision-making processes do have their own problem perceptions, mental frame or belief system.
They use a specic interpretation of the problem at stake and also a specic interpretation of the
future they are convinced to be desirable (Feldman 1989). We can nd a comparable idea in
Vickers (1965) who distinguishes between action judgements, reality judgements and value
judgements.
Facts, frames and ambitions are the ingredients of interaction processes. During these inter-
action processes these ingredients evolve, merge and disappear, due to endogenous and exo-
genous developments. The evolution of these elements is inuenced by internal dynamics but
also by their mutual interaction: facts can inuence frames as can ambitions and vice versa. Actors
negotiate about which facts are authoritative, which meta-frames are constructed and which
ambitions can be combined or traded. New facts are mobilized in order to break through a
situation of frame xation and frame reection can be initiated when negotiations stagnate. The
tracks model thus analyses the evolution of these tracks separately as well as by their mutual
interaction.
Figure 23.5 The concept of decision-making used in the tracks model
Source: Author
Research models
307
From this perspective decisions are seen as (temporal and dynamic) selections of facts, frames
and ambitions. These selections are only temporary: developments within one of the tracks (for
example new facts or changing ambitions) can distort such an equilibrium and can trigger new
decisions (van Buuren and Gerrits 2008; van Buuren et al. 2009). In more consensus-oriented
decision-making processes, the extent to which there is consensus within these three tracks is an
important selection criterion, while in more adversarial processes this selection depends upon
the outcome of a power struggle between actors. Actors easily can mobilize new facts, construct
new frames or air other ambitions to challenge this equilibrium.
A comparative analysis to highlight the relative value of the four models
In the previous sections we have examined four models. The phase model provides an insight
into the subsequent stages a focal actor goes through. The stream model focuses on links between
problems, solutions and politics. The rounds model provides an insight into the interaction
between actors. Mutual adjustment (by way of co-operation, conict or avoidance) leads to policy
results (see Table 23.1). And nally, the tracks model explains the way in which the content of
decisions evolves.
In order to argue what the added value of the rounds model can be, three themes will be dealt
with. The rst looks at the issue of actors, problems and solutions, the second with policy adoption
as a yardstick, event or result and the third with criteria for the evaluation of decision-making.
Finally, the rounds model will be considered as a useful tool for developing the governance
theories further.
Table 23.1 Comparative perspectives on the phase model, the stream model and the rounds model
Phase model Stream model Rounds model Tracks model
Criteria for the
separation of
strands of
activities
Stages a focal
organization goes
through
Different concurrent
streams of
problems, solutions
and politics
Rows of decisions
taken by actors,
creating rounds
through interaction
Tracks of different
types of content,
brought in by
various actors
Characterization
of decision-
making
Sequence of
formation, adoption
and implementation
Coincidental or
organized links
between streams
Interaction between
decisions taken by
various actors
Co-evolving tracks
of fact-nding,
framing and
will-forming
Assumptions
about the
nature of the
process
One moment of
policy adoption
holds way over
other decisions and
guides the process
A simultaneous
stream of problems,
solutions and
politics, linked more
or less at random
Decisions that
conclude a round
and initiate a new
round, without
xing its progress
Decisions as
temporary
constellations of
facts, frames and
ambitions
Assumptions
about the
content of the
process
A focal actor adopts
a dominant
denition of the
problem solution,
creating
governmental
policy
Dynamics within
and links between
streams determine
major policy
changes
Interdependent
actors take decisions
separately or jointly,
leading to
governance policies
Content evolves
dynamically due to
the evolution within
and between the
three tracks
Source: Authors
Teisman and van Buuren
308
Actors, problems, solutions and interaction
It is generally accepted that various actors are involved in decision-making. The phase model,
however, places certain actors in a more central position than others on an a priori basis. The
rounds model refrains from doing this. When dealing with complexity, it is not sensible to
exclude actors in advance or to assume that certain actors can be characterized on a priori
grounds as policy designers, adopters or implementers. Rather, it is advisable to start out with all
the (potential) participants who perform in decision-making. In the rounds model, decision-
making is not about a single issue, nor about separated streams of problems, solutions and par-
ticipants, but about dynamic combinations of sets of problems and solutions represented by
dierent actors. Complications in decision-making often appear when a solution adopted by
one or more actors constitutes a problem for others. Progress is often made when a solution is
provided which deals with sets of problems and the ambitions of several of the actors involved.
For this reason the rounds model focuses on the interaction between actors, during which they
can negotiate acceptable combinations of problems and solutions. To understand this interaction
in more detail, the tracks model focuses on the evolution of the ingredients of decisions during
this interaction process.
Policy adoption, yardstick, event or result
The phase model assumes that policies are set at a certain moment. The stream model assumes
that policy streams from an event in which the streams coincide. The rounds model, in contrast,
assumes that this moment does not exist. Policies result from a series of decisions taken by
various actors. The dynamics of combining problems and solutions and the relation between the
two account for the course of decision-making. A round of decision-making begins and ends
with the adoption of a certain combination of a problem denition and a (virtual) solution by
one or more actors.
The assumption is that the actors assess to what extent other actors share their denition of
reality and proceed to interact on this basis. In contrast to the phase model, none of the de-
nitions are seen as nal or permanent. Research based on the rounds model will focus on per-
ceived problems and solutions and will subsequently analyse whether and how actors have
managed to combine perceptions to such an extent that they are willing to support a joint solution
(Termeer 1993: 44, 4851). Adoption then becomes the consolidation of a problem-solution
combination (in terms of a specic constellation of facts, frames and ambitions) over a longer
period of several decision rounds.
Policy evaluation and evaluation criteria, shifting from a government to a
governance approach
In the phase model, the public interest as dened by the focal organization is often used as
guideline for evaluation. Evaluation focuses on the t between policy result and policy for-
mulated in advance by the focal organization. The rounds model questions this criterion. Policy
intentions at the beginning of a process are not necessarily the best indicator of public interest. It
could be argued that a posteriori opinions and judgments are at least as good an indicator.
Second, it is assumed that network society as a whole, and the government in particular, are
fragmented. As a result, the representation of the public interest is distributed over various parts
of government and organizations outside the government. Policy evaluation becomes more
meaningful if all these intentions are taken into account in the analysis. A tting overall concept
Research models
309
is joint interest (Teisman 1992: 912). Evaluation then no longer focuses on the question
whether the policy result agrees with a single policy intention, but whether it is based upon
agreed facts between participants, a shared problem frame and an attractive combination of the
various ambitions, and to what extent it responds to the objectives of all the parties involved at
the moment policy eects can be distinguished.
The shift in orientation from government to governance
By doing so, the rounds model can contribute to the discussion about the shift from government
to governance within several scientic communities involved in public administration.
In response to empirical studies by Mackintosh (1977) and Jones (1975), which undermined
some of the assertions of the Westminster model, Rhodes (in Rhodes and Dunleavy 1995)
suggested a new framework of analysis. This framework should focus on the complex web of
institutions, networks and practices surrounding the prime minister, Cabinet, Cabinet committees
and their ocial counterparts, namely the less formal ministerial clubs or meetings, bilateral
negotiations, interdepartmental committees, and so on (Rhodes 1995: 12). From this insight it
was a logical next step to focus on complexity of interactions between actors (see Smith 1998:
47). Government is depicted as an institutional framework, not as an actor. Governance is about
steering without presuming the presence of hierarchy (Rosenau 1992: 14). It refers to relational
contracting, organized markets in group enterprises, clans, networks, trade associations and
strategic alliances (Jessop 1995). Departments have to be seen as one of many competing centres
of authority (Rhodes 1996a, 1996b).
It is within this perspective that the rounds and tracks model must be placed. Consideration
should be given to the idea of using the rounds model in empirical research focusing on gov-
ernance. The model oers a way to reconstruct a basically unlimited complexity of events that
can be combined into a decision-making process. This will provide us with additional, more
detailed insights into these processes, thereby creating a basis for more management theories
about networks (Kickert et al. 1997).
A fourfold analysis of the Betuwe railway line
In this section we will present an in-depth case study of decision-making processes regarding
the construction of a new freight railway line between Europes largest port, Rotterdam, and
Germany. The so-called Betuwe line is one of the most disputed projects of the last decade in
the Netherlands. The parties involved have even called it a battle.
3
Despite all the problems
and opposition, construction of the railway line is still continuing. Therefore, we may consider this
to be a successful decision-making process, in which the ministry, the cabinet and the parliament
were able to undertake a strategic project that tted in with their policies.
At the same time, however, many questions can be raised. The expected growth of freight
transport by rail did not take place. It is far from clear whether or not the German section of the
line can support the number of trains needed to make the Betuwe railway line viable. There are
no private parties that want to invest in the line or exploit it, even though this was assumed to
be the case by the cabinet when the policy was being adopted.
Studies have questioned the positive environmental impact of transport by rail compared
with that by road and waterways. The costs of the line have risen from 2.5 billion initially to
9.35 billion in 1998. Recently the transport minister decided to forgo the construction of the
Northern branch of the Betuwe line in order to avoid any further increase in expenditure. A
fourfold analysis of this case is presented below.
Teisman and van Buuren
310
Application of the phase model: a central actor, a dened problem and a
good solution
In the Netherlands, the central government, specically the Ministry of Trac and Waterways,
is responsible for the planning of new infrastructure. To properly organie decision-making, the
ministry uses a formal procedure known as the Planning Central Decision Procedure (in Dutch:
PKB). At the end of the 1980s, the ministry was faced with congestion on existing freight con-
nections from Rotterdam to the hinterland, combined with an expected growth in freight trans-
port. In previous policy memoranda, the Government had appointed the distribution sector as a
core activity for the Dutch economy. The two main Dutch ports, Schiphol Airport and the port of
Rotterdam, should be enabled to function optimally and the main transport lines should be
provided with sucient capacity. The capacity of the hinterland connection could be increased
by three dierent means: road, waterways or a new railway line. Because road trac was seen as
having a negative impact on the environment and transport by water was not seen as a viable
option, the ministry decided in 1989 that a new railway link was needed.
The ministry decided that the railway should run through the rural region of the Betuwe and a
freight line was due to be completed before 1997. To implement this policy, the ministry set up the
necessary procedures to determine the lines trajectory and its incorporation into the landscape. But
while going through these procedures, the ministry encountered opposition from civilians and local
authorities. In order to delay implementation, regional actors asked for additional studies to be car-
ried out into the possible construction of an underground tunnel. Although the ministry indicated
that this was not a realistic plan, the Second Chamber let itself be persuaded to investigate this option.
This was the signal for other parties to present the Chamber with other new alternatives, such as
the submersion of the railway line within a cutting. The involvement of parliament resulted in a
considerable series of amendments and an increase in costs. While the rst plans were expected
to cost 4 billion Dutch guilders, subsequent calculations found that with the addition of the new
line the project would have cost more than 9 million guilders. At the end of 1993 the project
was approved by parliament. Decision-making was complicated, however, by the parliamentary
elections of 1994. One supporter of the project left the cabinet and was replaced by a minister
who opposed the project. To deal with this situation, the new cabinet appointed a Committee of
Experts chaired by a member of the opposition. In January 1995 this Committee declared itself in
favour, thus persuading the opposition to revise their point of view. In early 1997 all complaints
were rejected by the Council of State. The construction works could begin.
Application of the stream model: insights into how solutions, problems and
politics come together
The rst additional insight is that the need for a freight railway line had existed long before being
placed on the cabinets political agenda in 1989. In the early 1980s this idea had already been
discussed in Rotterdam. Transport of goods to the German hinterland was only possible via road
and inland waterways. Road transport was vulnerable due to environmental restraints, while any
growth in water transport was questioned due to its rigid institutional nature. The attractive third
solution, the construction of a freight railway line, however, was at that time incompatible with
problems at the national level.
Years later, it was taken up again by the new enterprise responsible for freight transport by rails.
This organisation resulted from the division of the Dutch Railway Company, a monopoly, into
two separate companies, one for passengers and one for freight. The latter saw the railway line as a
solution to its own unprotable position. The line was dened as a prerequisite for the growth
Research models
311
of freight transport by rail. However, the political argument for it was not made, and in 1988
the Transport Ministry turned down the proposal.
Suddenly in 1989 the ministry became interested in the solution, even though its character-
istics had not changed. An explanation for this can be found within the ministry itself. It was
preparing a strategic plan for transport investments in the next decade, and became aware in 1989
that a major key project was lacking in this plan, and other projects were faced with delays. A
Ministerial Committee was set up which advised the minister to approve the Betuwe railway
line. Due to budget decits, nancial problems remained. These were solved in two ways. First,
it was assumed that it would be co-nanced by private parties, and second, that exploitation of
the line would be protable. It was this combination of problems and solutions that convinced
parliament in 1993. The policy was approved.
Application of the rounds model: additional insights into internal and
external dynamics
In the rounds model, attention is paid to streams of decisions taken by several actors. The fol-
lowing groups of actors can be distinguished: the Rotterdam Port Authority, the freight railway
company NS Cargo, the Transport Ministry, parliament, local and national environmental groups,
the German Railway Company, and the European and German governments. Five dierent
rounds are distinguished. During the rst round, which started in the beginning of the 1980s,
supporters of the Rotterdam port called for an additional freight link to the hinterland, in addition
to the existing roads and waterways. They initiated the process. The aim was to increase the
amount of transport modalities that could be used. They were less interested in the use of rail as
such, but rather in increasing the range of options. This idea was discussed locally and shelved
after some time, partly due to the negative reaction of the Chamber of Commerce in Rotter-
dam. The rst round was terminated for this reason, and it seemed as though the proposal had
disappeared into a desk drawer for good.
A second round was started in 1987 by NS Cargo. It had recently split from its parent, the
Dutch Railway Company, and was faced with a weak market position. To strengthen its posi-
tion, it proposed to build a line specically for freight transport. This had not been proposed in
the past, for the reason that no powerful actor had been responsible thus far for freight transport
by rail. In the former Dutch Railway Company freight had always been subordinate to passenger
transport. With the birth of NS Cargo the railway line had obtained its own policy entrepre-
neur. However, NS Cargo did not have the legal or nancial means to construct the railway
line and began a lobbying process. Until 1989 the ministry showed no interest.
In that year, a third round of decision-making was begun in which the ministry now played a
leading role. The line was placed high on the governments agenda and has held this position
ever since. Decision-making was accelerated had already by the minister, and one year later a con-
crete route was proposed and the fourth round of decision-making had begun. In this round the
ministry still played an important role, but was at times outclassed by Parliament. This stemmed
directly from the role played by local and regional governments and environmental groups. At
the beginning of the process, national environmental groups supported the choice in favour of
transport by rail. Due to the speeding-up of decision-making, however, and a total lack of com-
munication with local and regional governments, resistance grew quickly in 1992 and 1993, and
national environmental groups felt compelled to withdraw their support. The Betuwe line became
the Dutch example of a closed and autistic central government giving priority to the traditional
economy (port development, transport and infrastructure) instead of the environment and quality
of life, or a more modern type of economy (knowledge infrastructure, services). The ministry rejected
Teisman and van Buuren
312
all the alternatives presented by the local authorities and other groups in society. Parliament was
more accommodating, however, and a range of amendments resulted, raising the cost to almost
10 billion guilders. The Betuwe line appeared to have been approved by the government.
The fth round began with the parliamentary elections and the change in the coalition of
governing parties, as has been described above. A high-level committee (the Hermans Com-
mittee) was created to provide independent advice about the Betuwe line. This committee advised
in favour of the Betuwe line but found it dicult to formulate their advice. They received
contradictory reports from consultancy rms, and various local and regional stakeholders tried to
inuence the committee. More interesting here is that under the surface of party-political
manoeuvring, a lot of interaction was going on in terms of nancing the project, exploiting the
line when in operation and creating a European competing network of freight railway services.
These decisions would be crucial to the success of the Betuwe line.
Several rounds of decision-making were yet to come. Decisions needed to be taken about
nancial support from private sources, exploitation of the line, harmonizing European working
arrangements, and so on. These decisions would determine whether or not a parliamentary inquiry
should be set up in the next century to investigate why so much public money had been
invested in something thatwas a failure. Thus far, decision-making on this issue had already had
two important unforeseen but desired results: the expected competition by the railway forced the
inland waterways shipping sector to make institutional changes and adopt a more competitive
approach. This had already led to an enormous increase in inland shipping. Second, freight trans-
port by road was becoming ecologically more sound. Ironically, it was then argued that both
these developments made rendered Betuwe railway line superuous.
Application of the tracks model: additional insights into internal and
external dynamics
The tracks model enables us to analyse in more detail the composition of the various decisions
marking the succession of the various rounds in the decision-making process.
Within the rst round especially, the port authorities were convinced about the shortcomings
of the existing railways capacity. Their ambition to construct a railway was based upon empirical
knowledge about the weaknesses of the other possibilities: road transport and inland shipping.
This ambition matched that of the freight railway company perfectly.
However, for a long time the ministry and parliament did not recognize the urgency of the
perceived problem. Only in 1989 was the Minister of Transport convinced of the necessity to
develop better railway connections, but this was not based upon much factual evidence. The new
1980 cabinet (Christian Democrats and Socialists) decided to invest in sustainable economic growth
and support the Betuwe line project. A breakthrough was came about by framing the Betuwe
line in such a way that it was compatible with the policy of sustainable economic growth.
After two years of further investigation, the Dutch parliament hesitated to ratify the Planning
Central Decision Procedure. A second opinion was sought and compensatory measures proposed
to meet the wishes of local and regional stakeholders. Parliament only approved the Betuwe
line after combining its main policy with a number of regional policies.
The Hermans Committee brought together much additional factual evidence but advised again
in favour of the Betuwe line. Increasingly the line was framed as a long-term strategic invest-
ment and as the only viable alternative for the harmful environmental impact of the existing
means of transport. This advice was an important building block for parliament to ratify the deci-
sion to start constructing the Betuwe line. Five years later, doubts arose about the short-term
eectiveness of the Betuwe line, and it came to be regarded as a potential planning disaster.
Research models
313
Table 23.2 Events in decision-making on the Betuwe line and a fourfold research result
Empirical events Interpretations based on
the phase model
Interpretations based on
the stream model
Interpretations based on
the rounds model
Interpretations based on
the tracks model
The Rotterdam Port
Authority proposes a
railway link to Germany
(1985)
Irrelevant
(Ministry did not respond to
proposal)
Solution was unable to nd a
problem and sufcient
participants
Start of rst round; the port
authority aims to increase the
range of transport modalities
Based upon a strong interest to
remain competitive, port
authorities perceive hinterland
connections as insufcient
New enterprise for railway
freight transport adopts
Betuwe railway line (1987)
Lobbying activity resulting in
a ministerial committee in
1989 (still not relevant)
Problem of a lack of prot
was combined with the
solution of a new line
The start of second round of
decision-making, aiming to
create a viable freight train
enterprise
Private ambitions are connected
and stakeholders starts to work on
a convincing factual underpinning
and problem frame
A ministerial committee
is set up to investigate the
viability of the Betuwe line
(1989/1990)
Minister begins
decision-making by setting
up a committee (starting
point for analyses)
The department is faced with
a lack of major key projects
in its new strategic plan
Start of third round leading to
the adoption of the project as
part of the strategic plan of the
ministry
Ambition of cabinet to invest in
sustainable growth is connected to
problem frame of Betuwe line
coalition
The minister points out a
concrete route (1992),
starts Planning Central
Decision Procedure and
organizes popular
participation
The ofcial start of the
Planning Central Decision
Procedure
(policy formation)
Choosing a concrete route
was seen by the policy
community as a solution to
solve the problem of slow
decision-making
Start of fourth round, aiming to
speed up decision-making, but
actually generating and
activating opposition against
project
The EIA and positive transport
scenarios contribute to the
problem frame that railway
connections are the weak link
Parliament adopts proposal
(1993)
Central decision is taken
(policy adopted)
Coupling of problem, solution
and participants
End of fourth round Parliament accepts Betuwe line
based upon second opinion and
with compensatory measures
Parliamentary elections
resulting in a new Cabinet
(1994)
The central decision is
reconsidered in an opaque
political arena
Second coupling in which
new participants introduce
new policy denitions
Fifth round helps party to
change position and used by
societal groups to get additional
proposal accepted
Hermans Committee decides to
use data about existing capacity to
advise in favour of Betuwe line.
Parliament enforces additional
compensatory measures
Table 23.2 (continued)
Empirical events Interpretations based on
the phase model
Interpretations based on
the stream model
Interpretations based on
the rounds model
Interpretations based on
the tracks model
The Administrative Court
overrules all written
objections (1997)
Ofcial start of construction
activities; the implementation
really starts
Conrmation of the existing
coupling between political,
policy and problem stream
In sixth round, opponents
activate potential coalition in
business, criticizing added
value of project
New factual evidence fuels framing
of Betuwe line as potential
planning disaster but is not
combined with powerful
ambitions that can alter new
ofcial frame in which Betuwe line
is strategic choice for the
long-term.
The Cabinet decides not
to build the northern
branch of the Betuwe
railway line (1999)
Partial policy termination due
to new information
New linking of politics with
alternative problems or
solutions
In seventh round, minister is
convinced by inuential actors
that public money is needed
elsewhere.
New insights in the added value of
the northern branch and local
resistance against it, contribute to
the decision not to build this
branch
Source: Authors
There was also erce regional resistance. All these considerations led to the decision not to go
ahead with the construction of the northern branch.
Conclusion
Decision-making has become increasingly complex during the past decades. There is a growing
variety of relevant actors and denitions of problems and solutions. In this chapter the question
of how to conceptualize decision-making in order to generate useful insights for the under-
standing of complex dynamics in decision-making processes has been answered. Four con-
ceptual models were presented: the phase model; the stream model; the rounds model; and the
tracks model. In the phase model, the focus is on decisions taken by a focal actor, targeting a
specic problem. In the stream model, the focus is on the linking of three more or less inde-
pendent streams, namely problems, solutions and politics. The rounds model focuses on the
interaction between the various decisions taken by dierent actors. And nally, the tracks model
claries how decisions are composed out of specic selections of facts, frames and ambitions,
where the separate tracks evolve erratically due to internal and external dynamics. If we analyse
reality from these four models, dierent images of reality are obtained, each of which provides a
partial insight into reality.
Thanks to the use of the phase model, we now know a great deal about how a single actor
denes policy in terms of problems and solutions, policy adoption, implementation and eva-
luation. Attention is paid to a focal actor, often the central government, and the way in which
this central actor organizes its own policy processes. The phase model focuses mainly on the
intended policy of this focal actor. This is both its strength and its weakness. The case study on
the Betuwe railway line presents a national government that is dedicated to the project and was
able to defend it successfully against outside attacks.
The stream model concerns the fragmentation of the decision-making world into problems,
solutions and politics as separate streams. If these streams come together by chance, progress can
be made. It is not the intended policy of one actor, but the links between the streams that are
crucial. The case study shows that dierent problems were linked to the Betuwe line solution.
The lack of alternative solutions was an important reason for this project being placed on the
central governments agenda. New fundraising initiatives are still a threat to the project.
The rounds model focuses on the interaction between interdependent actors. Every new actor
entering decision-making introduces new problems and solutions. Particularly on these points,
the rounds model oers a number of additional possibilities to enhance insight into decision-
making. By not just accepting that there are various actors, but also accepting that all these actors
contribute to the decision-making process and can even inuence the results of this process
helps to explain the complexity and gain insight into interaction patterns which are used for
governance of the network society. The model emphasizes that achieving satisfactory results
depends not only upon decisions taken by individual actors, but to an increasing extent upon
the interaction between decisions taken by several actors. By using the rounds model, the researcher
can analyse the interactions between decisions. All actors involved in governance can benet
from these insights.
As a further elaboration of this model, the tracks model highlights the evolution of the content
of decision-making within the various rounds. It focuses upon the question: what is exchanged
in the various interactions between actors? By distinguishing between facts, frames and ambi-
tions and by analysing the way they inuence each other, we enrich our understanding of how
the results of decision-making processes are formed out of the complex interaction between a
variety of partial and sometimes partisan knowledge claims, subjective problem perceptions and
Teisman and van Buuren
316
competing or complementary interests. Because of the fact that it combines attention to develop-
ment in actor ambitions with attention to knowledge dynamics and framing/learning processes, it
goes one step beyond traditional models which normally focus on only one or two of these issues.
New insights on traces, tracks, time lines and process systems indicate the need for a model
able to accommodate a wider perspective.
Notes
1 This is an updated and extended version of Geert R. Teisman (2000) Models for research into decision-
making processes: On phases, streams and decision-making rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756.
2 In this article we will not deal with the question of evaluation.
3 Between 1991 and 1997 the project director wrote a book on the subject entitled Slag om de Betuwe
Route (The Battle of the Betuwe Line) (Boom 1997).
Bibliography
Anderson, J. 1979. Public Policy Making. New York: Praeger.
Altman, J.A. and E. Petkus. 1994. Towards a stakeholder-based policy process: an application of the social
marketing perspective to environmental policy development, Policy Sciences 27: 3751.
Anglund, S.M. 1999. Policy feedback: The comparison eect and small business procurement policy,
Policy Studies Journal 27(1): 1127.
Bache, I. and M.V. Flinders. 2004. Multilevel Governance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boom, H. 1977. Slag om de Betuwe Route. Leuven: Balans.
Börzel, T.A. 1998. Organizing Babylon: On the dierent conceptions of policy networks, Public Administration
765: 25373.
Bryson, J.M. and B.C. Crosby. 1992. Leadership for the Common Good, Tackling Public Problems in a Shared-Power
World. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Butler, R. 1991. Designing Organizations: A Decision-making Perspective. London: Routledge.
Cohen, M.D, J.G. March and J.P. Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational choice, Administrative
Science Quarterly 17(1): 125.
Crozier, M. and E. Friedberg. 1980. Actors and Systems: The Politics of Collective Action. Chicago: University
Press.
Duit, A. and V. Galaz. 2006. Governance and complexity: Emerging issues for governance theory, Governance
23(3): 1135.
Dunleavy, P. and Gillian Peel (eds). 1990. Developments in British Politics 3. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Edelman, M. 1971. The Symbolic Uses of Politics: Mass Arousal and Quiescence. Chicago: Markham Publishers.
Feldman, Martha. 1989. Order Without Design: Information Production and Policy Making. 1st edn. Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press.
Fischer, F. 2003. Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative Practices. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Gerrits, L. 2008. The Gentle Art of Coevolution: A Complexity Theory Perspective on Decision Making over
Estuaries in Germany, Belgium and the Netherlands. Rotterdam: Erasmus University.
Hanf, K. and F.W. Scharpf (eds). 1978. Interorganizational Policy Making: Limits to Co-ordination and Central
Control. London: Sage.
Haynes, Philip. 2008. Complexity theory and evaluation in public management, Public Management
Review 10(3): 40119.
Heclo,
H. 1974. Modern Social
Politics in Britain and Sweden: From Relief to Income Maintenance. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
Heritier, A., C. Knill and S. Mingers. 1996. Ringing the Changes in Europe: Regulatory Competition and
Redenition of the State. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Hoogerwerf, A. (ed.). [1982, 1985]1989. Public Policy: An Introduction to the Policy Science (Overheidsbeleid:
een inleiding in de beleidswetenschap), 2nd, 3rd, and 4th edns. Alphen a/d Rijn: Samsom Tjeenk Willink.
Jessop, B. 1995. The regulation approach, governance and post-Fordism, Economy and Society 24, 30733.
Jones, G. 1975. Development of the Cabinet, in W. Thornhill (ed.) The Modernisation of British Government.
London: Pitman.
Research models
317
Judge, D. 1993. The Parliamentary State. London: Sage.
Kingdon, J.W. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Kickert, W., E.-H. Klijn and J. Koppenjan. 1997. Managing Complex Networks. London: Sage.
Koppenjan, J. 1984. Management of Policy Processes (Management van de beleidsvorming). The Hague: Vuga.
Lindblom, Charles E. and Edward J. Woodhouse. 1992. The Policy Making Process, 3rd edn. Englewood
Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Mackintosh, J.P. 1977. The Politics and Government of Britain. London: Hutchinson.
March, J.G. 1988. Decisions and Organisations. Oxford: Blackwell.
—— and J.P. Olsen. [1976]1979. Ambiguity and Choice in Organisations, 1st and 2nd edns. Bergen:
Universitetsforlaget.
Marin, B. and R. Mayntz (eds). 1991. Policy Networks: Empirical Evidence and Theoretical Considerations.
Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.
Mintzberg, H. 1973. The Nature of Managerial Work. New York: Harper & Row.
—— 1976. Planning on the left side and managing on the right, Harvard Business Review 54: 4958.
——, D. Raisinghani and A. Therot. 1976. The structure of unstructured decision processes, Administrative
Science Quarterly 21(2): 24675.
Morgan, G. 1997. Images of Organisation, 2nd edn. London: Sage.
Ostrom, E. 1990. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Quade, Edward S. 1972. Analysis for Public Policy Decisions. New York: Rand Corporation.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 1995. From prime ministerial power to core executive, in R.A.W. Rhodes and P. Dunleavy
(eds) Prime Minister, Cabinet and Core Executive. London: Macmillan.
—— 1996a. Governing without governance: Order and change in British government, inaugural lecture,
University of Newcastle, 18 April.
—— 1996b. The new governance: Governing without government, Political Studies 44: 65267
——and P. Dunleavy (eds). 1995. Prime Minister, Cabinet and Core Executive. London: Macmillan.
Rittel, H.W.J. and M.M. Webber. 1973. Dilemmas in a general theory of planning, Policy Sciences 4:
15569.
Rosenau,
J. 1992. Governance, order
and change in world politics, in J.N. Rosenau and E.O. Czempiel
(eds) Governance without Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sabatier, P.A. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy-oriented
learning therein, Policy Sciences 21(23): 12968.
—— 1999. Theories of the Policy Process, Colorado: Westview Press.
Sato, H. 1999. The advocacy coalition framework and the policy process analysis: The case of smoking
control in Japan, Policy Studies Journal 27(1): 2844.
Scharpf, F. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor-centered Institutionalism in Policy Research. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press.
——, B. Reissert and F. Schnabel. 1978. Policy eectiveness and conict avoidance, in Hanf, K. and
F.W. Scharpf (eds) Interorganizational Policy Making: Limits to Co-ordination and Central Control. London:
Sage.
Schön, D.A. and M. Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies,
New York: BasicBooks.
Smith, M.J. 1998. Reconceptualizing the British state: Theoretical and empirical challenges to central
government, Public Administration 76(1): 4572.
——, D. March and D. Richards. 1993. Central government departments and the policy process. Public
Administration 71: 56794.
Strand, R. 2002. Complexity, ideology, and governance, Emergence 4(12): 16483.
Teisman, G.R. [1992, 1995]1998. Complex Decision-making, A Pluricentric View (Complexe Besluitvorming),
1st, 2nd, and 3rd edns. The Hague: Vuga.
—— 2000. Models
for research into decision-making processes: On phases, streams and decision-making
rounds, Public Administration 78(4): 93756.
——with
E.H. Klijn. 1997. Strategies and games in networks, in W. Kickert, E.H. Klijn and J. Koppenjan
(eds) Managing Complex Networks. London: Sage, pp. 98118.
——and E.H. Klijn. 2002. Partnership arrangements: Governmental rhetoric or governance schema?,
Public Administration Review 62(2): 197205.
——, A. van Buuren, and L. Gerrits. 2009. Managing Complex Governance Systems, Dynamics, Self-Organization
and Coevolution in Public Investments. London: Routledge
Teisman and van Buuren
318
Termeer, C. 1993. Dynamics and Inertia in Manure Policy (Dynamiek en inertie in mestbeleid). The Hague:
Vuga.
van Bueren, E.M., E.H. Klijn, and J.F.M. Koppenjan. 2003. Dealing with wicked problems in networks:
Analyzing an environmental debate from a network perspective, Journal of Public Administration Research
and Theory 13(2): 193212.
van Buuren, A. 2006. Competent Decision-making. Making Multiple Knowledge for Spatial Development (in
Dutch), Boom/Lemma, Den Haag.
——and L. Gerrits. 2008. Decisions as dynamic equilibriums in erratic policy processes, Public Management
Review 10(3): 281399.
——, A. Gerrits, P. Marks. 2009. Public policy-making and the management of co-evolution, in Ties-
man, G., van Buuren, A., Gerrits, L. (eds) Managing Complex Governance Systems, London: Routledge,
134153.
van Herk, S., C. Zevenbergen, J. Rijke, and R. Ashley. 2011. Collaborative research to support transition
towards integrating ood risk management in urban development, Journal of Flood Risk Management
4(4): 30617.
Vickers, Sir Georey. 1965. The Art of Judgment: A Study of Policy Making. New York: Basic Books.
Wagenaar, H. 2007. Governance, complexity, and democratic participation: How citizens and public
ocials harness the complexity of neighborhood decline, The American Review of Public Administration
37: 1750.
Research models
319
24
The garbage can model and the
study of the policy-making process
Gary Mucciaroni
Origins and description of the GCM
Kingdon imported the garbage can model (GCM) into political science and adapted it to study
public policy-making from the seminal work of Cohen et al. (1972) who used the garbage
can metaphor to describe decision-making in universities and other complex organizations. As
Nikolaos Zahariadis (2007: 66) points out, the GCM theorizes at the systemic level, and it
incorporates an entire system or separate decision as the unit of analysis. Kingdon applied the
GCM to the study of the federal government and conducted panel interviews with more than
240 participants in the policy-making process, primarily in the areas of transportation and health
policies. Borrowing from Cohen et al., Kingdon described the federal agenda-setting process as
a mix of order and chaos, or organized anarchy. The can is the set of more permanent and
predictable features of the policy-making process, such as institutional arrangements and
procedures that shape and structure behavior.
The main focus of the GCM, however, is on the garbage in the can because the items that reach
the agenda at any given time arise out of the mix of contents in the can. The cans contents consist
of three streams”—“problems,”“solutions and politics, which operate largely independent of
one another. According to Kingdon (1984: 93), an issue reaches the agenda when a problem is
recognized, a solution is available, and the political climate makes the time right for change. Policy-
makers and others recognize problems when social indicators, such as crime or unemployment rates,
indicate that an undesirable condition is worsening or reaching a critical threshold, or, when a
focusing event”—a salient and usually dramatic episode or crisisdraws attention to the problem
and lends it a sense of urgency. Solutions include the gradual accumulation of knowledge and
perspectives among specialists in any given area. Specialists generate and disseminate solutions,
provide evidence and arguments in support of them that are intelligible to non-specialists, and help
to package them into concrete proposals. Politics refers to the wide variety of actors and forces
that constitute the political environment, including the national mood, the organization and
mobilization of interest groups and social movements, the partisan and ideological composition of
Congress and the executive branch, and other aspects of the political context in which agendas are set.
The streams operate largely independently because dierent groups of people or forces control
each of them. Problems come and go given changing conditions in the world, without regard
320
for either the status of solutions that might address the problems or the state of the political
context. Groups of experts and advocates conceive, develop and disseminate solutions over the
long-term, without necessarily reacting to the immediacy of problems or the tenor of the political
environment. And political change is governed by processes, like elections, budgeting, and the
mobilization of interests that operate on their own schedules and trajectories.
An item (problem or solution) reaches the agenda (or is adopted) only when the three streams
are aligned properly. Problem X or solution Y will not get on the agenda (or be chosen) unless
the problem is recognized, a solution is considered to be available, and political conditions are
conducive for giving the problem and solution serious attention. If any of these three elements
is missing, the item will not get on the agenda (or the policy adopted). Problem recognition,
solution availability and political opportunity, thus, each constitute necessary conditions for an
item to reach the agenda (or a policy adoption).
At particular junctures, a policy entrepreneur with a commitment to a particular issue and the
ability to draw attention to it, will couple a problem with a solution. Entrepreneurs wait for an
auspicious time, such as after a dramatic focusing event and when Congress and the president are
controlled by ocials who are interested in addressing the issue. These policy windows often
open unpredictably and only for a short while. Thus, entrepreneurs must act expeditiously and
eciently to get their pet item on the agenda (or get it adopted) before the window closes,
when the political environment changes and attention shifts to other issues.
Criticisms and limitations of the GCM
Scholars have pointed to a number of important problems and deciencies with the GCM. In
this section, we review several of these criticisms.
Falsiability. The model, at least as a whole, is not falsiable. Can we imagine a set of cir-
cumstances in which some condition in society was not considered a problem receiving serious
consideration in government? Or, a situation in which an item got on the agenda (or a policy
adopted) even though the political environment was not favorable to getting it on? Since the
agenda, by denition, is composed of conditions that some key group of decision-makers con-
siders problems, it would be impossible for non-problematic conditions to get on the agenda.
Since the political environment refers to those actors who are in power or who have inuence
over those in power, a problem or solution could not receive serious attention unless they
permitted it. Non-falsiability arises, as in most cases, because the model is formulated very broadly
and ambiguously. One strategy for making the model more falsiable would be to develop
categories of problems, solutions and political contexts from which we could derive testable
hypotheses about how particular kinds of problems and solutions reach the agenda given the
existence of particular political conditions (Mucciaroni 1992: 4635).
Bendor et al. (2001) have critiqued the original GCM developed by Cohen et al. (1972),
arguing that the model is more like a metaphor than a model. As a result, many applications of
the GCM do little more than describe some parts of an organization as garbage cans but it
is not at all clear that they provide real explanations. According to them, the GCM merely
provides a scheme for describing and labeling phenomena without explaining them.
Situational versus structural levels of analysis. Before we can model agenda-setting, we need to be
clear about what we are trying to explain related to agendas. It makes a great deal of dierence
whether we are asking why certain items reach the agenda at particular moments in time versus
why certain items reach the agenda ever. The GCM is better at explaining when the agenda
changes than explaining how and why the agenda changes. Much of the reason that the GCM is
better at explaining the timing of agenda (or policy) change rather than give a full accounting of
The garbage can model
321
it, arises because the model conceptualizes constraints on agenda-setting (or decision-making)
mainly at what I call the situational level of analysisaspects of the policy-making environment
that are relatively temporary and changeable. Problems (e.g. crime, airline safety) get hot and
then cool o as attention drifts to other problems and new crises. Solutions (e.g. the at tax,
deregulation) snowball into fads but eventually turn stale and their popularity fades. Congres-
sional majorities and presidential administrations come and go every two, four, or eight years;
the public mood varies with the vagaries of the economy and other conditions. But political
actors and forces that are more permanent, that change slowly or hardly at all from decade to decade,
also shape agendas and decisions. It would be as much of a mistake to overlook the impact of
these forces on agendas and policy decisions as it would be to ignore the impact of old age or
genetics on human health.
One of kind of structural constraint is culture, political traditions and dominant ideologies.
For example, the problems of anti-gay discrimination and poverty were o the agenda for many
decades before they appeared in the 1960s in the case of poverty, and after 1970 in the case of
gay rights. They were kept o the agenda by deeply ingrained, taken-for-granted beliefs that
either nothing could be done about poverty or that it was the result of personal failings and that
discrimination against gays was justied because they were sick,”“predators, or sinners.
Similarly, institutional arrangements hinder and facilitate problems and solutions from reaching
the agenda. For example, during the Great Depression of the 1930s, policy-makers in some
countries considered Keynesianism a plausible solution to the crisis while those in other nations
did not. But whether Keynesian ideas became accepted partly depended upon which institutions
had responsibility for making economic policy and whether institutions provided Keynesian
economists with access to decision-makers (Hall 1989; Skocpol and Weir 1985). And some
solutions have a bad t with particular institutions. For example, regardless of the backgrounds
of particular judges, or other relatively uid conditions, solutions that do not t into the logic of
legal reasoning and the language of rights may not get a hearing or may be rejected.
Kingdon was aware of the importance of structural features of the policy-making process. He
mentions, for example, that the budget process has particular procedures and timetables that
constrain agenda-setting, and that American political culture lters out solutions that are incompa-
tible with it before they can reach the agenda. The problem is that the GCM does not theorize
structural constraints, leaving them largely outside its parameters. Because they are not incorpo-
rated in the model, the GCM is signicantly incomplete. Admittedly, all models are incomplete,
but these are large omissions in light of the GCMs theoretical ambitions.
Lack of historical causality. Much of what happens in the policy-making process, how it hap-
pens, and to whom, is in some fashion rooted in the past. The GCM neglects much of history
because it focuses solely upon immediate or near-term changes in problems, solutions, and
politics. Kingdon justies overlooking historical explanations for agenda and policy change on
the grounds that historical investigation would simply lead us down a fruitless path of innite
regress: in searching for the relevant antecedent events and conditions that shaped the agenda,
we would be compelled to search for the antecedents to the more proximate antecedents, and
so forth, endlessly. Tracing historically relevant antecedents to explain later choices and condi-
tions need not, of course, end up being a slippery slope into an unceasing quest for initial
causes. If that were the case, historical studies would be impossible.
The lack of historical perspective contributes to the overall randomness of the GCM. With-
out examining antecedent choices and conditions that might have given rise to, or facilitated, a
problem or solution from getting on the agenda, many items seem to appear and disappear
unpredictably and suddenly. Problems may indeed suddenly
get hot but
the problems them-
selves and the reasons they come to be perceived as problems are rooted historically. For
Mucciaroni
322
example, under the GCM, we might observe that unemployment rises sharply within a few
months and that the public and policy-makers take notice. But whether we regard unemploy-
ment as a problem suitable for government attention, how high unemployment must be to be
considered unacceptably high, and why the rate went up, we can only understand adequately
in historical perspective. Similarly, to understand why supply-side tax cuts became perceived
as a plausible solution to unemployment or sluggish economic growth, one has to have some
historical understanding of the evolution of economists theories and opinions, in what sense
American economists came to understand Keynesianism, its rise and fall as a theory and policy
prescription, and the lessons that economists and others drew from experiences with previous
eorts to cut taxes. It is not enough to know that at a particular point in time Keynesianism
came to be seen as a solution to a particular economic problem. We want to know why and how
it became a viable solution.
Items often reach the agenda and come up for decision because past eorts to put them there
have failed or never materialized. Or, a problem reached the agenda and a policy was adopted
to address it, which in turn, gave rise to new problems that eventually gained agenda status.
Scholars working from a historical perspective have developed a number of concepts to help us
to understand history as a causal process. The development and dissemination of solutions, for
example, is often done through learning and lesson-drawing, which occur over time (Heclo 1975;
Rose 1991). Public policies are also often the product of critical junctures, which produce
distinct legacies that would not have occurred if the critical juncture had not occurred (Collier
and Collier 1991). Alternatively, the legacies may be the result of antecedent conditions and
constant causes that predated the hypothesized critical juncture and account for the legacy.
Policymaking is also subject to path dependency. Political events and policy choices at one point in
time often put nations and organizations on particular trajectories that close out or reduce the
probability of making other choices in the future because the original events and choices create
dominant frames, institutions and interests that become entrenched long after the conditions
that established the path have ended (Pierson 2000).
The criticism that the GCM is insuciently grounded in historical analysis would be less
problematic if the model was considered exclusively a model of agenda-setting. Since an agenda
is conventionally dened as consisting of those items that a government (or set of decision-
makers in any complex organization) gives serious attention at a point in time, paying attention
only to contemporary, immediate, situational factors is understandable. An organizations atten-
tion to particular problems is usually short-term and often intermittent. But if we extend the
GCM beyond agenda-setting to policy formulation and adoption, as many scholars have done, we
have a harder time justifying the lack of historical analysis and appreciation of structural con-
straints. Policy-making is more than attention-getting and a deeper understanding must go
beyond situational factors.
Randomness and the separation of the streams: Probably the most frequent criticism of the GCM
is that it portrays decision-making as overly chaotic and random. Even defenders and users of
the GCM admit that the model shares common ground with chaos theories in being attentive
to complexity, in assuming a considerable amount of residual randomness, and in viewing systems
as constantly evolving and not necessarily settling into equilibrium (Zahariadis 2007: 66). The
feature of the GCM that contributes most to the models randomness is the assumption the
loose and independent relationship exists among the three separate streams. While changes within
each stream reect purposive behavior and patterns, the core of the modelthe simultaneous
occurrence of a salient problem, available solution and favorable political conditionsgives rise
to outcomes that are largely fortuitous and unpredictable. The coupling of the three streams is a
purposive, non-random process, but it occurs after the alignment of the three streams. Kingdon
The garbage can model
323
(1984: 93) stipulated that only hints of connection existed among the streams. But is the lack
of connectedness among the streams justied? An alternative model would stress the importance
of changes in one stream contributing to changes in the others and would trace out the inter-
actions and interdependencies among the streams. Pursuing an approach in which the streams
were more interconnected would reduce the currently high level of indeterminacy and ran-
domness in the GCM and uncover a greater degree of behavior that is collaborative, purposive,
and strategic. Indeed, those items that reach the agenda may be precisely those that exhibit
stronger linkages and congruence among the streams, where advocates and their allies do not
leave congruence to chance, but actively promote it. In this model, changes in one stream give
rise to and reinforce changes in the others, increasing the probability that entrepreneurs will
attempt to couple the streams and that their eorts will succeed.
Perhaps the closest links are those between solutions and politics. Solutions that reach the
agenda are those that have a good t with policy-makers goals, such as reelection, inuence,
and promoting the adoption of good policy (Fenno 1973). Obviously, policy-makers choose
solutions that have the best chance of promoting their goals. At the same time, experts and
advocates craft and promote their favorite solutions with at least some attention to policy-
makers goals. The type of policy or program promoted, its specic provisions, the evidence and
arguments mustered for it, how it is packaged and framed––all are geared toward building support,
muting opposition, and persuading the undecided and ambivalent that the proposed course of
action is desirable, or at least plausible. Since policy-makers goals are usually often broad, and
their views on how to achieve them are malleable, those who advocate on behalf of particular
solutions have some room to persuade them.
Politics and problems are also closely connected. Perhaps the best-known example of this
phenomenon is when incumbent politicians are ousted from oce, or threatened with being
outsted, when economic indicators, particularly the unemployment rate, worsen or fail to
improve during a recession. Many less salient examples also exist. For example, when fuel prices
rose sharply in the mid-1970s, businesses that shipped their goods by truck, including farmers,
manufacturers and many other businesses, formed a coalition with liberal consumer groups to
push for trucking deregulation (Robyn 1987: 967, 2345). In other cases, previous policy
choices create new problems or exacerbate existing ones that, in turn, create political opportu-
nities for elected ocials. For example, the creation of very generous tax loopholes in 1981
resulted in large revenue losses. By the mid-1980s, a bipartisan coalition emerged in favor of
closing the loopholes and converting them into across-the-board rate cuts for taxpayers gen-
erally (Conlan et al. 1990). Republicans regained control of the House and made gains in the
Senate in the 2010 elections because the combination of a devastating recession, war spending
and growing entitlement spending created a debt crisis that allowed Republicans to push debt
reduction as the central issue on the agenda after the election. In both cases, the perceived wor-
sening of problems contributed to conditions that were conducive to getting the problems on
the agenda.
Finally, problems and solutions are linked. The GCM rightly uncovered instances when,
counterintuitively, experts developed solutions before they found the problems to which they
were eventually applied. At the same time, experts often develop solutions with very clear pro-
blems in mind at the outset and their linkage of a solution to that particular problem often
carries through the policy-making process. Both patterns are at work, perhaps often in the same
proposal. For example, the original rationale that tax experts in the Treasury Department put
forward the argument for reforming the tax code (by reducing the number of special provisions
in the code reducing taxpayers liability) was to increase the fairness of the income tax. Eventually,
policy-makers and others took up reform to address other problems (the complexity of the code
Mucciaroni
324
and economic ineciency created by distorted market incentives), but the original problem that
the experts were trying to address endured as a principal rationale for reform.
Problems and solutions are linked in more subtle ways as well. As problems get worse,
plausible solutions become attractive and are more likely to gain agenda status. Solutions that
might have a harder time getting political support (for any number of reasons) when a problem
is perceived to be under control or imposing only modest costs, will have an easier time as the
problem worsens and the expected windfall from applying the solution grows. In the tax reform
example again, as the problems of unfairness, revenue loss, complexity and ineciency grew, so
did the attractiveness of closing the loopholes because the costs of the existing policy rose at the
same time that the expected benet from closing the loopholes also rose (in the form of lower
tax rates, for example).
Studies that have employed the GCM after Kingdon
As of June 25, 2011, Google Scholar registered 6,650 citations for Kingdons Agendas book.
1
Many of the citations are from political science and policy studies as well as other disciplines,
elds and professions. At the same time, according to Bendor et al. (2001), the GCM is not used
extensively in political science research or in related disciplines. Indeed, the number of studies in
public policy that actually use the GCM or test hypotheses derived from it is surprisingly small
given the attention that Kingdons book received and its status as a staple on public policy syl-
labi. Zahariadis (2007: 79) acknowledges that the GCM, or multiple streams model, as he
prefers to call it, does appear to be an argument that many scholars quote but few explicitly
use. Bendor et al. attribute the GCMs relative lack of use in empirical studies to weaknesses in
the model that render it a poor theoretical guide for research. Zahariadis counters that the problem
has more to do with paradigmatic problems that have plagued the model. Following Sabatier
(1999), he suggests a number of reasons for why the GCM does not guide empirical research in
policy studies more frequently: the models principal proponent and popularizerKingdon
did not vigorously promote its usage; many people consider the GCM only relevant for under-
standing agenda-setting rather than policy formulation and adoption; and, researchers working
on subnational levels of government identify the GCM with agenda-setting at the national level.
These reasons are plausible. Kingdon retired from academe not that long after he published the
second edition of his book. And, in conning the application of the GCM to the agenda-setting
stage, Kingdon may have limited its perceived relevance given that conceptualizing the policy
process as a set of distinct stages may be a useful heuristic device, but not very realistic.
The GCM has appeared prominently in a modest number of public policy studies that came
after Kingdon s book was published. Most of these works have sought to broaden the applicability
of the GCM (or elements of it), rene its central concepts, and use it to interpret case study nd-
ings. Zahariadis, for example, has sought to show how the GCM (or multiple streams model,
as he prefers to call it) is useful for understanding policy-making outside the United States, speci-
cally the privatization of public enterprises in Britain and France (1995) and Greek foreign
policy (2005). An important aim of Zahariadiss (1995, 9) study of privatization was to extend the
GCM beyond agenda-setting, to the entire process of policy formulation and decision-making.
Zahariadis argues that Cohen, March and Olsen formulated the GCM originally to explain decision-
making, not just agendas, and that agenda-setting, policy formulation and decision-making are
integrally related. These arguments are sensible, but extending the GCM to the policy-making
process as a whole makes it even harder to maintain the notion that problems, solution, and politics
are largely separate until a nal coupling. Once an item reaches the agenda, it is implausible to
believe that the independence of streams remains relevant during policy formulation and
The garbage can model
325
decision-making. Unless we are trying to answer the narrow question of why did policy-makers
make any decision rather than none at all? the GCM would nd it dicult to explain why policy-
makers decided on one specic policy and rejected others. Second, extending the GCM beyond
agenda-setting does nothing to ameliorate other problems with the model, such as its failure to
ground its explanations suciently in the historical and structural aspects of policy-making.
Framing his explanation in terms of the coming together of the three streams of the GCM,
Zahariadis (1995) argues that Britain and France adopted privatization when the following con-
ditions converged: (1) policy-makers perceived the solutionselling o state-owned enter-
prisesas technically feasible and compatible with their values; (2) social indicators revealed a
problemthat government budgets were under stress and the public was resistant to new taxes;
and (3) the occurrence of a key change in the political environmentthe rise to power of
political parties that were not identied with public enterprise and that possessed the ideological
commitment and political capacity to work to end it. In some of cases, as Kingdon had found
earlier, specialists developed the solution (privatization) before the specic problem for which it
eventually was adopted had emerged.
In trying to account for Greek foreign policy-making over the span of ve years on the issue
of Macedonia, Zahariadis (2005) argues that the GCM is more useful than two other explana-
tory frameworks (rational internationalism and two-level games). The substance of Zahar-
iadiss explanation focuses on the importance of policy elites manipulation of emotive symbols
and domestic politics on foreign policy decisions. If the manipulation of emotion and con-
siderations of domestic politics are what matter in his explanation of Greed policy, then the
need for the GCM in Zahariadiss account is not readily apparent. According to Zahariadis
(2005: 172), as multiple streams [i.e. GCM] hypotheses, domestic agendas make a big dier-
ence in the making of foreign policy. But what rationale exists for equating the GCM (or
multiple streams) with domestic politics? And again, how does the GCM contribute to an
explanation that the variables emotion and domestic politics do not already contribute on
their own? A compelling case that the GCM helps to explain Greek foreign policy would
require showing how elements of the GCM are essential causal mechanisms that facilitate or
shape the inuence of emotion and domestic politics on foreign policy.
McLendon (2003) employed the GCM in his study of how the issue of higher education
decentralization reached the agenda in the US states in the 1980s and 1990s. He compared the
GCM with incremental and rational-comprehensive theories of policy-making to assess their
usefulness for explaining how the issue reached the agenda and for elucidating which actors in
the policy-making process exerted the most inuence. Analyzing an eclectic mix of data,
including 61 semi-structured interviews, from in-depth case studies of three states, McLendon
found that agenda setting on this issue resembled the GCM far more than the other two
models. Like Kingdon, McLendon found clarity, order and pattern within the structure of
each stream, and at the same time, elements
of ambiguity, anarchy
and unpredictability in
the specic coupling of problems, solutions and politics. He also found support for several of
the features of the GCM as Kingdon formulated them: dierent streams of activity that exhib-
ited a surprising degree of independence (though they were not entirely unrelated); con-
ict over autonomy and control within the education policy domain was weakly connected to
the reasons that decentralization reached the agenda; the development of the decentralization
solution occurred before, not in response to, the problem policy-makers eventually addressed;
the rapid, non-incremental movement of the issue to the top of the agenda; and the signicant
role of policy entrepreneurs in helping to push the item on to the agenda.
Instead of employing the entire GCM, other studies have explored and elaborated upon
particular elements of it. Birkland (1997: 2004) has claried and developed the concept of
Mucciaroni
326
focusing events and investigated under what empirical conditions focusing events help to
push issues on to the agenda and lead to the adoption of new policies. In his study of natural
disasters, oil spills, and nuclear accidents, Birkland (1997) stipulates that focusing events are harmful,
unexpected, relatively rare, and aect large numbers of people who learn about them simulta-
neously. Focusing events favor groups (particularly relatively weak ones) that seek changes in
public policy because the events provide valuable opportunities for the groups to point out
problems with the status quo and relieve them of the task of convincing the mass media to pay
attention to their issue. Not all focusing events lead to changes in the agenda or in policy.
Birkland argues that certain characteristics of focusing events and of the political environment in
which they occur help or hinder them from having an impact on policy. How much focal
power an event has depends, rst, upon the media attention that it receives. The level of media
attention, in turn, depends upon the scope of the event (or, how many people it aects), its
rarity, the size of the media market in which it occurs, and the visibility and tangibility of the
damages that it produces. Focusing events also have greater impact if the policy domain is char-
acterized by a high level of organization, whether the community of experts support change,
and in domains with less opposition and polarization among advocacy coalitions. In a follow-up
study, Birkland (2004) examined the impact of the September 11 attacks on the United States
He hypothesized that highly signicant focusing events like 9/11in which the level of damage,
potential future damage, and media attention were greater than typical focusing eventswould
lead to windows of opportunity that were kept open much longer and would inuence a
broader set of policy areas, initiatives, and agencies.
Finally, a few studies have tried to test hypotheses derived from the GCM. Even though the
GCM as a whole is not falsiable, parts of it generate testable hypotheses. Robinson and Eller
(2010) tested hypotheses related to one of the models central and most contested features: the
independence of the three streams. Robinson and Eller collected data from surveys of Texas
school district superintendents related to participation in local, school district policy-making
concerning violence prevention programs. They hypothesized that if the GCM is correct, we
should observe dierent sets of participants involved in the problem and solution streams.
Observing a participant in one stream should reduce the probability of nding the same parti-
cipant in the other stream. Since Kingdon also suggested that special groups of experts dominate
the solution stream, Robinson and Eller also tested the hypothesis that the solution stream
would be dominated by elite participants rather than ordinary citizens and non-specialists. Contrary
to the GCM, they found that participation in one stream dramatically increased the likelihood that
a participant would participate in the other stream and that elite participation did not crowd
out participation by mass participants (e.g. teachers and parents). One dierence between
Robinson and Ellers study and Kingdons, of course, is that one focused at the local and the other
at the federal level. Perhaps dierences in policy-making at the two levels accounts for the
dierent results. Obviously, much more research needs to be done to see if Robinson and Ellers
results hold up at the local and state levels, in other policy areas and on other issues, and if they
do, what might account for the dierences found when we compare degree of independence of
streams across levels of government.
Conclusion
The GCM has been, and will continue to be, among a handful of approaches to the study of
policy-making that all students in policy studies will learn about, discuss and use in their empirical
work. Undoubtedly, the debate over its strengths and weaknesses, its promise and limitations for
elucidating the real world of policy-making, will persist as well.
The garbage can model
327
Note
1 http://scholar.google.com/scholar?q=kingdon&hl=en&btnG=Search&as_sdt=1%2C39&as_sdtp=on
Bibliography
Bendor, Jonathan, Terry M. Moe, and Kenneth W. Shotts. 2001. Recycling the garbage can: An assessment
of the research program, American Political Science Review 95(1) (March): 16990.
Birkland, Thomas A. 1997. After Disaster: Agenda Setting, Public Policy, and Focusing Events. Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press.
——. 2004. ‘“The world changed today: agenda-setting and policy change in the wake of the September
11 terrorist attacks, The Review of Policy Research 21 (2) (March): 179200.
Cohen, Michael, James March and Johan Olsen. 1972. A garbage can model of organizational choice,
Administrative Science Quarterly 17(March): 125.
Collier, Ruth Berins and David Collier. 1991. Shaping the Political Arena: Critical Junctures, the Labor Movement
and Regime Dynamics in Latin America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Conlan, Timothy J. 1990. Taxing Choices: The Politics of Tax Reform . Washington, DC: Congressional
Quarterly.
——, Margaret T. Wrightson and David R. Beam. 1990. Taxing Choices: The Politics of Tax Reform.
Washington: CQ Press.
Fenno, Richard F. 1973. Congressmen in Committees. Boston: Little, Brown.
Hall, Peter. 1989. (ed.) The Political Power of Economic Ideas: Keynesianism Across Nations. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Heclo, Hugh. 1975. Modern Social Politics in Britain and Sweden. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Kingdon, John. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
McLendon, Michael K. 2003. Setting the governmental agenda for state decentralization of higher education,
The Journal of Higher Education 74(5) (September/October): 479515.
Mucciaroni, Gary. 1992. The garbage can model and the study of policy making: A critique, Polity 24(3)
(Spring): 45982.
Pierson, Paul. 2000. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, American Political Science
Review 94(2) (June): 25167.
Robinson, Scott E. and Warren S. Eller. 2010. Participation in policy streams: Testing the separation of
problems and solutions in subnational policy systems, Policy Studies Journal 382 (May): 199216.
Robyn, Dorothy. 1987. Braking
the Special Interests.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rose, Richard. 1991. What is lesson drawing?, Journal of Public Policy 11(1): 330.
Sabatier, Paul A. 1999. Theories of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 11766.
Skocpol, Theda and Weir, Margaret. 1985. State structures and the possibilities of Keynesian responses
to the depression in Sweden, Britain and the United States, in P. Evans, D. Reuschemeyer and Theda
Skocpol (eds). Bringing the State back in. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Zahariadis, Nikolaos. 1995. Markets, States and Public Policy: Privatization in Britain and France. Ann Arbor,
MI: University of Michigan Press.
—— 2005. Essence of Political Manipulation: Emotion, Institutions and Greek Foreign Policy. New York: Peter Lang.
—— 2007. The multiple streams framework: Structure, limitations, prospects, in Paul A. Sabatier, Theories
of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 6592.
Mucciaroni
328
Part VII
Understanding the
implementation process
25
Bureaucracy and the policy process
Ora-orn Poocharoen
Introduction
Bureaucracy is a concept that has been widely written about. Scholars in various elds of social
sciences, including sociology, political science, economics, anthropology, history, public admin-
istration and public policy, have produced a vast amount of literature pertaining to almost every
angle of bureaucracy one could ever imagine. This chapter focuses only on studies from the
eld of public administration and public policy. The aim is to provide a description of impor-
tant debates, theories and frameworks that explain the relationship between bureaucracy and the
public policy process. The chapter starts with denitions of the bureaucracy, followed by expla-
nations of bureaucratic roles in policy-making and policy implementation. In the latter half of
the chapter, the discussion focuses on the role of bureaucracy in the era of governance and the
chapter ends with the topic of heterogeneity of bureaucrats in the present.
Every country has some form of bureaucratic apparatus to perform government functions,
thus it is a subject of wide interest for scholars and practitioners who are involved with the public
sector. The term originates from a cloth covering the desk of French ocials in the eighteenth
century called a bureau (Niskanen 1973). In earlier works on public administration, scholars
used the word bureau synonymously with bureaucracy (e.g. ibid.; Downs 1967). Since German
sociologist Max Weber (18641920) wrote on the ideal type of bureaucracy, our understanding
of the bureaucracy has evolved in various ways. The term has attracted dierent sentiments ranging
from being powerful and eective to being slow and inecient. The bureaucracy can be seen as
the enforcer, the implementer, the administrator, the facilitator, the manager, or the mediator of
government. We rst turn to the original works on bureaucracy to explore its denitions.
Denitions of bureaucracy
The word bureaucracy can be referred to in two ways. First, it refers to the bureaucracy as a
form of organization, where there are structures, rules, resources and goals. The organization
can be in any sector: public, private, non-prot or a combination of these. Second, it refers to
the bureaucracy as administrative machinery that is part of the government. Its primary function
is to execute the will of the state or in other words to implement public policies. It is worth
331
noting that earlier scholars have identied the denition of bureaucracy to capture a spectrum
of meanings that fall within the two categories of organizational form and as part of the gov-
ernment. An often-cited author is Albrow, who suggested seven denitions of bureaucracy: (1)
bureaucracy as rational organization; (2) bureaucracy as organizational ineciency; (3) bureaucracy
as rule by ocials; (4) bureaucracy as public administration; (5) bureaucracy as administration by
ocials; (6) bureaucracy as the organization; (7) bureaucracy as modern society (Albrow 1970).
Denitions 1, 6 and 7 emphasize bureaucracy as an organizational form, whereas denitions 2,
3, 4 and 5 refer to bureaucracy as part of the government. When the word bureaucracy is used
in everyday language, often it is a combination of these two denitions. In addition, sometimes
the term bureaucracy is used synonymously with its agent, the bureaucrats. Typically, these are
the people who work as civil servants in the public sector and who would be involved in public
policy processes in various degrees. Next, we shall look at these two denitions in more detail.
Bureaucracy as an organizational form
Organization theory is a subeld that cuts across many disciplines including public administration,
business management and sociology. Organizations have various forms, structures, processes,
cultures, goals and values. Bureaucracy is nothing but one of the organizational form. The subeld
of organization theory provides rich research on the bureaucracy and bureaucratic behaviour.
Examples include March and Herbert (1958), Blau and Scott (1962), Downs (1964), Hall
and Quinn (1983), Wilson (1989), Scott (1992), Hall (1996), Christensen (2007) and Shafritz
et al. (2010).
The classic denition of the bureaucracy as dened by Max Weber often forms the basic fun-
damental traits of public sector organizations. In his seminal work, Weber oers an explanation
of the ideal type of bureaucracy that has six characteristics (1946).
There are xed jurisdictional areas that are determined by rules that are laws or administrative
regulations:
There is hierarchy, where there is supervision of subordinates by supervisors.
The management of the oce is based upon written documents.
There is oce management.
Full working capacity of the ocial is expected.
The management of the oce follows general rules that are stable and can be learned.
These characteristics were drawn from a study of various public organizations in Europe and
non-Western civilizations, including Egypt, Rome, China and the Byzantine Empire. This ideal
type describes the legal and rational system of authority that represents a modern bureaucracy. It
is dierent from the traditional authority system that relies more on personal ties and the char-
ismatic authority system that relies on strong leadership. Webers work was translated into English
only in 1940 and since has become the departure for all further analyses of the bureaucracy
(Shafritz and Hyde 2008).
This legal-rational foundation of the bureaucracy allows for institutions to gain and maintain
expertise, power and legitimacy for governance overtime. Public organizations, whether they
are ministries, bureaus, departments, or agencies, usually would be set up according to laws and
would employ full-time professionals, who are categorized into dierent hierarchical ranks. The
work of bureaucracies would be based on documentation, where records are kept and rules are
followed. This form of organization or system of administration is also found in private com-
panies, non-prot organizations, and international organizations where complex and large-scale
Poocharoen
332
administrative tasks take place. Kamenka provides a concise denition of bureaucracy that is
applicable to all organizations and not just governmental organizations as a centrally directed,
systematically organized and hierarchically structured sta devoted to the regular, routine and
ecient carrying out of large-scale administrative tasks according to policies dictated by rulers or
directors standing outside and above the bureaucracy (Kamenka 1989: 157). Bureaucracy was
and is still is, in some ways, understood to be the most ecient form of organizational
arrangement and is inevitable in all societies. Elliot Jacques alluded to this when he wrote,
[Bureaucracy] is one of the primary social institutions for any society which seeks the demo-
cratic enrichment and economic security which large-scale social, political, educational and
production technologies seem at their best to be able to provide. The simple fact is that if
we decide to proceed with the development of industrialized societies, then bureaucracies
on a large scale are here to stay.
(1976: 13)
Bureaucracy as part of the government
This view of the bureaucracy equates all public sector organizations the bureaucracy. Here, the
bureaucracy is made up of public ocials who are appointed through recruitment processes and
not elected. They are in contrast to electoral institutions such as politicians, parliament, and the
executive branch. The bureaucracy, as a legitimate actor of the state, has power to govern according
to laws and rules. Governments dene the scope and size of their bureaucracy dierently. Some
would include the military and judiciary, while others would not. In federal systems, the bureau-
cracy could refer to either national level or subnational levels of government agencies. Some
scholars would use the term public bureaucracy to emphasize that the focus is on the public sector.
However, most of the time, writers do use bureaucracy and public bureaucracy synonymously
and they usually mean bureaucracy in the public sector.
In conjunction with this denition, the bureaucracy is the institutional structure whereby the
bureaucrats are the individuals within that structure to implement policy and enforce laws.
Earlier, Downs wrote, In my analysis, the term bureaucrat is in no way derogatory, but because
it is so universally regarded as an insult, I will use the more neutral term ocial to describe
the type of person described above (Downs 1964: 4). Fifty years on and the general feeling
about the term have not changed. Due to connotations of ineciencies and unresponsiveness, it
is now more favourable to refer to bureaucrats as public managers. It gives the impression that the
bureaucrat is not just someone who pushes paper and complies with standard operating proce-
dures but rather someone who is entrepreneurial and innovative and who can manage complex
situations and problems. Whether they are called bureaucrats, public ocials, civil servants,
administrators, or public managers they are all agents within the bureaucracy.
One of the major debates in the eld of public administration is the premise that the will of
the state and the execution of that will should and can be separated. This is known as the
politics-administration dichotomy debate. Earlier scholars who have discussed this dichotomy
include W. Wilson (1887), Goodnow (1900) and White (1926). It is worth noting that their
works did not favour the dichotomy as many later claimed and that this debate has historical
roots in the United States, where the foundation of the state lies in the separation of power
between the executive, legislative and judicial branches of government (Svara 2001). This debate
is closely linked to the policy-making and policy implementation discussion of whether in
reality the two processes can be separated or not (e.g. Appleby 1949; Peters 1995). We can also
argue in the normative sense of whether or not the two processes should be separated. These
Bureaucracy and the policy process
333
debates shape the normative direction of division of role between politicians and bureaucrats.
The politicians are understood to be the designers of the will of the state, thus they have a clear
role to make policies, while bureaucrats are to execute that will by professionally implementing
policies using the bureaucratic machinery to achieve their objectives. Scholars have drawn
extensively on the debate to analyse political-administrative arrangements in dierent countries.
Examples of studies include Riper (1984), Rabin and Bowman (1984), Montjoy and Watson
(1995), Dunn (1997) Svara (1998, 1999, 2001) and Rutgers (2001). While in practice most would
agree that administrators do play important roles within the policy process and that the dichotomy
does not hold true, this debate continues to serve as a theoretical starting point for rening and
understanding the relationship between bureaucrats and politicians and the bureaucracys role in
the policy process.
In addition to the relationship between politics and administration, observation of the bureau-
cracy cannot be separated from the political system it operates in. Students of political science
and public administration would notably agree that political system is one of the most important
variables to explain decision-making processes, choices and outcomes of policy. Studies on the
bureaucracy have pointed to the inherent tension between bureaucracy and democracy (Mosher
1968; Beetham 1987; Smith 1988; Gormley and Balla 2004; Goodsell 2004). Albrow suggests
that this debate dates back to the nineteenth-century (Albrow 1970). Bureaucracy needs to have
a strong capacity to be eective in administration but at the same time it needs to be controlled
to ensure responsiveness to the public and higher authorities (Garvey 1995). Etzioni-Halevy argues
that bureaucratic power generates a dilemma for democracy (1983). It poses a threat to democratic
political structure. He also argues that democracy generates a dilemma for bureaucracy. Bureau-
cracy is expected to be independent and subservient to elected politicians at the same time. This
rule is self-contradictory. Last, he argues that the dilemma of bureaucracy is an important source
of political friction especially between senior bureaucrats and senior politicians. Many have used
this debate as a point of departure and have either rebutted or supported these claims.
Some scholars see bureaucracy as not in conict with democracy but as an important vehicle
to push for better democratic governments, in addition to political parties, elections, and the
legislatures (Thompson 1965). For example, Kim has empirically demonstrated that democratic
control can and does go hand-in-hand with bureaucratic autonomy (2008). He emphasized
how bureaucratic behaviour is inuenced by multiple political institutions that have relation-
ships with the public agency. Since the mid-1990s, scholars have begun to discuss the rela-
tionship between public bureaucracy and the use of performance management systems in the
evolving democratic processes (e.g. Gormley and Balla 2004; Peters 2010). Performance systems
can be seen as instruments to control the bureaucracy by electorates and citizens in democratic
settings. Rather than focusing only on the bureaucracy, Meier points to the need to balance our
focus on the electorates (1997). He argues that most problems in the United States stem from
the inability of politicians to formulate good policies. These debates illustrate the ongoing need
for students of political science and public administration to understand the two groups in relation
to each other. In sum, bureaucracy continues to be an important component of democratic
systems, despite inherent tensions between the two concepts. Needless to say, the bureaucracy
has always been important for non-democratic systems especially in authoritarian and commu-
nist systems where the state has an overarching role in many aspects of citizens lives. In general,
bureaucracy in the twenty-rst century is inevitably becoming more democratic as citizens con-
tinue to demand higher levels of accountability and responsiveness, regardless of the type of
political system they are in.
As political systems and economic systems are intertwined, observation of the bureaucracy
cannot be separated from the economic system it operates in. There are numerous studies of the
Poocharoen
334
relationship between bureaucracy and the market mechanism. There are three ways of viewing
this relationship. One is to treat the bureaucracy as a system existing within a larger economic
system. Webers studies on the bureaucracy stemmed from his question of the consequences of
modern capitalism. He infers that the capitalist system provided the best chance for preservation
of individual freedom and creative leadership in a bureaucracy (Mommsen 1974: xv). Marxist
schools of thought equally debated and discussed the role of the bureaucracy, specically on the
bureaucracy and class and implications for society as a whole (e.g. Chattopadhyay 1993; Burn-
ham 1941; Westoby 1985). In this camp, bureaucracy presented the new elites with managerial
and technical power that would dominate the working class (Westoby 1985). The second view
sees the co-existence of the bureaucratic system and market mechanisms. Recent debates have
extended the focus to observe the co-existence between market, bureaucratic and network
mechanisms in public service delivery (e.g. Olsen 2006; Koliba 2011). This view does not treat
the bureaucracy as working in a certain economic system but rather as a system operating side-
by-side with other systems. The third view is to treat bureaucracy and the market as dierent
mechanisms for organizational control or management (e.g. Ouchi 1980). Similarly, accountability
systems, as a form of organizational control, can also be divided into market and bureaucratic or
administrative frames, aside from the democratic frame (Koliba 2011).
Now that the two views of the denition of bureaucracy have been elaborated, next we will
discuss the role of the bureaucracy in the policy process, which is an extension of this second
denition that bureaucracy is part of government. From here onward I will use the term
bureaucracy synonymously with the term public bureaucracy.
Role of the bureaucracy in the policy process
The bureaucracy plays a very important role in the entire policy process: setting agendas and
formulating, implementing and evaluating policies. This understanding of the dominant role of
the bureaucracy in the policy process is not new and has been recognized for many years by
prominent scholars. Examples include Our Wonderland of Bureaucracy (Beck 1932) and The
Managerial Revolution (Burnham 1941) as well as more recent works such as Breaking through the
Bureaucracy (Barzelay 1992). In his work to introduce the concept of bureaucratic government,
Peters writes, It is by now almost trite to say that bureaucracy and administration are an increas-
ingly signicant if not the most signicant feature of modern policymaking (1981: 56).
Peters identies subsets of literature pertaining to bureaucracy and public administration. They
are the positivist theorists that borrow economic rationality through the public choice approach
to explain bureaucrats to be power-maximizing actors (Downs 1964, 1967). The other group of
scholars, called descriptive theorists, explain bureaucrats behaviour as political actors and not the
non-political technicians stressed in the Webers ideal-type bureaucracy. Bureaucracies are given
wide latitude to include details of actual implementation of legislation and to spell out all the
rules and guidelines that need to accompany the policy or law.
Peters reiterated in his often-cited book The Politics of Bureaucracy that administrative systems
do inuence policy outputs of the political system (1995). Bureaucracies are always either
explicitly or implicitly included in theoretical discussions of the public policy process. Charles
Lindbloms well-known incrementalism theory explains that due to standard operating proce-
dures ingrained in the bureaucracy, there is always a tendency for governments to preserve the
status quo or to change very minimally from the status quo. The bureaucracy is understood to
be one of the main actors in other models of public policy whether it is the elite model, the
group model or the institutionalist model. The traditional rational model of policy-making, by
emphasizing objective and technical knowledge in decision-making is inevitably supporting the
Bureaucracy and the policy process
335
role of the bureaucracy (see Parsons 1995). Thus it is vital to understand the bureaucratic admin-
istration system alongside political, economic and social systems in order to understand public
policy. Most public policy textbooks would not be complete without mentioning the role of
the bureaucracy and bureaucrats in the policy process. See, for example, Wu et al. (2010),
Howlett and Ramesh (2003), Parsons (1995), Considine (1994) and Gupta (2001).
There are several reasons why bureaucrats can and do inuence policy processes at various
stages. First, the policy process can only be divided in theory but not in practice. In practice, the
process is often a mix of the policy stages because policies are constantly being changed or
adjusted based on implementation and evaluation experiences. Second, because the bureaucracy
often has expert and long-term institutional knowledge of public issues, it is often involved at
the very early stage of agenda-setting. Sometimes it is the bureaucracy that initiates policies. A
clear example is the bureaucracys involvement in the national budget decision-making process.
Line ministries are asked to submit a draft of their budget proposal each year. This often occurs
without the direct involvement of ministers or politicians. Wildavsky has written extensively on
this topic (e.g. Wildavsky 1979, 1986; Wildavsky et al. 2006) and this topic was extended to
include assertions that bureaucrats tend to maximize their interests through the budget process
(Blais and Dion 1991; Peters 1995).
In addition, bureaucrats usually stay in their posts longer than politicians. They have the
opportunity to see through policies. They are sometimes known for taking a longer-term view
of public problems. Furthermore, bureaucrats are recruited on the basis of their expertise and
profession, while politicians are elected on popularity and big policy promises. The bureaucracy
is often perceived to speak more creditably about the technical aspects of policies. This is a form
of knowledge-based power that bureaucrats exercise. Finally, bureaucrats usually have access to
more data and information regarding specic policies. By being the implementers of policies,
bureaucrats have many opportunities to collect data and information that would be valuable for
policy-making and evaluation. The level of inuence that bureaucrats do have in the policy pro-
cess is also determined by other factors, including historical legacies, governance structures or
political systems, the Constitution or the most important laws. In one country, the level of
inuence can also change over time depending on the arrangement and preferences at dierent
points in time. In sum, it has long been recognized that the bureaucracy plays an important role
in all stages of the policy process. Next, we will focus on the policy-making process.
Bureaucrats as policy-makers
Bureaucrats can and do greatly inuence policy-making. They can be the source of ideas. They
can be the advocate of ideas. They can take part formally and informally in the policy-making
process. They can also be the sole actor or leader in the policy-making process.
Bureaucracy can directly and indirectly shape the discourse of public policies. Indirectly,
during the policy formulation stage, bureaucrats can inuence the discourse of broad policies
through their communications with politicians and the wider public. After broad goals have
been set, the bureaucracy plays an important role in outlining policy details through the design
of specic programmes. It is precisely this that will largely inuence the overall policy outcome
and citizens perceptions of the policy and the government. Peters suggests that there are soft
and hard versions of agency ideologies (1995). Soft ideology refers to when ministers are being
inuenced by bureaucrats preferences in order to maintain certain policies, that is to say they
are the source of ideas and are indirectly inuencing policy.
Hard ideology refers to when bureaucrats actively seek to alternate or initiate policies. This
latter version sees bureaucracy as an active participant in the political arena of the policy process.
Poocharoen
336
It accepts that bureaucrats can act similarly to pressure groups, namely they are the advocates of
ideas and are directly inuencing policy. This could take the form of lobbying, trying to
inuence discourse through media and possibly also through participating in protests. This is
because bureaucrats have their own sets of ideologies and preferences. This view diers from
seeing the bureaucracy as being politically neutral and acting as a buer between the state and
interest groups. A similar idea is found in the concept of representative bureaucracy, where bureau-
cracy is accepted as a political actor in the policy sphere and is expected to help shape public
policies (Krislov 1974; Seldon 1997; Dolan and Rosenbloom 2003). To put it positively, bureau-
crats can also be seen as policy entrepreneurs. In systems where the bureaucrat is stationed in
one agency for their entire career, as is the case in the United States and Scandinavian countries,
for example, they tend to be policy advocates because they hold such deep expertise and opinions
on their policy area (Peters 1995). On the other hand, if bureaucrats are centrally recruited, and
are rotated around various agencies, such as in France and the United Kingdom, they might be
less attached to certain policy opinions (ibid.). This is in stark contrast to before the 1950s when
bureaucrats were understood to discreetely shape policy behind the scenes (Svara 2001).
Furthermore, the bureaucracy sometimes even takes the leadership role with very little
inuence from other actors, including politicians (Peters 1995). This resonates with Moshers
idea of the professional state where professionals in public agencies through their expertise and
knowledge do not only generate new policy ideas but are the main actors to formulate the ne
details of policies as well (Mosher 1968). In relation to seeing the bureaucracy as taking the leading
role in specic policy areas, many scholars have pointed to the bureaucracys critical role in the
entire administration of developing countries. For example, scholars have associated the suc-
cessful development of some Asian countries and regions with the idea of a strong state, namely
strong bureaucracy. They include the so-called four tigers of Taiwan, South Korea, Singapore, and
Hong Kong (for more on East Asia see, for example, Wade 1990; World Bank 1993; Henderson
2011). Japan is also known to have a strong bureaucracy with greater inuence than politicians and
which has dominated policy-making since World War II (Ramseyer and Rosenbluth 1993).
Bureaucracies that are core agencies, regulatory agencies and planning agencies are often in a
position to inuence policy-making and setting the policy direction for the country. The term
super bureaucrat depicts the prominent role of high-ranking bureaucrats in the policy process
(Campbell and Szablowski 1979). These bureaucrats are usually in the central ministries or the
peak policy agencies such as Thailands National Economic and Social Development Board,
Singapores Economic Development Board, Taiwans Council for Economic Planning and
Development, Japans Ministry of Economy, Trade and Industry, and Malaysias Prime Minis-
tersOce. Similarly in the area of public administrative reform policy, only a handful of key
central agencies would be involved in the design of the policy. These agencies have been called
system designers (Olsen and Peters 1996). On the other hand, in some cases the line ministries
might dominate policy-making. Mostly these are areas where great technical expertise is required.
They are, for example, policies related to energy, health, transportation, food regulation, just to
name a few. Examples of studies include the Medicare movement (Marmor 1973) and com-
munity mental health programmes (Foley 1975) in the United States and foreign policy-making
(Ahn 1998) and telecommunication policy (Eiji 2001) in Japan.
In a bureaucracy, it is not only the bureaucrats who can inuence policy-making. In pre-
sidential systems where there are political appointees in the bureaucracy, such as the United
States and the Philippines, studies conrm that career and non-career administrators contribute
signicantly to policy-making (Aberbach et al. 1981; Rourke 1984; Dolan 2000). In parlia-
mentarian systems, such as the United Kingdom, it is also known that ocials whether selected
by appointment with lifetime tenure or politically selected for the duration of a government,
Bureaucracy and the policy process
337
can also have signicant inuence on policy-making as long as they are part of the bureaucracy
(e.g. Bevir and Rhodes 2006).
In the debate on the appropriate role of the bureaucracy in the policy process, some see that
the bureaucracy can stabilize governance where the political party system is weak. In many
countries, when the political executive is weak, the bureaucracy often gains more importance
and strengthen its hold on policy decisions (Peters 1981: 68). For some developing countries in
the early to middle stages of development, the bureaucracy often have control over policy
directions of the country. For example, during the years 1932 to 1973 the bureaucrats in
Thailand were considered to be elites who had overthrown the absolute monarchy. They led
the government in an authoritarian fashion, setting the tone of a semi-democracy that still
persists many years after (Bowornwathana 2011). In turn, bureaucracy can also dominate policy
processes to the detriment of political institutions and actors. Heady calls this imbalance thesis
(2001). Similarly, Riggs has argued that bureaucracy is mostly made up of the ruling class that
impedes the development of strong political systems (2001).
Naturally, this bureaucratic power in policy-making has never been a comfortable fact for
politicians. Studies have shown how political leaders have intentionally excluded high-ranking
bureaucrats from policy-making processes (Cole and Caputo 1979; Bevir and Rhodes 2006).
Parliamentarians keep a check on the public bureaucracy by scrutinizing their policies and imple-
mentation in parliament debates (e.g. Ho 2000 on Singapore). The new public management
(NPM) movement that originated in the Anglo-Saxon countries in the 1980s is an attempt to
strengthen the checks on bureaucracies and bureaucratic power. On the contrary, when the rela-
tionship between bureaucrats and politicians becomes too cozy, it is labelled iron triangle and
that is when there is a monopoly of policy-making power among the politicians, the bureau-
cracy and industry or the interest groups. Some of these sectors include defence in the United
States (Adams 1981) and agriculture in the European Union (Hix 1999). These relationships can
easily lead to corruption and a conict of interest for the government.
Another aspect of the bureaucracy that inuences policy-making is structure. Bureaucratic
structure can be both an independent and dependent variable in relation to policy. Policy can be a
determinant to explain bureaucratic structures. Frequently we witness governments setting up
new bureaucracies in order to take charge of new policies. These are usually new policies that
existing agencies do not cover. For instance, they could be policies related to climate change,
food security, crisis management, terrorism, non-traditional security and population or migration.
Bureaucratic structure is a reection of politics (West 1997). It shows how scarce resources are
allocated. The structures are nothing but evidence of institutional choice and power in the public
sector. However, bureaucratic structure can be a determinant of policy direction and policy
choice. Examples include studies on bureaucratic structure and personality by Robert K. Merton
(1957), Allison (1971) and Egeberg (1999). Bureaucratic structure determines the ow of
information processing, which would inuence the type and value of information that is ltered
up and down the bureaucracy. Bureaucratic structure also dictates the dynamics of politics among
bureaucracies. And scholars have long argued that policy decisions are dominated by the dynamics
of bureaucratic politics (Allison and Zelikow 1999). Following Allisons (1971) seminal work on
foreign policy other works have expanded our understanding of how bureaucratic politics govern
policy processes (e.g. Peters 1995; Bowornwathana and Poocharoen 2010). There are many exam-
ples of when decisions on administrative reform policies are shaped by the struggle between key
central agencies to maintain or gain more power during the reform and after the reform.
Bureaucracies can also indirectly inuence domestic policy-making from the international
arena. It is suggested that bureaucrats often take part in professional policy networks, where
they pick up ideas and good practices and then try to implement those policies and practices to
Poocharoen
338
their own agency, community or government (Peters 1995). International organizations often
provide platforms for such exchanges, such as the model of community of practice in the World
Bank or Asian Development Bank. Many examples can be found in the EU especially in the
standardization of various social services (ibid.). There are also studies that point to how domestic
bureaucracies can inuence policies made at the international level (Hopkins 1976). Lastly, aside
from focusing on domestic bureaucracies, more and more attention is being focused on the role of
international bureaucracies. In a highly globalized world, we cannot ignore the signicance of
international bureaucracies and their impact on global governance and domestic policy choices
(e.g. Mouritzen 1990; Barnett and Finnemore 1999; Muldoon et al. 2010). In sum, international
bureaucracies are also important actors in the policy-making process both domestically and
internationally. Next we will discuss bureaucracy in the policy implementation process.
Bureaucrats as policy implementers
The main function of the bureaucracy is to implement public policies, programmes and pro-
jects. In the process of implementation, the bureaucracy inuences the direction of policy in
several ways. Policies are often very broad and vague due to the complexity of most public
policy problems. For example it is dicult for governments to have certain explicit policies on
climate change issues, gender equality or poverty reduction because often the responsibility to
solve these problems is diused among many bureaucracies. There is no one bureaucracy to
take ownership of these complex problems. Thus, during the implementation stage, depending
on the level of discretionary power, dierent bureaucracies have room to interpret policies to t
their own views and maintain practicality. The bureaucracy also adjusts rules and instructions to
suit local contexts. This process of interpretation is where intentionally or unintentionally bureau-
crats can and do inuence policies. Sometimes, the original intent of the policy, as set by policy-
makers, is altered due to the bureaucrats interpretation of the policy (Pressman and Wildavsky
1973). Also, during the implementation stage, as policies are being further dened and designed,
bureaucracy can come up with bureaucratic standard operating procedures or process-oriented
policies that can also aect the policy outcome. At this stage, politicians and other stakeholders
might also intervene and inuence how implementation processes are set (Furlong 1998).
Studies about street-level bureaucrats give a clear illustration of how bureaucracies inuence
policy outcomes at the implementation stage (Lipsky 1980). Street-level bureaucrats are those
who have face-to-face communication with citizens. Examples include police, teachers, immi-
gration ocers, social workers and those who work in service delivery agencies such as birth
and marriage registration or passport and drivers license issue. Street-level bureaucrats have to
constantly interpret and reinterpret policy goals. At the same time, they often have individual
agendas, expectations, values and capacity. Studies have found that street-level bureaucrats lack
of conformity to procedures and decision-trees set by top administration is a stable norm of
policy implementation (Mashaw 1983; Mashaw and Marmor 1988). They often feel frustration
due to the need to face ongoing conict between responding to clients or citizens and the need
to properly implement policies. Put positively, street-level bureaucrats discretion can help policies
to be more adaptive and enhance governments ability to respond to individual cases. On the other
hand, street-level bureaucrats can also change the course of the policy entirely.
Aside from street-level bureaucrats, there are also studies that explain how mid-level bureaucrats
also inuence policies. In their study of mid-level civil servants in the United Kingdom Page
and Jenkins identify three types of policy roles: (1) a production role in making policy drafts and
documents; (2) a maintenance role in tending and managing policies; and (3) a service role in
oering knowledge and skills to those involved in the policy process (2006).
Bureaucracy and the policy process
339
Aside from large- and medium-sized states, some scholars have pointed to the uniqueness of
bureaucracy of small island states. Similarly to many fragile states, these bureaucrats are often
implementing not only the national policy but also policies directed by international donors
(Baker 1992; Garcia-Zamor 2004). Often bureaucrats struggle to achieve policy goals set by
international donors and international organizations because they are confronted with many
challenges on the ground during the implementation stage.
During the policy monitoring and evaluation stage, bureaucrats often play the most impor-
tant role in providing information to external evaluators, if the evaluation is not done in-house.
As mentioned in the previous section, the bureaucracy has access to sensitive data and institu-
tional information that outsiders do not have. Thus they have some control over the evaluation
studies or reports of most policies and programmes. It is often dicult to determine the validity
of evaluation reports when done in-house by the bureaucracy. Naturally they would be inclined
to not publicize policy failures. Overall, there is limited scholarly work on the issues pertaining
to bureaucracy and policy evaluation. In general, evaluation frameworks tend to focus less on
who is doing it but rather on how to do it. This topic should be further expanded in the future.
In sum, we can see that the bureaucracy is very inuential in the policy process. Bureaucrats
can be seen as policy owners, policy advocates, policy managers, policy interpreters and policy
technicians. Next we shall discuss the evolving role of bureaucracy in the era of governance.
Bureaucracy and governance
Between the 1980s to 2000s, we witnessed the spread of the NPM movement across many
countries. As bureaucracies grew in size and power over the years between the 1940s and the
1980s, the rhetoric of the need to curb bureaucratic power gained momentum. Many govern-
ments went through phases of downsizing the public sector, tightening control over bureau-
cracies, and introducing market-based competition for traditional public services. The discourse
emphasized how bureaucracies were inecient and too big. Proponents of such ideas came
from public choice theorists (Niskanen 1974), New Institutional Economic theorists in New
Zealand (Boston 1991), and New Right ideologies in the 1980s (Saint-Martin 2004; Pollitt and
Bouckaert 2004). The book, Reinventing Government by Osborne and Gaebler (Osborne and Gaebler
1993), which made an impact on the United States reform movement, was widely read by
practitioners of public administration and public policy in other countries.
The NPM movement highlighted that bureaucrats should only implement policies and be
accountable to politicians and citizens for policy outcomes. Bureaucrats should not inuence policy-
making. The movement had a goal to change bureaucratic structure and culture to be more
ecient and responsive to public interests (Barzelay 1992). Proponents of NPM used economic
theory, incentive theories and market-driven decisions as a basis for solutions. A prime example
of a tool that emerged was the signing of contracts between ministers and permanent secretaries to
promise certain deliverables, such as in Australia and the United Kingdom. Another example
was the separation of policy-making agencies from service delivery and production bureau-
cracies. Owing to NPM, some have pointed to the decline of bureaucratic power in the policy-
making process (Wilson 2008). However, there are also a number of studies that explained how
NPM was business as usual and that the bureaucracys role had not diminished in any way (e.g.
Cheung and Scott 2003).
Since the early 2000s, especially since 9/11 in the United States, scholars have referred less to
the NPM paradigm and now refer more to the governance paradigm. The rapid process of
globalization, the emergence and spread of the Internet and other communication media have
changed the way that we understand and approach problems of governance. The meaning of
Poocharoen
340
governance can be broadly dened as structures and processes by which people in societies make
decisions, set rules, and share power (Folke et al. 2005: 444). Rhodes oers six approaches to
the denition of the term: governance as corporate governance; governance as New Public
Management; governance as good governance; governance as international interdependence;
governance as a socio-cybernetic system; and governance as networks (Rhodes 2000).
Despite the changes and reforms during the NPM era, in the era of governance, the bureaucracy
continues to be an integral part of the policy process. Some argue that the bureaucracy is
stronger than before and that there is a need to continue to build up bureaucratic capacity. Thus
it is necessary to re-emphasize the bureaucracy in the study of policy processes (e.g. Howlett
and Ramesh 2003; Krause and Meier 2005). In the governance paradigm, the role of the
bureaucracy and the bureaucrats is understood to be dierent from before. Governance stresses
the value of bureaucrats among other actors in creating public value and the bureaucracy as an
important part of issue networks and service delivery networks. While most literature on public
administration regards the evolution of the bureaucracy as a linear process, some have argued
the contrary. Lynn argues that the traditional bureaucratic paradigm showed far more respect for
law, politics, citizens and values than the NPM paradigm (Lynn 2001). Thus there is more resem-
blance between the traditional bureaucratic paradigm and the governance paradigm. The gov-
ernance paradigm values the role of the bureaucracy, unlike the NPM paradigm, yet at the same
time it is pushing the bureaucracy to improve and evolve further.
Within the governance paradigm the notion of networks and collaborations is prominent. There
are now more studies on the bureaucracy and its relations and power in various types of networks.
One example is the notion of policy networks. Policy networks refer to a group of various
people or organizations who are connected or are held together by common interests in certain
policy problems. Policy networks try to inuence policy decisions (Marsh and Rhodes 1992; Marsh
1998). A bureaucracy is one actor in the complex web of actors in the society that make up policy
networks. Eective bureaucracies would be able to manage and manoeuvre policy networks in
the direction that is best for the general public. This is dened as network governance which is the
act of designing, managing, coordinating strategies, structures and processes of inter-organizational
relations in order to aect public policies (Baker 1992; Provan and Kenis 2007). Bureaucrats need
to have a dierent set of skills to maneuver in this kind of context, whether it is to eectively
take part in a policy network or to exercise network governance (Edelenbos and Klijin 2005).
Public managers are co-creators of public value, which in turn sets the direction for bureaucracies
and public policies. Moores concept of public value has gained momentum in the public sector and
has implications on how we understand the role of the bureaucracy in the policy process (Moore
1995). As bureaucracies are working in a networked environment, they are consistently shaping
public value through networks. Concepts that have gained attention include co-production and
co-creation where the bureaucracy partners work with the private sector and non-prot orga-
nizations to provide public goods and services, and to set regulations for governance. These
ideas fall under the rubrics of collaborative governance (e.g. Ansell and Gash 2008; OLeary and
Bingham 2009) and also sound governance (Farazmand 2004). All these frameworks have one
common focus on partnership as a form of participatory governance. This shifting role of the
bureaucracy will have implications on how it can inuence the policy process. In one view, this
could lead to a more restricted role for bureaucracies. This is due to the increased role and
power of non-state actors in networks. On the other hand, bureaucracy might gain more power
and control because of their continual advantage over public resources and the opportunity to
shape public values through public policies.
In sum, the bureaucracy continues to be the centre of study no matter how paradigms have shifted
in public administration, whether it is the traditional public administration, new public management,
Bureaucracy and the policy process
341
or governance paradigms (Koliba 2004; Jreisat 2012). Its role in the policy process will continue to
change depending on the political, economic and social changes that each country goes through.
For now, it continues to be one of the most important actors in all stages of the policy process.
Future studies
To successfully understand this topic in greater depth, there need to be more studies of the
dierent types of bureaucracy and of bureaucrats, in other words the heterogeneity of bureaucracy
and bureaucrats. Bureaucracies are currently not homogeneous. Many have little resemblance
to Webers original ideal type. We should compare dierent types of bureaucratic behaviour,
structure and culture and their inuences on policy processes. For example, they could be studies
of comparisons between central and local bureaucracies, line -ministries versus central ministries,
higher, middle and lower ranks of bureaucrats, developed and developing countries, and
bureaucracies of dierent sectors such as health and education. The literature on decentraliza-
tion has begun to focus on bureaucratic capacity but not so much on how local bureaucracy
shapes policy at the local and national levels. Lastly the literature on multilevel governance has
started to focus on the relationship between national and local bureaucracy with supra-national
bureaucracy such as that of the EU. But there is much more room for research.
Another phenomenon worth noting is the expansion of semi-bureaucrats, in other words,
those who are employed by the public sector but who are treated dierently from a career civil
servant or bureaucrat. Semi-bureaucrats are usually employed based on market-mechanisms.
Examples of this group include contract employees, state enterprise employees, experts, profes-
sionals, advisors, consultants and ad hoc public managers. It is also important to understand how
their role diers or is the same compared to the typical bureaucrat.
In the past, scholars could study one agency within a ministry and could claim that the study
represented that entire bureaucracy. Today, uniqueness is the new norm. Each agency can be
quite unique due to information technology, leadership style, organizational culture, and hier-
archical arrangements of the organizations. Aside from the above mentioned semi-bureaucrats,
many public agencies are frequently using more matrix approaches to management rather than
relying solely on hierarchical control. These semi-bureaucracies or hybrid organizations have
mixed management instruments between bureaucracy, the market and networks. They have a
variety of structures for decision-making such as the use of task forces, inter-departmental com-
mittees, and ad hoc committees. Thus, in addition to understanding the semi-bureaucrats roles,
we should also understand how these new structures of the bureaucracy eect policy processes.
In sum, the Weberian model continues to be a reference point for any discussion on the
bureaucracy and its role in the policy process. However, we have moved quite far from that
starting point. Bureaucracies have achieved great success in some countries as well as failing
miserably in others. Despite being understood as being rigid and hierarchical, they continue to
evolve and adapt to changes in political, economic and social systems. In this era of governance
we recognize the bureaucracy as public organizations and bureaucrats as public managers, who
have to manoeuvre in the complex web of multiple actors in all stages of the policy process.
bureaucracy has played an important, if not the most important role, in policy-making and policy
implementation throughout the history of its existence and it will continue to do so.
Bibliography
Aberbach, Joel D., Robert D. Putnam and Bert A. Rockman. 1981. Bureaucrats and Politicians in Western
Democracies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Poocharoen
342
Adams, Gordon. 1981. The Iron Triangle: The Politics of Defence Contracting. New York: Council on Economic
Priorities.
Ahn, C.S. 1998. Inter-ministry coordination in Japans foreign policy making, PacicAairs 72(1): 4260.
Albrow, Martin. 1970. Bureaucracy. London: Pall Mall.
Allison, G. 1971. Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. Boston: Little Brown.
——and P. Zelikow. 1999. Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. New York: Longman.
Ansell, C. and A. Gash. 2008. Collaborative governance in theory and practice, Journal of Public Administration
in Research and Theory 18(4): 54371.
Appleby, Paul. Policy and Administration. 1949. Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.
Baker, R. 1992. Public Administration in Small and Island States. West Hartford, CT: Kumarian Press.
Barnett, Michael N. and Martha Finnemore. 1999. The politics, power, and pathologies of international
organizations, International Organization 53: 699732.
Barzelay, Michael. 1992. Breaking Through Bureaucracy. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Beck, James M. 1932. Our Wonderland of Bureaucracy: A Study of the Growth of Bureaucracy in the Federal
Government, and Its Destructive Eect upon the Constitution. New York: Macmillan.
Beetham, David. Bureaucracy. 1987. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Bevir, Mark and R.A.W. Rhodes. 2006. Governance Stories. Routledge: London.
Blais, Andre and Stephane Dion (eds). 1991. The Budget-Maximizing Bureaucrat: Appraisal and Evidence .
University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA.
Blau, Peter M and W. Richard Scott. 1962. Formal Organizations: A Comparative Approach. San Francisco:
Chandler.
Boston, J. 1991. The theoretical underpinnings of public sector restructuring in New Zealand, in J. Boston,
J. Martin, J. Pallot and P. Walsh (eds) Reshaping the State: New Zealands Bureaucratic Revolution. Auckland:
Oxford University Press,
Bowornwathana, Bidhya. 2011. History and political context of public administration in Thailand ,in
Evan Berman (ed.) Public Administration in Southeast Asia: Thailand, Philippines, Malaysia, Hong Kong and
Macau. New York: CRC Press, Taylor & Francis, 2952.
——and Ora-orn Poocharoen. 2010. Bureaucratic
politics and administrative
reform: Why politics matters,
Public Organization Review 10: 30321.
Burnham, James. 1941.The Managerial Revolution. New York: John Day.
Campbell, C. and G. Szablowski. 1979. The Superbureaucrats: Structure and Behaviour in Central Agencies.
Toronto: Macmillan.
Chattopadhyay, Paresh. 1993. The (ex) Soviet economy: Towards a reassessment of contending theses,
Economic and Political Weekly 28(5): 1322.
Cheung, Anthony B.L. and Ian Scott. 2003. Governance and Public Sector Reform in Asia: Paradigm Shifts or
Business as Usual? London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon.
Christensen, T. 2007. Organization Theory and the Public Sector: Instrument, Culture and Myth. London:
Routledge.
Cole, Richard and David Caputo. 1979. Presidential control of the senior civil service, American Political
Science Review, June: 399413.
Considine, Mark. 1994. Public Policy: A Critical Approach. South Melbourne: Macmillan Education Australia
Pty Ltd.
Dolan, Julie. 2000. The senior executive service: Gender, attitudes, and representative bureaucracy, Journal of
Public Administration Research and Theory 10: 51330.
——and David H. Rosenbloom. 2003. Representative Bureaucracy: Classic Readings and Continuing Controversies.
New York: M.E. Sharpe.
Downs, Anthony. 1964. Inside Bureaucracy. Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation.
—— 1967. Inside Bureaucracy. Boston: Little, Brown.
Dunn, Delmer D. 1997. Politics and Administration at the Top: Lessons from Down Under. Pittsburgh, PA:
University of Pittsburgh Press.
Edelenbos, J. and E.H. Klijin. 2005. Managing stakeholder involvement in decision-making: A comparative
analysis of six interactive processes in the Netherlands, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory
16: 41746.
Egeberg, Morten. 1999. The impact of bureaucratic structure on policy-making, Public Administration 77:
15570.
Eiji, Kawabata. 2001. Sanction power, jurisdiction, and economic policy-making: Explaining contemporary
telecommunications policy in Japan, Governance 14(4): 399427.
Bureaucracy and the policy process
343
Etzioni-Halevy, E. 1983. Bureaucracy and Democracy: A Political Dilemma. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Farazmand, Ali. 2004. Sound Governance: Policy and Administrative Innovations. New York: Greenwood
Publishing Group.
Foley, Henry A. 1975. Community Mental Heath Programs: The Formative Process. Lexington, MA: D.C.
Health.
Folke, C., T. Hahn, P. Olsson and J. Norberg. 2005. Adaptive governance of social-ecological systems,
Annual Review of Environment and Resources 30: 44173.
Furlong, F.R. 1998. Political inuence on the bureaucracy: The bureaucracy speaks, Journal of Public
Administration Research and Theory 8: 3965.
Garcia-Zamor, Jean-Claude. 2004. The struggle of small bureaucracies to develop traditional ethical
policies, in Ali Farazmand (ed.) Sound Governance: Policy and Administratiive Innovations. Westport, CT:
Praeger, 290308.
Garvey, Gerald. 1995. False promises: The NPR in historical perspective, in Donald F. Kettl and John
J. DiIulio, Jr., Inside the Reinvention Machine: Appraising Governmental Reform. Washington, DC: The
Brookings Institution, 87106.
Goodnow, Frank J. 1900. Politics and Administration: A Study in Government. New York: Macmillan.
Goodsell, Charles T. 2004. The Case for Bureaucracy: A Public Administration Polemic. Washington, DC: CQ
Press.
Gormley, William T. Jr. and Steven J. Balla. 2004. Bureaucracy and Democracy: Accountability and Performance.
Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Gupta, Dipak K. 2001. Analyzing Public Policy: Concepts, Tools, and Techniques. Washington, DC: Congressional
Quarterly Inc.
Hall, Richard H. 1996. Organization: Structure, Processes and Outcomes. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
——and Robert E. Quinn. 1983. Organization Theory and Public Policy. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Heady, Ferrel. 2001. Public Administration: A Comparative Perspective. New York: Marcel Dekker.
Henderson, Jerey. 2011. East Asian Transformation: On the Political Economy of Dynamism, Governance and
Crisis. London: Routledge.
Henry, J. 2006. Educating managers for post-bureaucracy: The role of the humanities, Management
Learning 37: 26781.
Hix, Simon. 1999. The Political System of the European Union . London: Macmillan.
Ho, Khai Leong. 2000. The Politics of Policy Making in Singapore.
Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Hopkins, R.F. 1976. The international role of domestic bureaucracy, International Organization 30(3):
40532.
Howlett, Michael and M. Ramesh. 2003. Studying Public Policy: Policy Cycles and Policy Subsystems. Toronto:
Oxford University Press.
Jacques, E. 1976. A General Theory of Bureaucracy. London: Heinemann.
Jreisat, Jamil E. 2012. Globalism and Comparative Public Administration. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.
Kamenka, Eugene. 1989. Bureaucracy. Oxford: Blackwell.
Kaufman, H. 1981. Fear of bureaucracy: A raging pandemic, Public Administration Review 41: 19.
Kim, Doo-Rae. 2008. Political control and bureaucratic autonomy revisited: A multi-institutional analysis
of OSHA enforcement, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 18(1): 3355.
Kjaer, Anne Mette. 2004. Governance. Oxford: Polity Press.
Koliba, C. 2004. Is service-learning contributing to the downsizing of American democracy? Learning our
way out, The Michigan Journal of Community Service Learning Spring: 5768.
—— 2011. Administrative strategies for a networked world: The educational imperative for inter-
governmental relations in 2020, in K. Thurmaier and J. Meek (eds) Network Governance: Implications for
Intergovernmental Relations in 2020. New York: Sage.
——, Jack W. Meek and Asim Zia. 2010. Governance Networks in Public Administration and Public Policy.
New York: CRC Press.
Krause, George A. and Kenneth J. Meier. 2005. Politics, Policy, and Organizations: Frontiers in the Scientic
Study of Bureaucracy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Krislov, Samuel. 1974. Representative Bureaucracy. Englewood Clis, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Lipsky, Michael. 1980. Street-Level Bureaucracy: Dilemmas of the Individual in Public Services. New York;
Russell Sage.
Lynn, Laurence E. Jr. 2001. The myth of the bureaucratic paradigm: What traditional public administration
really stood for, Public Administration Review 61(2): 14460.
March,
James G and
A. Simon Herbert. 1958. Organisations. New York: Wiley.
Poocharoen
344
Marmor, Theodore R. 1973. The Politics of Medicare. Chicago: Aldine and Atherton.
Marsh, David. 1998. Comparing Policy Networks. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
——and R.A.W. Rhodes. 1992. Policy Networks in British Government. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Mashaw, Jerry. 1983. Bureaucratic Justice: Managing Social Security Disability Claims. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
——and T.R. Marmor. 1988. Social Security: Beyond the Rhetoric of Crisis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Meier, K.J. 1997. Bureaucracy and democracy: The case for less democracy and more bureaucracy, Public
Administration Review 67(3): 19399.
Merton, Robert K. 1957. Bureaucratic Structure and Personality. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Mommsen, Wolfgang J. 1974. The Age of Bureaucracy: Perspectives on the Political Sociology of Max Weber.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Montjoy, Roberts S. and Douglas J. Watson. 1995. A case for reinterpreted dichotomy of politics and
administration as a professional standard in council-manager government, Public Administration Review
55(3): 2319.
Moore, Mark Harrison. 1995. Creating Public Value: Strategic Management in Government. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Mosher, Frederick C. 1968. Democracy and the Public Service. Oxford University Press: New York.
Mouritzen, Hans. 1990. The International Civil Service: A Study of Bureaucracy: International Organisations.
Aldershot: Dartmouth,
Muldoon, James P., Joann F. Aviel and Richard Reita. 2010. The New Dynamics of Multilateralism: Diplomacy,
International Organizations, and Global Governance. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Niskanen, W.A. 1973. Bureaucracy: Servant or Master? Lessons from America. Washington, DC: The Institute
of Economic Aairs.
—— 1974. Bureaucracy. Chicago: Aldine Press.
OLeary, Rosemary and Lisa Blomgren Bingham. 2009. The Collaborative Public Manager: New Ideas for the
Twenty First Century. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.
Olsen, Johan P. 2006. Maybe it is time to rediscover bureaucracy, Journal of Public Administration Research
and Theory 16(1): 124.
——and G. Peters. 1996. Lessons from Experience. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press,
Osborne, David and Ted Gaebler. 1993. Reinventing Government: How the Entrepreneurial Spirit is Transforming
the Public Sector. New York: PLUME.
Ouchi, William G. 1980. Markets, bureaucracies, and clans , Administrative Science Quarterly 25: 129 41.
Page,
C. and B.
Jenkins. 2006. Policy Bureaucracy: Government with a Cast of Thousands. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Parsons, D.W. 1995. Public Policy: An Introduction to the Theory and Practice of Policy Analysis. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar.
Parsons, Wayne. 1995. Public Policy: An Introduction to the Theory and Practice of Policy Analysis. Northampton,
NH: Edward Elgar.
Peters, B.G. 1981. The problem of bureaucratic government , The Journal of Politics 43(1): 56.
—— 1995. The Politics of Bureaucracy, 4th edn. New York: Longman Publishers USA,
—— 2010. Bureaucracy and democracy in the modern state, Public Administration Review 70(4): 6423.
——and John Pierre. 1998. Governance without government? Rethinking public administration, Journal
of Public Administration Reseach and Theory : 22343.
Pollitt, Christopher and Geert Bouckaert. 2004. Public Management Reform: A Comparative Analysis. Oxford:
Oxford University Press,
Pressman, Jerey L and Aaron B. Wildavsky. 1973. Implementation: How Great Expectations in Washington are
Dashed in Oakland. Berkeley: University of California Press,
Provan, Keith G and Patrick Kenis. 2007. Modes of network governance: structure, management, and
eectiveness, Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 18: 22952.
Rabin, Jack and James S. Bowman. 1984. Politics and Administration: Woodrow Wilson and Public Administration.
New York: Marcel Dekker.
Ramseyer, J.M and F.M. Rosenbluth. 1993. Japans Political Market Place. Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 2000. Transforming British Government. London: Macmillan,
Riggs, Fred W. 2001. Bureaucratic links between administration and politics, in Ali Farazmand (ed.)
Handbook of Comparative and Development Public Administration. New York: Marcel Dekker.
Bureaucracy and the policy process
345
Riper, Paul P Van. 1984. The politicsadministration dichotomy: Concept or reality, in Jack Rabin and
James S. Bowman (eds) Politics and Administration: Woodrow Wilson and Public Administration. New York:
Marcel Dekker, 20318.
Rourke, Francis E. 1984. Bureaucracy, Politics and Public Policy. Boston: Little, Brown.
Rutgers, Mark R. 2001. Splitting the universe: On the relevance of dichotomies for the study of public
administration, Public Administration Administration and Society 33(1): 320.
Saint-Martin, Denis. 2004. Building the New Managerialist State: Consultants and the Politics of Public Sector
Reform in Britain, Canada and France, 2nd edn. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Scott, W. Richard. 1992. Organizations: Rational, Natural, and Open Systems. Englewood Clis, NJ:
Prentice Hall.
Seldon, Sally Coleman. 1997. The Promise of Representative Bureaucracy: Diversity and Responsiveness in a
Government Agency. New York: M.E. Sharpe.
Shafritz, J.M. Jr. and A. Hyde. 2008. Classics of Public Administration, 6th edn. Boston: Wadsworth.
——, S. Ott and Y.S. Jang. 2010. Classics of Organization Theory. Boston: Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
Smith, B. 1988. Bureaucracy and Political Power. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.
Svara, James H. 1998. The politics-administration dichotomy model as aberration, Public Administration
Review 58(1): 518.
—— 1999. Complementarity of politics and administration as a legitimate alternative to the dichotomy
model, Administration and Society 30(6): 676705.
—— 2001. The myth of the dichotomy: complementarity of politics and administration in the past and
future of public administration, Public Administration Review 61(2) (March/April): 17683.
Thompson, J.A. 1965. Bureaucracy in a democratic society, in R. Martin (ed.) Public Administration and
Democracy. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press, 21012.
Wade, Robert. 1990. Governing the Market: Economic Theory and the Role of Government in East Asian
Industrialization. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
Weber, Max. 1946. Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, H.H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (ed. and trans.).
London: Oxford University Press,
West, William F. 1997. Searching
for a theory of bureaucratic structure, Journal of Public
Administration
Research and Theory: 591614.
Westoby, Adam. 1985. Introduction, in Bruno Rizzi (ed.), Adam Westoby (trans.) The Bureaucratization of
the World: The First English Edition of the Underground Marxist Classic that Analyzed Class Exploitation in the
USSR. New York: Free Press, 133.
White, Leonard D. 1926. Introduction to the Study of Public Administration. New York: Macmillan.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1979. The Politics of the Budgetary Process. Boston: Little, Brown.
—— 1986. Budgeting: A Comparative Theory of Budgetary Processes. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
——, Brendon Swedlow and Joseph White. 2006. Budgeting and Governing, Brendon Swedlow (ed.). New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers
Wilson, James Q. 1989. Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why they Do it. New York: Basic Books.
—— 2008. American Government Brief Version. Boston: Wadsworth.
Wilson, Woodrow. 1887. The study of administration, The Academy of Political Science: 197222.
World Bank. 1993. The East Asian Economic Miracle: Economic Growth and Public Policy. New York: Oxford
University Press,
Wu, Xun, Ling Hi Yan, Wen Sun Tung and Allen Lai. 2010. Public administration research,inReform
and Transition in Public Administration Theory and Practice in Greater China: 1978. Hong Kong: University
of Hong Kong.
Poocharoen
346
26
Disagreement and alternative
dispute resolution in the
policy process
Boyd Fuller
Introduction
Disagreement is a natural feature of the policy process, and negotiation is one of the common
processes for resolving it. Both are facts of life in the interdependent relationships among gov-
ernment and non-government actors involved in and impacted by the policy process. However,
the degree and kind of disagreements can have very dierent impacts on the ecacy and outcomes
of the policy process and its negotiations. Similarly, not all negotiation behaviors and processes
are equally eective and they need to be chosen strategically to suit the context and kind of
disagreement. Some negotiations are organized, visible, inclusive, and are managed using carefully
constructed processes. In other cases, they can be disorganized, hidden, exclusive, and ad hoc.
Whatever the case, where parties seek to cooperate, the quality of their negotiations and its
contribution to public value can be improved by using the best knowledge from the alternative
dispute resolution literature.
Studies on policy-making and the policy process tend to focus mostly on negotiations that are
convened to nd agreement among stakeholders who have varying interests and, where the policy
has become the subject for signicant disagreement among stakeholders, to resolve a dispute. As
such, mediation and consensus building theory have received the most attention. Negotiation
theory, however, provides much of the basis for them and so this chapter covers it too.
Negotiation theory starts with the premise that parties publicly stated positions mask their
needs and interests and that an eective negotiation must uncover the interests on all sides. After
that, interests can be met creatively through a multiplicity of dierent possible solutions, which
often also gain value through skillful trading across interests that the parties prioritize dierently.
More detail on negotiation theory is given in the next section.
Consensus building and mediation theory tell us about when parties can be brought together,
by whom, for what purposes, and using what kind of processes. Getting the process right is
important, and often challenging. In public policy settings, there are many processes and forums
in which stakeholder representatives can pursue the goals of their organization, and thus it may
be dicult to get stakeholders to authentically participate in negotiations until they are con-
vinced that the other venues cannot produce a better solution. Even when stakeholders do send
347
representatives to the negotiating table, it is often dicult to truly represent the constituencies,
which are often large, divided, and thus inexible. This inexibility increases when one or more
constituencies believe that fundamental values are at stake. Knowledge provides no assistance,
because it is often uncertain and contested. These challenges and the ideas and practices in the
consensus building literature that address these challenges are discussed below.
Finally, possible criteria for evaluating consensus building processes employed in the policy-
making process, the shortcomings in the literatures current data and the trials facing those
seeking to monitor and evaluate such processes in the future are summarized.
Negotiation theory as a starting point
Alternative dispute resolution theories about negotiation, mediation, and consensus building touch
upon all stages of the public policy process as long as there are interdependent parties who need
to cooperate to achieve a solution. In this section, I introduce the fundamental building blocks of
negotiation theory, which is the key building block for much of mediation and consensus building
theory as well. Negotiation, mediation, and consensus building theory approach a similar problem,
cooperation among parties with dierent interests, from slightly dierent perspectives. All are
focused on the challenges to and opportunities for improving the outcomes of negotiations.
Negotiation theory focuses on the barriers, strategies and tools relevant to individual parties
who are preparing for or participating in negotiations, and thus the ideas and practices proposed
are evaluated according to what benet they will bring one of the parties.
1
These parties can be
an individual, an organization, a nation, or some kind of grouping of these as long as they seek
to coordinate their actions together. However, the eld generally assumes that parties can do
better when they also help the other party(-ies) achieve results that are better than what the latter
might achieve when there is no cooperation. Otherwise, their counterpart will seek to meet
their interests elsewhere. (Fisher and Ury 1991)
Perhaps the most important building block of much of current negotiation theory is the
separation of interests and positions, which in practice are often conated by negotiators.
Negotiation theory denes positions as the stated wants and solutions that one party seeks to get
the other to accept. The underlying interests, on the other hand, are the wants and needs that
motivate the positions negotiators take. So, for example, an organization may demand that certain
best management practices for water management be required for farmers. That is their position.
Their interests, on the other hand, may be to preserve an ecosystem or particular species, to gain
political advantage in an upcoming election, or another want or need that can be fullled
should their position be accepted by the other parties.
To be able to negotiate interests rather than positions, it is important that the negotiating parties
also (a) identify the interests of their counterpart(s) in pre-negotiation research and in-negotiation
discussions and (b) determine how each party, including themselves, prioritizes their interests.
First, it is important to consider the interests of counterpart(s) because any idea we propose
should meet their interests as well or they will not agree. Second, not all interests are equally important,
and sometimes value can be gained when a negotiator agrees to a counterparts proposal on one
issue that impacts on less important interests as long as they get a more preferred option on
another issue which touches more important interests.
Getting interests on the table is also important for problem denition. The purpose of a
negotiation is, after all, to nd a solution that meets the interests of the parties as eectively as
possible. So, for example, in California, parties locked in a decades-long conict about water
allocation among agricultural and environmental uses were able to make progress when they
redened the problem. The conict had for many years revolved around two contentious
Fuller
348
questions: (a) which universal best management practices should be used on farms throughout
the state; and (b) and how much water could be saved by agricultural water users? The parties
were able to engage in more productive negotiation when they redened the problem by
asking, simply, how can downstream environmental objectives be met in a way that allows
farms to choose what means they employ for doing so? This denition touched more directly
on the interests of the various parties (preservation of environmental systems, self-determination
in managing farms and water, prot) and, once found, resulted in negotiations that reached an
unexpected and welcome agreement.
2
Once a negotiator clearly denes the interests of the parties to the negotiation, he or she
must then identify dierent possible solutions for meeting his or her own interests eectively.
Here, negotiation theory broadly distinguishes two kinds of solutions: options and alternatives.
Options are the set of possible solutions that the negotiating party thinks (a) are benecial
to themselves and (b) also meet the interests of their counterparts in the negotiation. The nego-
tiator is encouraged to prepare multiple options that can be combined to make deals possible; they
must also be willing to brainstorm additional ones as they learn more about the interests of the
other party(-ies). Often, value can be created on both sides if the right trades can be made,
especially those based on dierently prioritized interests, so that each side is trading something
that they want less for something that they want more. Alternatives, on the other hand, are the
set of possible solutions by which the party can meet its interests without the cooperation of
their counterpart. The most attractive of these alternatives, or the best alternative to a nego-
tiated agreement (BATNA), then becomes the minimum that a party will accept in the nego-
tiation, because no party should accept an agreement that produces less value for them than what
they could achieve elsewhere.
Interests, options, and alternatives are three elements of the Seven Elements Framework which
was developed by the Harvard Negotiation Project.
3
The other elements are objective criteria,
commitment, communication, and relationships. Objective criteria are external standards that
parties agree to as the basis for a decision about how value will be divided among them.
4
Com-
mitment is an important element in public policy and relates to the connection between the
negotiators, the constituencies they represent, the broader institutions of governance, and the
general public. Essentially, negotiators need to consider what authorization will be required for
proposed deals to be implemented. Such authorization can come from the support of key
individuals, but it may also require a change in regulation or law, the creation of a necessary
organization, or some other change in the policy, rules, or another institution. The relationship
element reminds negotiators that it is important to maintain and improve relationships with
their counterparts and that this relationship building should be done in parallel with the sub-
stantive elements of the negotiation, rather than depending on its outcomes. Finally, the commu-
nication element is where a negotiator will consider what information will be shared and sought,
and how he or she would like that process to proceed. Again, this is important in public policy
settings where information must be managed among multiple, complex constituencies, the broader
public, the media, and government decision-makers.
In the next section, this chapter introduces some of the challenges that make negotiation and
consensus building in policy-making dicult.
Why negotiations (and disagreements) in the policy process are
more difcult
Negotiations in the policy processes are marked by several factors that can make the management
of disagreement within them complex including challenges posed by managing the complexity
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
349
and scale, representing complex or unorganized constituencies, stakeholders contested knowledge,
and divergent values, frames, and belief systems. I describe each in more detail in this section.
Complexity and scale
As policies move through the policy process, discussions, debates, and negotiations occur in
many forums, some concurrently and some sequentially. Policy-making interactions can occur,
for example, in state and federal legislatures, courtrooms and administrative tribunals, the public
media, global and local multi-stakeholder processes and, of course, various backroom negotia-
tions. Each of these forums has its own rules and norms, includes dierent parties, and produces
diverse kinds of outcomes.
5
More importantly for negotiation, these forums can restrict or
encourage the participation of various stakeholders and other parties (e.g. experts and mediators).
Such choices are often made to set the table by promoting or discouraging certain interests,
ideas, and styles of deliberation (e.g. emotive vs. less emotive) as well as inuencing what resources
are brought to the table, how much and what information is shared (e.g. people are less likely
to disclose sensitive information to parties they mistrust), and the methods by which the support
of various constituencies be gained.
In addition, the visible processes are often not the only ones occurring nor are they always
the most important. In rooms out of view, some parties may enter in negotiations that shape
who gets standing, what issues are discussed, and other elements of the more ocial processes.
Similarly, the bigger, more visible negotiations impact the backroom ones. These backroom
negotiations may occur among fewer parties and exclude some stakeholders (de Sousa Briggs
2008), and there may be many smaller negotiations instead of one larger, multiparty one. In some
cases, the convening of less visible processes is on purpose, providing space for exploring new
ideas away from the inexible gaze of warring constituencies (Martinez et al. 2000; Fuller
2009b, 2009c)
Keeping track of all the parties and processes can become overwhelming and so it is not a
surprise that parties tend to reduce the complexity. Often they do so by forming coalitions
organized around common positions and belief systems. However, while coalitions can reduce
complexity, they also introduce some additional challenges. As coalitions form, they must
negotiate what they stand for. Often, these negotiations are settled by dicult compromises on
a common position that becomes inexible. However, negotiation theory argues that negotiating
from positions leads to unwise outcomes because of their inexibility and because they hide the
true wants and needs of the parties that could be solved in other ways more acceptable to their
counterparts.
In two-party negotiations, skilled negotiators can build relationships and manage commu-
nication with their counterparts to get at the interests and look for creative options and trades to
meet them concurrently with their own. However, as new ideas emerge from negotiations, each
side must consider quickly the impact of these ideas on their interests. Individuals can do so
quickly, but as the complexity of each entity increases, so does the time required to analyze the
new ideas, particularly when the parties in the constituency need to reopen negotiations among
themselves about what their joint response will bee.g. accept, reject, modify for the other partys
consideration.
Representing complex or unorganized constituencies
The classic problem of divergent interests between principal and agent presents one well-known
challenge.
6
Principal-agent or representative-constituency relationships are much more complex
Fuller
350
in public policy settings, however. First, constituencies are often too complex to be eectively
characterized as a single entity. Instead, constituencies are often divided by their internal
dierences in interests, values, and framese.g. when the constituency is an alliance of
multiple organized actorsor unorganized populations that have not yet formulated and
articulated what they stand for. In both cases, negotiators of these constituencies will nd it
dicult to negotiate well. They may become inexible, especially if their negotiating position is
the result of a hard-won compromise among the factions of the constituency, who would
naturally be reluctant to reopen their internal negotiations when the negotiators ask them to be
more exible.
Where constituencies are unorganized, it may be easy to ignore their interests and values at
rst. However, agreements can then be undermined if the unorganized feel that their interests
and values have been ignored. Mansbridge (1996) notes that policy systems often go through
cycles in which decisions are made which impact unorganized and uninterested groups, who
then organize to change the policies, which then can impact other old and new parties, and the
cycle repeats itself.
Of course, constituencies are not the only groups to which the negotiation and its parties are
beholden. In the public realm, any deals must also respect the institutions of governance. Where
there are sunshine laws which require transparency in public participation processes, for instance,
then the meetings must be open to the public, and thus negotiators may play to their home crowd
rather than seeking to make a potentially dicult deal. Whatever agreement is constructed must
also be allowable given the laws, policies and regulations of the government(s) involved or there
must be a plan to change the appropriate institution, perhaps along with a contingency plan
should that change turn out to be impossible.
In the next two sections, this chapter covers the challenges that arise when facts are contested
and stakeholders believe values are at stake.
Contested knowledge
Knowledge is one of the pillars for problem denition and the formulation of solutions. When
it is contested, identifying, developing, and deciding among multiple viable problem denitions
and solutions can be dicult. And yet, without knowledge, policy-making is blind, both in
what solution it chooses and also in what it learns from the implementation and evaluation of
that solution.
Contested knowledge arises from apparently competing claims about what data and ndings
are correct. Knowledge can dier across groups for two kinds of reasons. The rst kind relates
to the dierent frames and practices that each group employs in creating, validating, and dis-
seminating knowledge. The second kind occurs when parties choose which knowledge they
share for strategic rather than factual reasons: lying, withholding, and re-interpretation are all
possible activities here. I start with the rst kind.
Parties holding dierent frames may ask dierent questions about the environment and hold
to dierent facts and theories about how things work. Such disputes are hard to resolve in most
policy disputes. Data is often incomplete, uncertain, and often associated with one side or the
other. The problem is further exacerbated by how easily knowledge claims can be decon-
structed in the dierent policy forums. Much knowledge relies on a set of imperfect practices that
are nonetheless accepted within knowledge communities. The problem arises when such sci-
ence enters other forums which have dierent methods for generating and validating knowl-
edge. In the forums of public policylegislatures, courtrooms, scientic advisory committees,
and so onit is easy to argue that the knowledge of other parties is invalid. The standing of
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
351
dierent stakeholders as knowledge holders can be challenged. Assumptions and methodologies
can be questioned. The amount of uncertainty and risk that is acceptable for decision-making can
be contested. For example, local communities collect signicant data, but the method of its col-
lection (everyday practice and experience) and the form of its storage (often stories) is not
considered valid by many scientic communities (Fischer 2000; Corburn 2005; Fuller 2009a).
Those same communities, however, argue that much of expert science lacks the data that local
communities have, and that they overly simplify the complex situations on the ground and use
values and criteria for analyzing the meaning and impact of the data that do not reect the
values of the community. Furthermore, whosoever counts as an expert may be contested as
well, and a persons standing is often crucial for the authority of his analysis in addition to
whatever methods they use. Even the questions that the knowledge holders ask can be quite
dierent, and thus the data that one side collects may be seen by another side as the invalid
because its holder was asking the wrong question.
Furthermore, it would be naïve to neglect the strategic considerations behind contested knowl-
edge. A party that feels under threat may construct false data and ndings to protect its interests
(Forester 2005). Given the degree of uncertainty in todays knowledge about the many complex
systems being considered in public policy, such knowledge claims can be dicult to completely
refute. While their authenticity may be called into question, the claimers can also easily undermine
the knowledge claims of others. This again leaves policy analysts and makers with no one
legitimate set of facts that they can use to make authoritative policy.
Values, frames, and belief systems
Perception, interpretation, and the formulation of solutions are shaped by the lens through
which we view the world. Schön and Rein (1994) and Lewicki et al. (2003) argue that many
policy conicts are driven by the divergence among actors’“frames, which they describe as
normative/prescriptive stories that actors use to interpret the world, dene problems, and choose
actions. The frames that individuals, organizations, and coalitions use contain causal perceptions
that link actions and impacts as well as values about right and wrong. Similarly, Sabatier and
other students of the Advocacy Coalition Framework
7
argue that many long-term policy
disputes are driven by the presence of two or more advocacy coalitions that are organized around
divergent belief systems and who disagree about what should be done around a particular
policy issue.
Conicting values and frames pose several problems to eective negotiation. First, the dierent
interpretations and meanings actors attribute to actions, words, and phenomena often lead to
misunderstanding, which over time can lead to each side attributing hostile intentions to their
counterparts. Even the most well-meaning actions by one party may antagonize the other(s). In
some cases, leaders of one side may aggravate the situation by strategically misinterpreting the
others actions, since the creation and maintenance of a hostile enemy discourages the exploration
of internal disagreements and dierences.
Furthermore, the parties with divergent frames may dene problems quite dierently. Some
might, for example, see that slums are an unsightly blight which will then lead them to think of
removing the slums and placing its inhabitants elsewhere. Others might see slums as a place where
poor people work as a community to generate resources for self-reliance and see the problem
more as one of providing the right policy environment for that innovation to ourish. Often,
the dierences in stakeholders stories of problem denition and appropriate solutions are missed
by analysts and negotiators, who then attribute negative characteristics to the other side (unwilling
to listen, not intelligent, aggressive) instead of understanding that the two sides are having two
Fuller
352
mostly independent conversations in which they argue about solutions (positions) without rst
clarifying what problem each side is talking about and what problem they should be solving
as a group.
The problem is not only one of interpretation. When parties start speaking about values and
rights, negotiation becomes even more dicult. Conicts about values and rights are notoriously
more dicult to resolve than interest-based disputes (Tribe et al. 1976; Lord 1979; Susskind and
Field 1996; Fuller 2009b, 2009c). Once a party invokes one (or both), it becomes more dicult
for them to consider solutions that are dierent from their public positions since no one wants
to compromise their values. This is especially true when the negotiators represent constituencies
who have access to the meeting or its records. In these instances, negotiators tend to prefer
tough language, inexible positions, and disparaging language to maintain their reputation
within their constituency. All of these, unsurprisingly, provoke the other side to negotiate in a
similar fashion.
In public policy contexts, in which policy processes can extend over multiple years and even
over a decade, these problems of framing become hardened as negotiators can fall into unhelpful
routines and habits. In many cases, constituencies no longer believe that they have anything to
gain from cooperating with the other side, and will punish representatives who start exploring
those possibilities. Group polarization can occur, in which each side demonizes the other side,
attributing the worst intentions to their actions while suppressing their own internal dierences
(Northrup 1989; Sunstein 2002). As hostility grows, the ability of each side to negotiate becomes
more dicult as agreement is seen as a deal with the devil (Benjamin 1990; Mnookin 2010).
In the light of these challenges, it is not surprising that some authors propose that the parties
need to increase their understanding of one another. Schön and Rein argue that policy delib-
erations should help the parties put the others shoes on,
8
which means that each party can see
the problems, solutions, and other elements of their discussion using the same frames or belief
systems of their counterparts. In doing so, it is understood that the negotiating parties (or analysts)
should be able to reframe the negotiation in such a way that the problems of their divergent
belief systemsdierent and conicting interpretations of communication and phenomena,
problem denitions, and knowledgewill be resolved. What is not spelled out is how the parties
use this shared understanding and how they will make their solutions acceptable to the constituencies
who have not undergone this epiphany.
In the next section, I introduce and summarize consensus building and mediation theory, and
show what ideas and recommendations they put forward to manage and move through these
challenges.
Consensus building and mediation theory
Consensus building and mediation theory relate to the convening and management of nego-
tiation processes. In particular, they provide ideas, understandings, and guidance related to the
challenges of and better approaches to designing processes, convening stakeholders, managing
their negotiations, and promoting eective agreements. Both provide guidance about how the
parties can approach the challenges described in the previous section. Consensus building theory
focuses more on negotiations convened by actors other than the courts or other adjudicative
bodies. However, for the purposes of this chapter, there is enough similarity between the two
theories that I will hereafter refer to both as consensus building theory.
Negotiation theory is the building block for consensus building theory. Like negotiation
theory, consensus building theory emphasizes interests instead of positions, the desirability of
creating and investigating multiple options to meet interests, and so on. As a starting point,
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
353
consensus building theory promotes certain steps as part of an eective strategy, which for the
readers will seem mostly similar to the policy stages, save that evaluation is missing. I cover the
evaluation of these processes in the next section. For consensus building, the recommended
steps are
9
(with the equivalent policy stage in brackets):
convening the relevant parties (agenda-setting);
clarifying the rules and responsibilities for the group and its participants;
deliberating to develop options and then packages of options that seek to meet the needs of
the participating stakeholders as well as the public interest (policy formulation);
making decisions that have the support of all or almost all the stakeholders (decision-making);
implementing agreements and other commitments (implementation).
In the rest of this section, I describe the steps and highlight where they address the challenges
described above.
Conveninggetting the problem and parties right
Convening in consensus building is about the iterative design of the consensus building process.
Essential in convening are two tasks: getting the problem and parties right. Convening starts
with identifying the key players, including both nongovernment and government actors. Some
of these parties will need to participate in the proposed consensus building process. It often helps to
have certain key agencies or players openly support the processfor example, a prominent
leader might talk to certain people to gain their participation. Others may provide sta support,
particular expertise, monetary resources, or just observation. (Carlson 1999)
To get the problem right and the right parties at the table, consensus building theory argues
that a conict assessment should be conducted. A conict assessment occurs before the process is
ocially convened and is crucial both for process design, problem denition and for motivating
stakeholders to attend. In practice, a conict assessment is usually conducted by a neutral third
party who is often but not always the mediator. The assessors rst task is to identify and interview
potential stakeholders and their representatives. In these interviews, the conict assessment has
two basic tasks. The rst is to gather information about the parties, including their interests,
ideas for solutions, and their willingness to participate in the dialogue. The second task is to tell
them, and answer questions, about the conict assessment process and the proposed negotiation.
The latter is a part informing and part trust-building task. It allows the stakeholders to develop
more comfort about the process (Susskind and Thomas-Larmer 1999).
After the interviews, the conict assessor should put together a report, usually without attri-
bution, that summarizes what he or she has discovered about the parties and what process she
suggests for their negotiation. In some cases, the assessor might also recommend that the
negotiation should not proceed, especially if he or she believes that the parties are unlikely to
reach agreement. This report is shared with the parties who are asked to provide feedback on it.
Once it is completed, it will be handed over to the proposed convenor of the negotiations.
Again, this feedback is not only intended to improve the document, but also to build trust with
stakeholders. If they approve of the suggestions, they are more likely to attend when the
negotiations are convened.
As an agenda-setting exercise, conict assessment and the broader convening process is a proac-
tive means of determining who the parties are and what issues should be discussed. Participation
in a consensus building process is also voluntary and so the conict assessor will seek some
agenda of issues that attracts the interests of participants and decision-makers and will often seek
Fuller
354
an overarching framing of the issue that all sides agrees is a good start for the discussions. This
reframing and agreement on the agenda is an important rst step to dealing with problems of
divergent frames and beliefs and in keeping constituencies apprised and supportive of the
deliberations.
In some cases, for example, the conict assessor may propose that stakeholders can be grouped
into categories based on similar interests so that the common perspective can be spoken for by a
few selected representatives. The process can also be set up other forums in which the repre-
sentatives of large constituencies can meet with their selected representatives to debrief current
developments in the consensus building groups emerging ideas for vetting and feedback.
While consensus building theorys ideas about convening and conict assessment provide
some traction on the challenges discussed above, implementing them in practice is no trivial
task. For example, identifying the right stakeholders can be dicult when some of the interests
are held by populations and communities who are unorganized (Mansbridge 1996; Laws 1999).
Their members may not have realized that they do constitute a group or at least they may not
have chosen a representative. Where an organization has chosen a representative, that person may
not be the best choice for the negotiation because they are, for example, inexible and unwilling
to learn, poor negotiators, or unable to forge good working relationships with other partici-
pants. In other cases, some stakeholders may be reluctant to send a representative because they
feel that they have little to gainfor example, because they distrust each other, believe that the
convenor is unwilling or unable to translate their agreement into action, or feel that they can
achieve their interests and protect their values more eectively in other policy forums.
Clarifying rules and responsibilities
At the beginning of the process, the various parties should agree about the responsibilities of the
group and the various participants (stakeholders representatives, mediators, sta, experts, etc.).
For example, they need to determine what purpose the group is supposed to achieve, what pro-
ducts it seeks to produce, what roles and responsibilities, the mediator, negotiating representa-
tives, experts, and any other participating parties will take on, and so on. Ground rules will also
have to be established. Some will cover what parties can and cannot do during the delibera-
tions. Ground rules start with behavior at the table, but they can be extended to cover behavior
away from it as well. Examples include whether parties will pursue their interests in other
forums and whether and how the individual parties can share information with non-participants,
including constituencies, other ocials, the media, and so on.
Clarifying the responsibility of the group and its individuals is especially important when
parties believe values and rights are at stake (Forester 1999). A relatively safe environment for
dialogue and negotiation needs to be created when there is signicant mistrust among the par-
ties or about the process. By using rules to moderate the dialogue, and establishing norms of
good listening, mediators can help to create the conditions needed where parties can explore
each others claims about values in order to test their genuineness and to acknowledge them as
being legitimate. This inquiry and acknowledgment need not mean agreement.
Also, ground rules are important in terms of moderating how information is shared with
others outside the group. Rules favoring transparency, for example, are common in some
countries but while they have normative appeal, they may hamper communication and pro-
blem-solving in cases where the parties do not trust each other. Where constituencies distrust
representatives who make overtures to the other side, it may make more sense for some of the
negotiations to take place out of the public eye. During the less visible negotiations, the
representatives can listen more carefully and explore some new ideas without fear of censure.
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
355
However, when this is done, there should be clear ground rules and a strategy for how infor-
mation will be shared with constituencies, decision-makers, and the public (Martinez et al.
2000; Fuller 2009c).
Deliberating to nd and package options
To develop a solution, the parties need ideas that go beyond the initial positions that each bring
to the table. These ideas, when combined, need to produce potential agreements that all parties
see as being better than that which they could achieve in another forum (i.e. their best alter-
native to a negotiated agreementBATNA). These ideas start as discrete solutions to dierent
parts of the puzzle that the group is trying to solve. Some may provide value to all parties;
others may benet only some of the parties. This packaging is made more eective when parties
prioritize among their interests, and then look for trade-os in which each party gives up
something less important in exchange for something more important. As parties move toward a
solution, they will begin to package these ideas together more and more, with each party
examining the emerging packages to determine whether their set of interests is being met more
eectively in the proposed deal than in their best alternative.
10
Often this packaging is done using single texts. Single textssuch as draft agreements, charts,
and mapscan be used to synthesize and present certain understandings, draft ideas, and mile-
stones during the process. They can be records created by the mediator that the parties agree
clarify areas of emerging agreement and ongoing contention, including possible solutions, facts,
and so on. Stakeholders can use draft agreements to organize their deliberation, by adding,
subtracting, and modifying text in the single text until they can agree to what is stated there.
Making decisions
In negotiations between two individuals, the decision is simply made by the parties at the table.
In any other negotiations, decision-making becomes more complex, especially as the number of
parties and constituencies increases. Public policy involves many stakeholders and so most nego-
tiations will include more than two parties. Since not all these negotiations will require unani-
mity to make a decision, a decision rule must be agreed upon at the beginning of the negotiation.
Such a decision rule could be simply 50 percent plus one or some kind of supra-majority such as 66
percent. It might also be a weighted majority. For example, the Kyoto Protocol decision rule
required that at least 55 percent of the countries approve the deal and that the aggregate percentage
of emissions represented by those countries must exceed 55 percent of the worlds total emissions.
While the parties may make a decision at the table, the work of decision-making is not done.
The transition to implementation often requires signicant eorts to gain support from key
members of constituencies and other parties who will be crucial to the decisions implementa-
tion. In international cases, the decision will likely have to be formally ratied, which requires
an additional set of negotiations within the constituency.
Implementation
Decision-making and implementation are in fact intertwined in consensus building. Decisions
should not be made until the parties are fairly sure that they will get the support needed from
decision-makers (legislators, community leaders, agency ocials, etc.) who were not at the table.
In well-managed processes, draft ideas and agreements will be shared with such leaders to get
their feedback and seek their backing. Where success is unlikely, the negotiators should consider
Fuller
356
other options even if the parties agree the rst idea is superior. Where success is possible, the
parties then consider what additional mechanisms and responsibilities should be built into the
recommendations to improve their implementation. For example, the parties might agree to
lobby particular parties together to gain support for the recommendations.
Sometimes, the negotiations may also ignore various additional forums to test the emerging ideas
with constituencies and the wider public. The city of Chelsea, Massachusetts, for instance, created
a new city charter using a consensus building process in which developments were continually
revealed to the public for their feedback and then support using radio and other media.
Often the convenor of a negotiation or consensus building process has the major role in
implementing the recommendations. The negotiating groups themselves rarely have formal
authority to make decisions. Instead, they make recommendations that they expect the convening
actor to translate into an agenda, set of solutions, or a policy or program to be implemented as
part of the policy process. In reality, the conveners may choose to follow only some or even
none of the recommendations, though they put their legitimacy at peril when they do so. Or
they may adopt them all but struggle to implement them in practice.
Finally, as the literature on public policy has also found, implementation brings about its dif-
ferent interpretations of the agreement, as well as new misunderstandings and disagreements. An
eective agreement often includes provisions for how the parties will manage their disagreements
and disputes during the implementation (Podziba 1999).
Evaluating negotiations and mediations in the public sector
Negotiations that occur in policy processes can be both easy and very dicult to assess. At rst
brush, they are easy to evaluate because as long as the parties are satised, then the negotiations
can be deemed to be a success. If eciency is a concern, one could look at the interests of the
dierent actors and see from a dispassionate viewpoint whether one or both of the parties could
have done better without any party losing gains (Raia 1982; Raia et al. 2002).
However, scholars of the policy process can and should ask more demanding questions of
such negotiations (Coglianese 2003). We ask that policy processes be ecient in time and
resources, wise in the use of the best knowledge, and fair in how the process is conducted and
how resources are allocated. In this light, Bingham (2003) proposes that there are three possible
kinds of benets from negotiations in the public sector: substantive, process, and relationships.
Substantive benets revolve around improved outcomes. One common claim is that the out-
comes of negotiations are better than that achievable by each party without their agreement and
cooperation (their BATNA). Similarly, some point to the creativity sparked by options, in
which new ideas emerge from the deliberations among the participants. Proponents of public
dispute resolution also argue that when parties do negotiate and their recommendations are imple-
mented by the convening actor, stakeholders are more likely to support, or at least not actively
oppose, the subsequent policy. This logic is also used to argue that the policies developed by
such negotiations are better than those developed through other processes.
Process benets include reduced time and resources to reach an implementable policy. A
negotiation can also increase the perceived fairness of the process by providing opportunities for
new actors to participate and by giving each actor an equal chance to present and advocate for
their interests. A negotiation may also be considered more fair and wise when multiple forms of
knowledge are brought to the table and when joint fact-nding allows the group as a whole to
decide what facts they will accept.
Relationship benets can include better personal relationships among the representatives who
negotiated or between the groups who were represented. Groups can learn that the other side is
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
357
reasonable even if they have come to dierent conclusions. They may share more information
and thus be better informed. Future negotiations and other deliberative and policy-making
processes may go more smoothly because the parties now understand one another better.
Unfortunately, the research on evaluating such processes is still in its infancy and faces several
key challenges. Data can be hard to access because the group agreed to condentiality. Many studies
of negotiations in the public sector are individual, descriptive case studies rather than hypothesis
testing, higher-n inquiries. These cases tend to be custom-designed to t each context and they
occur in a wide variety of settings, both of which makes them dicult to compare. The cases
tackled through negotiation are suciently dierent from other cases in that it is dicult to
compare the eectiveness of traditional policy-making processes with those supplemented by
negotiation (Emerson et al. 2003).
In addition, many of the evaluations are written up by mediation practitioners, which raises
the possibility of bias. Finally, negotiations convened in and around policy processes are not dis-
crete phenomena. Even a process that fails to reach an agreement may produce information that
improves the policy process or result in improved relationships, thus reducing the amount of
conict manifest in other stages of the policy process.
Conclusions
Negotiation itself has always been a part of policy-making. However, the push in recent dec-
ades for more inclusive and science-based processes has brought negotiation out of the back
halls and legislatures to include a wider group of people who set the agenda, seek inclusive and
creative solutions, and make and implement agreements. Such negotiations can touch any part
of the policy process. They may, for example, be used to set the agenda, to create ideas for policy
formulation, to make recommendations that inform decisions, and to aid in the implementation
of policies.
Negotiation and consensus building rely on the parties to share information and to be open
to new ideas. To make the negotiations productive in public policy settings, much care must be
taken to help the stakeholders to be willing and able to engage one another even when they
feel that values are at stake or that they cannot trust the other parties. Such negotiations must be
carefully convened, usually through an interactive conict assessment that helps the convenor
and mediator determine the agenda and process design and otherwise bring the parties together
ready to talk about a solvable problem. For the negotiation to be credible and eective, it must
be strategically linked to the ongoing policy-making process and to decision-makers outside
government as well.
Knowledge is often contested and so mediators must help the parties to engage in joint fact-
nding so that they have a common set of agreed-upon facts for their deliberations. Joint fact-
nding does not necessarily result in one agreed-upon theory or interpretation of the data, but
it is a common foundation for discussions about what is happening and what might happen if
changes are made.
Notes
1 This summary of negotiation theory draws upon several sources, including Fisher and Ury (1991), Lax
and Sebenius (2006), and Raia (1982).
2 For more information on water conicts in California and the challenges and opportunities of nego-
tiating them, see Fuller (2009b, 2009c) and the special issue on the CALFED Bay Delta Program in the
Environmental Science and Policy Journal 12(6).
3 See Fisher and Ury (1991) and the Program on Negotiation website: http://www.pon.harvard.edu.
Fuller
358
4 For example, negotiators might refer to pollution standards in other areas with similar conditions and
industries as a fair way of setting the standard for their own region.
5 Some outcomes are enforceable decisions, some provide input or analysis, and some have no real
outcomes even as they try to increase the legitimacy of the processfor example, courtroom decisions
have legal backing that encourages implementation while global agreements rely on national legislatures
to ratify and enforce agreements.
6 Principles and agents interests are not always aligned, and thus agents may act in ways that serve the
agents interests rather than the interests of the principle who hired them.
7 For more information about the Advocacy Coalition Framework, see Chapter 10 in this volume and
Sabatier and Weible (2007).
8 See Schön and Rein (1994) and Rein and Schön (1996).
9 See Susskind (2005) and Susskind and Cruikshank (2006).
10 In fact, where parties, problems, and solutions are many and complex, negotiating groups often focus
most of their eorts on developing, modifying, and make decisions by focusing mostly on packages, as opposed
to the discrete trades often discussed and analyzed in the negotiation literature (Innes and Booher 1999,
Fuller 2009c).
Bibliography
Benjamin, M. 1990. Splitting the Dierence: Compromise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics. Lawrence, KS:
University Press of Kansas.
Bingham, G. 2003. Foreword,inR.OLeary and L.B. Bingham (eds) The Promise and Performance of
Environmental Conict Resolution. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.
Carlson, C. 1999. Convening, in L. Susskind, S. McKearnan and J. Thomas-Larmer (eds) The Consensus
Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement. Thousand Oaks, CA, Sage.
Coglianese, C. 2003. Is satisfaction enough? Evaluating public participation in regulatory policymaking,
in R.OLeary and L.B. Bingham (eds) The Promise and Performance of Environmental Conict Resolution.
Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.
Corburn, J. 2005. Street Science: Community Knowledge and Environmental Health Justice. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
de Sousa Briggs, X. 2008. Democracy as Problem Solving: Civic Capacity in Communities Across the Globe.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Emerson, K., T. Nabatchi R. OLeary and J. Stephens 2003. The challenges of environmental conict
resolution,inR.OLeary and L.B. Bingham (eds) The Promise and Performance of Environmental Conict
Resolution. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.
Fischer, F. 2000. Citizens, Experts, and The Environment: The Politics of Local Knowledge. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Fisher, R. and W. Ury. 1991. Getting to Yes: Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In. New York: Penguin
Books.
Forester, J. 1999. Dealing with deep value dierences, in L. Susskind, S. McKearnan and J. Thomas-
Larmer (eds) The Consensus Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement. Thousand
Oaks, CA: Sage, 46393.
—— 2005. Policy analysts can learn from mediators, in J.T. Schloz and B. Stiftel (eds) Adaptive Governance
and Water Conict: New Institutions for Collaborative Planning. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future,
15063.
Fuller, B. 2009a. Local knowledge and consensus building: from access to impact,
LKY School of
Public
Policy Working Papers, SPP09-08.
—— 2009b. Moving Through Value Conict: Consensus Building and Trading Zones for Resolving Water Disputes .
Wiesbaden: VDM Verlag Dr. Mueller e.K.
—— 2009c. Surprising cooperation despite apparently irreconcilable dierences: Agricultural water use
eciency and CALFED, Environmental Science and Policy 12(6): 66373.
Innes, J.E., Booher, D.E. 1999. Consensus building as role playing and bricolage: Towards a theory of
collaborative planning, Journal of the American Planning Association, 65(1): 926.
Laws, D. 1999. Representation of stakeholding interests, in L. Susskind, S. McKearnan and J. Thomas-
Larmer (eds) The Consensus Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement. Thousand
Oaks, CA: Sage, 24185.
Disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
359
Lax, D.A. and J.K. Sebenius. 2006. 3-D Negotiation: Powerful Tools to Change the Game in your Most Important
Deals. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press.
Lewicki, R.J. and B. Gray. 2003. Framing of environmental disputes, in R.J. Lewicki, B. Gray and M. Elliott
(eds) Making Sense of Intractable Environmental Conict: Concepts and Cases. Washington, DC: Island Press.
Lord, W.B. 1979. Conict in federal water resource planning , Water Resources Bulletin 15(5): 122635.
Mansbridge, J.J. 1996. Using power/ghting power: The polity, in S. Benhabib (ed.) Democracy and Dierence.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Martinez, J., L.E. Susskind, et al. 2000. Parallel informal negotiation: An alternative to second track
diplomacy, International Negotiation 5(3): 56986.
Mnookin, R. 2010. Bargaining with the Devil: When to Negotiate, When to Fight. New York, Simon and
Schuster.
Northrup, T.A. 1989. The dynamic of identity in personal and social conict, in L. Kriesberg, T. A.
Northrup and S. J. Thorson (eds) Intractable Conicts and their Transformation. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse
University Press.
Podziba, S. 1999. ‘“Case 3. The Chelsea Charter consensus process, in L. Susskind, S. McKearnan and
J. Thomas-Larmer (eds) The Consensus Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement,
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Raia, H. 1982. The Art and Science of Negotiation. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University
Press.
——, J. Richardson and David Metcalfe 2002. Negotiation Analysis: The Science and Art of Collaborative
Decision Making. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Rein, M. and D. Schön. 1996. Frame-critical policy analysis and frame-reective policy practice, Knowledge
and Policy: The International Journal of Knowledge Transfer and Utilization 9(1): 85104.
Sabatier, P.A. and C. Weible. 2007. The advocacy coalition framework: Innovations and clarications,i
n
P.A. Sabatier (ed.) Theories
of the Policy Process. Boulder, CO, Westview Press.
Schön, D.A. and M. Rein. 1994. Frame Reection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies.
New York: Basic Books.
Shafritz, Jay M., J. Steven Ott, and Yong Suk Jang. 2010. Classics of Organization Theory. Boulder, CO:
Wadsworth Cengage Learning.
Sunstein, C.R. 2002. The law of group polarization, Journal of Political Philosophy 10(2): 17595.
Susskind, L.E. 2005. Consensus building and ADR: Why they are not the same thing?,inM.Mott and
R. Bordone (eds) The Handbook of Dispute Resolution. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass.
—— and P. Field. 1996. Dealing with An Angry Public: The Mutual Gains Approach to Resolving Disputes.
New York: Free Press.
—— and J. Thomas-Larmer. 1999. Conducting a conict assessment, in L. Susskind, S. McKearnan and
J. Thomas-Larmer (eds) The Consensus Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
——and J.L. Cruikshank. 2006. Breaking Roberts Rules: The New Way to Run Your Meeting, Build Consensus,
and Get Results. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tribe, L.H., C.S. Schelling and John Voss 1976. When Values Conict: Essays on Environmental Analysis,
Discourse, and Decision. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger Publishing Company.
Fuller
360
27
Governance, networks and
intergovernmental systems
Robert Agranoff, Michael McGuire and Chris Silvia
Governments today operate within systems of governance that include interacting govern-
mental bodies and nongovernmental organizations (NGO). These interconnections have
increased dramatically in recent decades because of increased intergovernmentalization and
government externalization. The former refers to grant, regulatory, and related vehicles of
connecting central and subnational governments and the latter to moving governmental func-
tions and services delivery outside governments boundaries through contracting, vouchers for
goods and services, and related means of privatization. This has led to the need to capture the
essence of public activity as governance, a mix of all kinds of governing eorts by all manner
of socio-political actors, public as well as private; occurring between them at dierent levels, in
dierent governing modes and orders (Kooiman 2003: 3). Such interactive governance
increasingly occurs within networks of government ocials and NGO actors, that is structures
of interdependence involving multiple organizations or parts thereof, where one unit is not
merely the formal subordinate of the others in some larger hierarchical arrangement (OToole
1997: 45).
Collaboration
In governance networks, the actors depend on the collaboration imperative, that is the actions
of ocials and managers crossing the boundaries of their organizations working in dyadic, tria-
dic, or networked relationships that are transactional. These actions bring on the need for col-
laborative actions beyond cooperation, working jointly in some fashion, creating or discovering
solutions within given constraints, for example knowledge, time, money, legal authority, or other
resources. As such, collaborative management is a concept that describes the process of facil-
itating and operating in multi-organizational arrangements to solve problems that cannot be
solved, or solved easily, by single organizations (Agrano and McGuire 2003: 4). Collaborative
activity among the actors within governance makes their home organizations more conductive,
organizing its work for external as well as internal activity. A conductive organization is one that
continuously generates and renews the capabilities to achieve breakthrough performance by
enhancing the quality and ow of knowledge and by calibrating its strategy, culture, structure
and systems externally (Saint-Onge and Armstrong 2004: 213).
361
The transformation of intergovernmental relations
The era of governance networks has also transformed intergovernmental relations (IGR) beyond
its traditional scope as involving combinations of interdependencies and inuences among
public ocials working on nancial, policy, and political issues (Krane and Wright 1998: 1168) to
incorporate waves of collaborative operationalism external to governments as well as between
them. Indeed, IGR has evolved through four distinct waves of development including the
current network era (Agrano 2010).
The rst, law and politics, emerged with the building of integral nation-states, primarily in
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, where legal distinctions of governmental isolation and
jurisdiction held true. Generally, responsibilities were separated and isolated. The dual feder-
alism doctrine in the United States held that the national government and the states were each
sovereign in their respective spheres and that between them exist areas of activity in which neither
can enter. While there is reasonable evidence that completely separate spheres never existed in
practice (Elazar 1962), the legal distinction and intergovernmental norms of separation held for
some time, despite the fact that by the mid-1800s modern communications, which required a series
of local delivery units (postal units, roads, canals, railways) and cross-links, pushed jurisdictional
separation to its limits.
This situation changed from the early twentieth century to roughly the 1960s when the
welfare state ushered in the second epoch. It marked a time of growth and more professional
central governments that also included an increasing interdependency that linked subnational
and central governments (Skowronek 1982). In particular, the welfare state was very much a
top-down eort that enhanced the scal and program strength of national governments every-
where (Loughlin 2007: 389). Most central social policies (welfare, social services, employment,
economic development) were polity-wide because central governments were suspicious of uni-
versal local commitment, so national nancing and programming were linked with local com-
mitment (Ashford 1988: 18). Later in the era came newer social welfare programs, for example
drug abuse, child and family abuse, mental disabilities, and new eorts in community develop-
ment, which were less suited to central organizations, bringing on the need for important
intergovernmental adjustments (ibid.: 19). The resulting impact was considerable jurisdiction
overlap (Watts 1999: 38).
By the middle of the twentieth century governments began to recognize the gradual intro-
duction of organized actors outside government as also involved in funding and programming,
particularly in Western Europe and the Anglo-American countries. NGOs became agents and
partners of the state (Rhodes 1997). Through some grants but predominantly by contracts, gov-
ernments linked with nonprot service agencies and for-prot vendors of services. In the case of
nonprots, they had been around for decades but the boundaries of the state expanded to
include them in various forms of externalized direct services delivery, a sort of government for
hire (Smith and Lipsky 1993: 5). For-prots have always been part of government procurement,
and certain basic services like building security and road building were regularly contracted out,
but now such direct government services as public health care, services for the disabled, voca-
tional rehabilitation, mental health, substance abuse, and family violence, along with nance and
accounting services and other management functions, are contracted out. Just as the welfare state
philosophy once expanded the role and number of involved governments, beliefs in the primacy of
market forces, reduction and importance of the public sector, deregulation of state controls, and
abandonment of the principle of equality led to a prevailing political view of a more minimalist
state, with less direct government intervention in the economy and society (Loughlin 2007:
390). Market superiority that could either provide for the needs of people or a market-model
Agranoff et al.
362
of government services that could provide greater eciencies than by public operation prevailed
as an attitude. This also was the era of the New Public Management (NPM), with heavy bor-
rowing from the private sector with its benchmarking, performance targeting, competitive
bidding, outsourcing, and the like, all of which reinforced IGR by government/NGO part-
nerships (Hood 1991). This led to new sets of alliances between governments at all levels and a
host of public and private bodies. Thus, the public administration problem has spread well
beyond the borders of the government agency (Salamon 1995: 2).
The fourth and currently developing IGR network era gradually emerged out of the pre-
vious era and became fully acknowledged in the rst decade of the twenty-rst century. It has
been dubbed a world where everything is connected in networks (Castells 1996). Public agen-
cies and NGOs now network for purposes of exchanging information, enhancing one anothers
capabilities, smoothing services interactions, and solving policy/program problems (Agrano
2007). In some ways, IGR networking began as a parallel activity to contracting, where funders
and their agents began to build contractor-government networks (Brown and Potoski 2004;
Van Slyke 2007), building on prior networks of local government, business associations, and
economic development agents who have worked among themselves at the community level for
some four or ve decades, and these entities have had extensive links with higher level gov-
ernments in order to secure support to promote local economies (Agrano and McGuire 2003;
Eisinger 1988; McGuire 2002). The emergent set of intergovernmental networksand what
makes them dierentis the way ocials from the dierent levels of governments and NGOs
representing the nonprot sectors are challenged to sit down with one another at the same table
to deal with uncertainties and discuss, explore, negotiate, and solve issues (Koppenjan and Klijn
2004; Radin et al. 1996).
The network construct
While just one of a number of vehicles in the panorama of governance (Thompson 2003: 150,
237; Salamon 2002: 11), networks involve a cluster or complex of organizations connected to
each other by resource dependencies and are distinguished from other clusters or complexes by
breaks in the structure of resource dependencies (Rhodes and Marsh 1992). In order to broaden
the discourse on networks (Thompson 2003: 9) into a potential theory in this area, it is important
to understand dierentiation of governance capacity when the potential role of networks is
considered to construct a more nuanced understanding of the relative contributions which
these actions now make to the governance of society (Peters 2000: 47, 50). This implies that
both network opportunities and barriers are equally important to understanding any outcomes
and process elements (Scharpf 1978: 346) in any set of macro-level theories of the state
(Rhodes and Marsh 1992: 203).
To focus on governance networks requires the drawing of parameters around use of the term
network. As Rhodes (2003: 21) suggests, network is an everyday term used by consumers
and managers (and perhaps politicians) to describe the web of relationships in which they are
embedded, giving rise to dierent meanings that need to be captured. Here we focus on the
construction of meanings given by government managers and their interlocutors as they work
within organized entities that involve parts of organizations nonhierarchically (OToole 1997).
As such, we are not directly focusing on the broader issue of democratic network governance,
that is, cross-sectoral and based in civil society involvement where issues of deliberation and
citizen responsibility, as well as questions of equity, accountability, and democratic legitimacy to
serve public purposes are at stake (Bogason and Toonen 1998; Skelcher 2004; Sorenson and
Torng 2007). Although we clearly realize that network management is a central part of
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
363
public network governance and impacts it in many ways (for example, it could limit participa-
tion and representation), we choose here to focus more directly on managerial arrangements
and behaviors that contribute to policy theory within larger issues of democratic participation
and governance. We thus use the term network to refer to structures involving multiple
nodesagencies and organizationswith multiple linkages, ordinarily working on cross-boundary
collaborative activities.
Networks and their work
Some networks are constructs based more or less on forms of linkages and are intermittently
interactive and cooperative, that have been identied as serendipitous, whereas others are goal-
directed and are based on more regularized interactions (Kildu and Tsai 2003: 91), that is the
action of networking (Alter and Hage 1993). The latter can be either chartered or nonchartered
in character. Both types of networks share certain characteristics: permanent status; regular formal
meetings; a denable communication system; leaders and participants; taskforces or work groups;
identiable operating structures; identiable partners; and some form of division of labor/task
allocation. Chartered networks are formally established as organized entities. In the United States
they are often established by intergovernmental agreement, registration as a 501c(3) nonprot
organization, by act or resolution of a state legislature, a governors executive order, and/or through
corporate registration with a state government representative, such as the secretary of state.
Nonchartered networks have no such formal-legal status, but their continuing presence and
operations, regular meetings, concrete problem-solving actions, websites, newsletters, and the like
are testimony to their existence. Many longstanding networks are non-chartered. Nonchartered
networks are often harder to locate in telephone directories or on websites than those that have
been formalized, but those without chartered status prove to be equally viable bodies.
Networks need to be understood in the context of how they operate. Five basic characteristics
of their functioning provide a context for understanding formation, operation, and value-adding.
First, not all networks are alike; whereas some exchange information, some build partner capacity,
some blueprint strategies and process interorganizational programming, and some make
policy/program adjustments. Some do more than one or more. Second, networks are non-
hierarchical but organized into collaborarchies that blend todays conductive bureaucracies with
voluntary organization-like structures. The key is not the ocial leaders but their champions,
vision-keepers, technical cores, and sta. They are mainly organized around work and working
groups as communities of practice. Third, the most important function of these communities is
to discover, organize, and engage in knowledge management (KM). The KM process binds the
network as it approaches problems of a multi-organization, multijurisdictional orientation. Fourth,
networks are overlays on the hierarchies of participating organizations. They inuence but do not
control home agency decisions. The core work of the public agency goes on but in an
increasingly conductive manner. Fifth, networks do add public value. To varying degrees they
help multiple organizations to engage in problem identication and information exchange,
identify extant knowledge, adapt emergent technologies, engage in KM, build capacity, develop
joint strategies and programs, and adjust policies and programs (Agrano 2007).
Governance networks and public policy
The rst group of scholars to deal with the network concept in IGR were those who dealt with
policy implementation (Marsh and Smith 2000). As IGR expanded through welfare state pro-
grams and beyond the problem became, as Sundquist (1969: 12) observes, how to achieve
Agranoff et al.
364
goals that are established by the national government, through the actions of other governments.
In most cases, he concludes, governments choose to rely upon systems of mutual adjust-
ment rather than through the exercise of hierarchical authority (1969: 19). Implementation
then began to focus on the interaction of actors down the line as they attempted to make
programs work (Ingram 1977; Pressman 1975; Pressman and Wildavsky 1973; Williams 1980).
The network of actors, particularly at the bottom rung of the chain of implementation, became
a focal point of research (Elmore 1985; Hjern and Porter 1981; Lynn 1981). In one of the early
studies of implementation by network, Scharpf concludes that:
it is unlikely, if not impossible, that public policy of any signicance could result from the
choice process of any single unied actor. Policy formulation and implementation are inevi-
tably the result of interactions among a plurality of separate actors with separate interests,
goals, and strategies.
(1978: 347)
As such, he concludes that research should go beyond the strategies of policy formulation and
implementation but include the more structured and stable relations between organizations.
Network formation
The policy implementation connection
The formation of networks is, in many cases, driven organically by the simple need to combine
resources in ways that facilitate the implementation of a program. Networks are also formed by
legislation or are mandated by others. Hall and OToole (2000) examined the US institutional
arrangements incorporated into the legislation enacted by the eighty-ninth and the one hundred
and third Congresses. They found that the majority of signicant new legislation prescribed the
involvement of collaborative structures for policy implementation. Their ndings
demonstrate that the institutional settings in which public programs are placed, at least via
national legislation, are multiorganizational and networked rather than unitary and unam-
biguously hierarchical. Most new and amended programs encounter implementation set-
tings of the more complicated varietieswith intergovernmental and/or cross-sectoral
involvement more the rule than the exception. The arrays for program execution also
require signicant and skilled public management, particularly because the extent of interunit
coordination required for program success is often substantial The networked reality of
todays public management, furthermore, is important but clearly not unprecedented.
Subsequent research by the authors showed that post-legislation rule-making by implementing
federal agencies also led to collaborative administrative arrangements (Hall and OToole 2004).
Pressman and Wildavsky (1973) were among the rst to discuss public policy in terms of
shared administration, suggesting the networked nature of policy implementation. Based on an
empirical investigation of the US Economic Development Administrations attempts in the
1960s to address unemployment of minorities in Oakland, California, their ndings describe the
multiplicity of participants and perspectives from all levels of government pursuing policy goals
that in practice may be conicting. The evidence from Europe is the same: collaborative
structures used for implementing manpower training in Germany and Sweden in the 1970s
were characterized at that time in terms of multiple power centers with reciprocal relationships,
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
365
many suppliers of resources, overlapping and dynamic divisions of labor, diused responsibility
for actions, massive information exchanges among actors, and the need for information input
from all actors (Hanf et al. 1978). More than three decades ago, Hjern and Porter (1981)
described implementation structures that operate with representatives of dierent agencies and
exercise considerable discretion in practice. Many policy studies in the 1980s revealed the extent
of collaboration in public policy implementation (Hull with Hjern 1987; Mandell 1984;
OToole 1985). There is thus a rich history of networked policy implementation.
Activating networks
Activating a network for the purposes of policy planning and/or implementation requires a
heavy dose of developmental activity on the part of some partners who act either as champions
or promoters (or vision keepers). Exclusivity or limited involvement leads to information and
support gaps, as well as lost potential in interagency adjustment, so network managers need to
know who has the critical policy-making resources: money, technology, information, expertise,
time, and other necessary commodities (Agrano 2003). Even if networks are formed through
mandated action, there is still the need to recruit constantly by enlisting necessary partners who
possess particular resources, expertise, and support for the networks activities. All networks
depend on one or a small number of champions not just to help establish the network, but also,
perhaps most importantly, to maintain commitment among network partners.
Networks are based in at least four dimensions. First, all network structures have a technical
core, or knowledge about how to do it (Agrano 2007). For example, internal and external
expertise is a mainstream source of technical knowledge. Most participants will ask sta scientists
or specialists inside and outside governments, along with university-based researchers, to share their
technological knowledge with the network. In environmental and natural resource networks,
engineering knowledge that deals with ooding and oodplain concerns, water supply, water
quality, agricultural use, and recreation and wildlife management are all at the forefront of partici-
pating agency needs. In local economic development, city administrators, development directors,
and NGO development corporation executives work to revise development plans, requiring
expertise in engineering and planning; they negotiate nancing mechanisms with local business
groups, nancial institutions, and state and federal governments; and they handle issues of water
capacity and waste water with the state environmental agency. The network activities become a
technical basis of intergovernmental/interorganizational exchange.
Second, there is also a legal dimension that denes whether a particular networked action can
be undertaken. Laws governing each entity aect the ability of any single organization to act.
An added overlay is the set of legal norms governing the management activity, whether it is law
determining the formal structure (e.g. task force, committee, coalition) or the general legal fra-
mework governing any project that a network might undertake. Control of operations may be
achieved through the use of government regulations that constrain the actions of network
partners, through the distribution of funds or manpower, or through regulations that stipulate
the powers and responsibilities of certain actors or specify what conditions potential actors must
meet before they can qualify to be members of a collaborative structure.
Third, nancial feasibility is another important dimension of networks. Can we aord it? is
a central question in any public undertaking. Perhaps the most contentious, dicult, but necessary
element of networking is pooling nancial resources. Such sharing or pooling is implicit in
Barbara Graysdenition of collaboration in which she asserts that it is the pooling of appreciations
and/or tangible resources, e.g., information, money, labor, and so on, by two or more stake-
holders to solve a set of problems which neither can solve individually (Gray 1985). However,
Agranoff et al.
366
there is no magic formula for determining the extent to which public sector organizations and
NGOs exchange, share, or pool resources.
The fourth important dimension of network management is political. The politics of activities
between and among organizations and their managers permeate the managerial process. Public
managers not only engage in politics within their own organizations, but also must strike political
(in addition to operational) bargains with other partners. In many contexts, network manage-
ment consists of conict resolution using the important political skills of bargaining, negotiation,
diplomacy, and consensus building (Gray 1989; Ingram 1977).
Network operation
Building blocks
Network management behaviors are employed to help to frame the structure and the norms
and values of the network as a whole. Managers cannot draw up an organizational chart in a
network as is done in single organization structures, but they do try to inuence the roles that
each participant may play at any given time and the perceptions one has about the common
purpose of the network. Managers do this by facilitating agreement on leadership roles; helping
to establish an identity and culture for the network; assisting in developing a working structure
for the network (e.g. committees, network assignments); and altering the perceptions of parti-
cipants to understand the unique characteristics of working with persons in contexts without
organizational mechanisms based in authority relations.
Seeking support from external groups and stakeholders for collaborative operations has proven
to be a major component of collaboration eectiveness. Those within the collaboration must
foster the buy-in of key stakeholders, particularly those whose power will be relied upon to
signal support of the collaborative throughout their home agency. Managing the external net-
work environment thus is important for the collaborative public manager. Encouraging support
from and keeping a collaborative network in good standing with the higher governmental
authority ranked very high in an empirical study of network leadership (Silvia and McGuire 2010).
Similarly, encouraging support from and keeping the network in good standing with stakeholders
both inside and outside the government was viewed as being very signicant. Such behavior
helps to establish the legitimacy of the network (Milward and Provan 2006) and acts as a mobi-
lizer to develop commitment and support for network processes from network participants and
external stakeholders (McGuire 2002).
Managers must also employ behaviors intended to create an environment and enhance the
conditions for favorable, productive interaction among network participants. One critical behavior
of network management is to build relationships and interactions that result in achieving the
network purpose. The strategies of each network participant and the outcomes of those strategies
are inuenced by the patterns of relations and interactions that have developed in the network.
Such behaviors include facilitating and furthering interaction among participants, reducing com-
plexity and uncertainty by promoting information exchange, and facilitating linkages among
participants. Successful network management will thus achieve cooperation between actors
while minimizing and removing informational and interactional blockages to the cooperation.
Klijn and Edelenbos (2008) draw a distinction between process design and management and
institutional design for describing various network management strategies. Process design involves
agreements regarding the nature of the interaction process and the ground rules for participating
in the network. The authors assert that there is no standard, all-encompassing design type for
networks; it is situational. Process management includes the direct, hands-on application of the
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
367
behaviors and tasks discussed above. Institutional design, on the other hand, is indirect. Such
design strategies are typically focused on changing the formal and informal rules that inuence,
guide, and limit the behavior of the network participants (2008: 207). The strategies include
changing the network composition, inuencing network outcomes, and aecting network
interactions.
Learning and network management
Public managers in network settings face a number of both constraints and opportunities, most
of which exist due to the primacy of government in many such settings. Such actions are driven
by the knowledge that develops as implementers work through the process and learn what
works and what does not work. The public knowledge that is generated by the process is thus
informed by the outcomes of networks. Knowledge is that major step beyond information; it
provides the capacity to act (Sveiby 1997). It is the
uid mix of framed experience, values, contextual information, and expert insight that
provides a framework for evaluating and incorporating new experiences and information
In organizations, it often becomes embedded not only in documents or repositories but
also in organizational routines, practices, processes, and norms.
(Davenport and Prusak 2000: 5)
The importance of learning together in networks to create knowledge is captured by the work
of Koppenjan and Klijn (2004). Joint action by interaction is seen in part as
searches wherein public and private parties from dierent organization (levels of) govern-
ment and networks jointly learn about the nature of the problem, look at the possibility of
doing something about it, and look at the characteristics of the strategic and institutional
context within which the problem-solving develops.
(2004: 10)
Cooperation, then, presupposes structured learning between actors: It requires numerous
skills, tacit knowledge of the network and negotiation skills since the adopted strategies are
implemented in a situation where singular hierarchical relations are lacking (Koppenjan and
Klijn 2004: 11). Thus, learning in multi-actor situations is crucial.
Informal structures that develop around shared knowledge are namely communities of practice
and the epistemic communities that they often lead to. The former are self-organizing systems
that share the capacity to create and use knowledge through informal learning and mutual
engagement (Wenger 2000). Most communities are self-organized and bring in new knowledge
bearers when needed, from wherever they can be found. Maintenance of communities of
practice requires eorts to keep dierent types of knowledge bearers in, by challenging busy people
with solving important public problems, and by calling on their experience and know-how in an
interdisciplinary manner. Epistemic community can be facilitated by mobilizing a multi-agency
group of professionals from dierent disciplines because they often share common outlooks and
similar solution orientations. They also tend to share causal beliefs, notions of validity, and a
common policy experience. An epistemic community normally produces consensual knowledge.
Epistemic communities also can be important knowledge sustainers, as they can have a dispropor-
tionate eect on organized learning and behavior. Bringing together these communities for
enhanced deliberation is among the emergent networked tasks of public management.
Agranoff et al.
368
Governance networks add value
The ability to create or add value has long been a central concern of the public sector. As a result of
public managers attempting to discover, dene, and produce public value (Moore 1995: 20),
the utilization of collaborative networks for public sector service delivery and policy implementa-
tion has increased notably over the last two decades. It is now quite common for governments
at all levels to rely upon other governments, private sector actors, and non-prot organizations to
plan, implement, and manage government programs and services (Silvia 2011). However, as
Bardach (1998) concludes, the question is not whether networks exist, but rather, whether networks
increase the public value beyond which the agency would have in the absence of the network.
It has been argued that the frequency of the establishment of networks and the sustained
utilization of networked approaches in the public sector provides evidence that such organiza-
tional structures do add value (Cropper 1996; Howlett 2002; Thomson et al. 2008). Howlett
(2002) found that in four policy sectors networks matter in policy change as ideas and interest
are transmitted through policy subsystems. Nevertheless, collaboration is, after all, not easy. The
presences and gravity of collaborative challenges, including time costs, the logistical issues, varying
degrees of interorganizational and/or interpersonal trust, the integration of multiple organiza-
tional cultures, the sharing of control over resources, and the disparate goals and objectives held
by the dierent collaborative partners, have caused some to dissuade parties from collaborating
unless it is necessary (Huxham and Vangen, 2005). However, the inability of single organizations
to solve the wicked problems they face often requires a collaborative approach. Thus, despite
the challenges posed by collaboration, networked arrangements for addressing shared problems
has added important value to the public undertaking that undoubtedly would not have otherwise
occurred (Agrano 2007: 4).
To the network administrators, the rationale for investment in the network entails more
than serving the collective public purpose, vaguely understood but also includes certain
advantages the network can bring to their organizations mission and functioning and to
the managers as professionals involved in public programs.
(Agrano and Yildiz 2007: 337)
Thus, this added value can be seen from the perspective of the individual collaborative partner, from
the perspective of the participating organization, as a result of the network process, and as a
result of network outcomes (Agrano 2007, 2008; Agrano and Yildiz 2007).
From the perspective of the individual collaborative partner, value is created through a number
of dierent mechanisms. In his studies of 14 public management networks, Agrano (2007,
2008) described ve mechanisms through which individual collaborators benet from their
involvement in the network. The rst relates to the knowledge gained and the skills learned
through working with others. Second, networks are often interdisciplinary in nature. Thus, col-
laborators learn how to work with and learn from those from dierent organizations, back-
grounds, and functional areas. In addition, the opportunity to work with and/or manage individuals
from dierent organizations enhances the ability to manage and work within intergovernmental
arenas is a third advantage. The fourth area for potential benet for the individual is the increased
networking opportunities. Working with representatives of other organizations allows network
members to build relationships with and gain access to other entities and individuals. Finally,
individuals perceive that networks add value to them personally as networked governance struc-
tures strengthen their public service motivation and provide them with additional opportunities
for public service.
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
369
Policy design and implementation via a networked structure also provides a number of
advantages to the organizations participating in the joint venture. The value added is realized by
the participating organizations as they attempt to achieve collaborative advantage, or the synergy
created as organizations collaborate (Huxham 1996; Huxham and Vangen 2005). Collaboration
has been conceived of as a strategy for increasing the value that a single organization is able to
create on its own (Kim 2010: 112) in part because such arrangements expand the capabilities
and capacity of the individual organizations involved. By working together, organizations are
able to increase their capacity to serve their constituents by accessing their collaborative partners
knowledge, information, connections, personnel, material, and monetary resources. In addition,
the participating organizations also realize the value added via collaboration as risk is shared
among all of the partners, as eciencies are realized as networks are able to take advantage of
economies of scale and sectoral dierences, as the organizations are able to learn from each
other, and as the delivery of services is coordinated (Cropper 1996; Huxham and Vangen 2005).
There is also value added as a result of the collaborative process. While not realized by any one
person or organization, the benets of the collaborative process are realized by the network as a
whole and, more importantly, often felt by those for whom the network is intended to serve. If
the value that the network is trying to create is the public value, then perhaps the dierent
perspectives voiced while collaborating can help to determine what the public value is. This value
creation may in essence be the product of the interorganizational, intersectoral, and interideological
conversation aimed at problem identication and resolution between government agencies and
its interlocutors. As Innes and Booher remind us, a process that is inclusive, well informed, and
comes close to achieving consensus is more likely to produce an implementable proposal than one
lacking these qualities (1999: 420). In the absence of the network, a siloed approach to value
creation occurs, whereby individual organizations view the problem from their own, isolated per-
spective. Networked approaches to service provision and program implementation, on the other
hand, can result in a process whereby the agencies involved engage in dialogues that they otherwise
would not have, approach the issues from a less partisan perspective, create a synergy where
individual members exchange ideas, and build communal knowledge to work toward a solution.
The added value resulting in improved collaborative outcomes is, generally speaking, the
driver behind the formation of collaborative networks. Bardach (1998: 8) dened collaboration
as any joint activity by multiple entities that is intended to increase public value by their
working together rather than separately. Here, this public value refers to the outcomes pro-
duced by the collaborative eorts. Networks, in the course of addressing the problems for
which they were formed to solve, generate collaboratively produced products, such as reports,
publications, conferences, training programs, datasets, and so on, that can be used not only by
the networks and its constituent members, but also by others outside the network and even
outside the area served by the network. Collaboration within a networked governance structure
also commonly results in changes to old programs and the formation of new ones. These jointly
constructed and implemented service delivery programs are often more holistic and compre-
hensive in their approach. In the process of working with each other on the issue that brought
them together, networks also often engage in spin-o projects as discussion between network
members bring previously unaddressed or unrealized issues to the forefront.
Conclusion
Networks are notable information age responses to the most dicult of policy and adminis-
trative problems but they are by no means replacing the authority of government as they share
involvement with NGOs. First, while networks and the NGOs work with public agencies,
Agranoff et al.
370
inuence policy and have a role in management, those organizations and agencies that comprise
these networks work with governments as the latter continue to maintain some important abil-
ities that guide public action. The agencies retain their authority under law. Second, while an
interactive interdependency has emerged within networks crossing many boundaries, public agency-
NGO organization connections seem to overlay the hierarchy rather than act as replacements
for government action. Networks are not the exclusive mode of collaborative government-
nongovernmental relations. Many of the more standard tools of governmentfor example, grants,
loans, regulatory programs, insurance guarantees, and cooperative agreementstie governments
together and public agencies to NGOs without employing networks. Finally, not all govern-
mental agency administrators are totally or to a high degree in the business of working in net-
works. With the exception of certain boundary spanners who spend full-time in cross-agency
work, many administrators spend a small proportion of their total work time in collaborative
activity, including participating in networks.
Networks have not eclipsed or displaced the power or centrality of government agencies. The
empirical evidence is too mixed to support such a contention. Thus, despite the very broad range
of network activity, in the United States it was found that the ability [of nongovernmental
actors] to inuence the public agency domain is real but quite limited in scope accommodations
are made, decisions are inuenced, strategies are altered, resources are directed, intensive groups
exert undue inuence, and public responsibility is indirectly shared (Agrano 2007: 219). The
reality is that neither networks (or the for-prot and nonprot partners within them) nor gov-
ernment agencies dominate, and in many cases the government agencies prove to be the key
leaders within the networks.
Bibliography
Agrano, Robert. 1986. Intergovernmental Management: Human Services Problem-Solving in Six Metropolitan
Areas. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
—— 2003. Leveraging Networks: A Guide for Public Managers Working across Organizations. Arlington, VA:
IBM Endowment for The Business of Government.
—— 2007. Managing Within Networks: Adding Value to Public Organizations. Washington, DC: Georgetown
University Press.
—— 2008. Enhancing performance through public sector networks: Mobilizing human capital in
communities of practice, Public Performance & Management Review 31(3): 32047.
—— 2010. Towards an emergent theory of governance within IGR, in Edoardo Ongaro, Andrew
Massey, Marc Holzer, and Ellen Wayenberg (eds) Governance and Intergovernmental Relations in the European
Union and the United States. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
——and Michael McGuire. 2003. Collaborative Public Management: New Strategies for Local Governments.
Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
——and Mete Yildiz. 2007. Decision making in public management networks, in Goktug Morcol (ed.)
Handbook of Decision Making. New York: CRC, Taylor & Francis, 31945.
Alter, Catherine and Jerald Hage. 1993. Organizations Working Together. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Ashford, Douglas E. 1988. Decentralizing welfare states: Social policies and intergovernmental policies,
in Bruno Dente and Francesco Kjellberg (eds) The Dynamics of Institutional Change: Local Government
Reorganization in Western Democracies. London: Sage.
Bardach, Eugene. 1998. Getting Agencies to Work Together. Washington, DC: Brookings.
Bogason, Peter and Theo A.J. Toonen. 1998. Networks in public administration, Public Administration
76(Summer): 20527.
Brown, Trevor L. and Matthew Potoski. 2004. Managing the public service market, Public Administration
Review 64(6): 65668.
Castells, Manuel. 1996. The Rise of the Network Society. Oxford: Blackwell.
Cropper, S. 1996. Collaborative working and the issue of sustainability, in C. Huxham (ed.) Creating
Collaborative Advantage. London: Sage.
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
371
Davenport, Thomas H. and Laurance Prusak. 2000. Working Knowledge: How Organizations Manage what
they Know. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School Press.
Eisinger, Peter K. 1988. The Rise of the Entrepreneurial State. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
Elazar, Daniel J. 1962. The American Partnership: Intergovernmental Cooperation in the Nineteenth Century
United States. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Elmore, Richard F. 1985. Forward and backward mapping: Reversible logic in the analysis of public
policy, in Kenneth Hanf and Theo A.J. Toonen (eds) Policy Implementation in Federal and Unitary Systems.
Dordrecht: Martinus Nijho Publishers.
Gray, Barbara. 1985. Conditions facilitating interorganizational collaboration, Human Relations 38: 91136.
—— 1989. Collaborating: Finding Common Ground for Multiparty Problems. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Hall, Thad E. and Laurence J. OToole. 2000. Structures for policy implementation: An analysis of
national legislation, 196566 and 199394, Administration and Society 31(6): 66786.
—— 2004. Shaping formal networks through the regulatory process, Administration and Society 36(2):
186207.
Hanf, Kenneth, Benny Hjern and David O. Porter. 1978. Local networks of manpower training in the
Federal Republic of Germany and Sweden, in Kenneth Hanf and Fritz W. Scharpf (eds) Interorganizational
Policy Making: Limits to Coordination and Central Control. London: Sage.
Hjern, Benny and David O. Porter. 1981. Implementation structures: A new unit for administrative
analysis, Organizational Studies 3: 21137.
Hood, Christopher. 1991. A public management for all seasons?, Public Administration 69(1): 319.
Howlett, Michael. 2002. Do networks matter? Linking policy network structure to policy outcomes:
evidence from four Canadian policy sectors 19902000, Canadian Journal of Political Science 35(2): 23567.
Hull,
Christopher J. with
Benny Hjern. 1987. Helping Small Firms Grow: An Implementation Approach.
London: Croom Helm.
Huxham, Chris. 1996. Collaboration and collaborative advantage, in C. Huxham (ed.) Creating Collaborative
Advantage. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 118.
——and Siv Vangen. 2005. Managing to Collaborate: The Theory and Practice of Collaborative Advantage. New
York: Routledge.
Ingram, Helen. 1977. Policy implementation through bargaining: The case of federal grants-in-aid , Public
Policy 25(4): 499526.
Innes, Judith E. and David E. Booher. 1999. Consensus building and complex adaptive systems: A framework
for evaluating collaborative planning, Journal of the American Planning Association 65(4), 41223.
Kildu, Martin and Wenpin Tsai. 2003. Social Networks and Organizations. Los Angeles, CA: Sage.
Kim, S. 2010. Collaborative leadership and local governance,inR.OLeary, D.M. Van Slyke and S. Kim
(eds) The Future of Public Administration Around the World: The Minnowbrook Prespective . Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press, 11115.
Klijn, Erik-Hans and Jurian Edelenbos. 2008. Meta-governance as network management, in Eva Sor-
ensen and Jacob Torng (eds) Theories of Democratic Network Governance. London: Palgrave Macmillan,
199214.
Kooiman, Jan. 2003. Governing as Governance. London: Sage.
Koppenjan, Joop F.M. and Erik-Hans Klijn. 2004. Managing Uncertainties in Networks. London: Routledge.
Krane, Dale and Deil S. Wright. 1998. Intergovernmental relations,inInternational Encyclopedia of Public
Policy and Administration. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1168 70.
Loughlin, John. 2007. Reconguring the state: Trends in territorial governance in European States,
Regional and Federal Studies 17(4): 385404.
Lynn, Lawrence E. 1981. Managing the Publics Business: The Job of the Government Executive .
New York:
Basic Books.
McGuire,
Michael. 2002. Managing networks: Propositions on what managers do and why they do it,
Public Administration Review 62(5): 42633.
——and Robert Agrano. 2010. Networking in the shadow of bureaucracy, in Robert F. Durant (ed.)
The Oxford Handbook of American Bureaucracy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mandell, Myrna P. 1984. Application of network analysis to the implementation of a complex project,
Human Relations 37(8): 65979.
Marsh, David and Martin Smith. 2000. Understanding policy networks: Towards a dialectical approach,
Political Studies 48(1): 421.
Milward, H. Brinton and Keith G. Provan. 2006. A Managers Guide to Choosing and Using Collaborative
Networks. Arlington, VA: IBM Center for the Business of Government.
Agranoff et al.
372
Moore, Mark H. 1995. Creating Public Value: Strategic Management in Government. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
OToole, Laurence J. 1985. Diusion of responsibility: An interorganizational analysis, in Kenneth Hanf
and Theo. A.J. Toonen (eds) Policy Implementation in Federal and Unitary Systems . Dordrecht: Martinus
Nijho, 20125.
—— 1997. Treating networks seriously: Practical and research-based agenda in public administration,
Public Administration Review 57(1): 4552.
Peters, B. Guy. 2000. Policy instruments and public management: Bridging the gaps, Journal of Public
Administration Research and Theory: J-PART 10(1): 35 47.
—— 2002. Globalization, institutions, governance, in B. Guy Peters and Donald J. Savoie (eds) Governance
in the Twenty-First Century: Revitalizing the Public Service. Montreal: McGill-Queens University Press.
Pressman, Jerey L. 1975. Federal Programs and City Politics: The Dynamics of the Aid Process in Oakland.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
——L. and Aaron Wildavsky. 1973. Implementation. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Radin, Beryl A., Robert Agrano, C. Gregory Buntz, Ann OM. Bowman, Barbara Romzek and Robert
Wilson. 1996. New Governance for Rural America: Creating Intergovernmental Partnerships. Lawrence, KS:
University of Kansas Press.
Rhodes, R.A.W. 1997. Understanding Governance: Policy Networks, Governance, Reexivity and Accountability.
Buckingham: Open University Press.
—— 2003. Putting people back into networks, in Arie Salminen (ed.) Governing Networks. Amsterdam:
IOS Press.
——and David Marsh. 1992. New directions in the study of policy networks, European Journal of Political
Research 21(2): 181205.
Saint-Onge, Hubert and Charles Armstrong. 2004. The Conductive Organization. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Salamon, Lester M. 1995. Partners in Public Service.
Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
—— 2002. The new governance and the tools of public action, in Lester M. Salamon (ed.) The Tools of
Government. New York: Oxford.
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1978. Interorganizational policy studies: Issues, concepts, and perspectives, in Kenneth
Hanf and Fritz W. Scharpf (eds) Interorganizational Policy Making. London: Sage.
Silvia, Chris 2011. Collaborative governance concepts for successful network leadership, State and Local
Government Review 43(1), 6671.
——and Michael McGuire. 2010. Leading public sector networks: An empirical examination of integrative
leadership behaviors, The Leadership Quarterly 21(2): 26477.
Skelcher, Chris. 2004. The new governance of communities, in Gerry Stoker and David Wilson (eds)
British Local Government into the 21st Century. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Skowronek, Stephen. 1982. Building a New American State: The Expansion of National Administrative Capacities,
18771920. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, Steven R. and Michael Lipsky. 1993. Nonprots for Hire: The Welfare State in the Age of Contracting.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sorenson, Eva and Jacob Torng. 2007. Theoretical approaches to democratic network governance, in Eva
Sorenson and Jacob Torng (eds) Theories of Democratic Network Governance. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Sundquist, James L. 1969. Making Federalism Work . Washington, DC: Brookings.
Sveiby, K.-E. 1997. The New Organisational Wealth: Managing and Measuring Knowledge-Based Assets. San
Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.
Thompson, Grahame F. 2003. Between Markets and Hierarchies: The Logic and Limits of Network Forms of
Organization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thomson, A.M., James L. Perry, and T.K. Miller 2008. Linking collaboration processes and outcomes,in
L.B. Bingham and R. OLeary (eds) Big Ideas in Collaborative Public Management. Amonk, NY: M.E.
Sharpe, 97120.
Van Slyke, David. 2007. Agents or stewards: Government nonprot social service contracting relationships,
Journal
of Public Administration
Research and Theory 17(2): 15787.
Watts, Ronald L. 1999. Comparing Federal Systems in the 1990s, 2nd edn. Kingston: Institute of Inter-
governmental Relations, Queens University.
Wenger, E. 2000. Communities of practice: The key to knowledge strategy, in E.L. Lesser, M. A. Fontaine
and J.A. Slusher (eds) Knowledge and Communities. Boston: Butterworth-Heinemann.
Williams, Walter W. 1980. Government by Agency: Administering Grants-in-Aid Programs. New York: Academic
Press.
Governance, networks and intergovernmental systems
373
28
Development management and
policy implementation
Relevance beyond the global South
Derick W. Brinkerhoff and Jennifer M. Brinkerhoff
As a subset of the discipline of public administration, development management (also referred to
as development administration) has traditionally concentrated on the organizational and managerial
problems confronting the countries of the global South. Development management has been
long associated with international foreign assistance, and debates regarding what it is, how to do
it, and what it achieves are frequently embedded within larger arguments about foreign policy,
development assistance, and power imbalances between the global North and South. Reecting
this association, development management is often distinguished as concerning the implementation
of donor-funded policies, programs, and projects intended to promote socio-economic devel-
opment in low-income countries. Development management has been swept by the same tides
that have shaped foreign assistance over the decades since the post-World War II era, and that have
revisited notions of development and what is needed to make it happen (Brinkerho 2008).
Some analysts distinguish between management of developmentreferring to the manage-
ment of the mechanics of foreign aid procedures, programs, and projectsand management
for development, which addresses the underlying substance of development as a transforma-
tional process that improves the well-being of citizens in poor countries (see Thomas 1999). Yet
this distinction can be dicult to maintain. Donor countries pursue a wide variety of foreign
policy objectives under the broad rubric of foreign assistance. The publicly espoused aim of most
donor foreign assistance is to contribute to development in recipient countries. Thus, ocial
development policy statements reect an assumption that management of the development
projects and programs that are designed to implement those policies is tantamount to, or at least
aspires to be, management for development. As numerous critical studies of foreign assistance
reveal, however, donor countries use foreign aid in the service of political, diplomatic, economic,
humanitarian, and security aims that may sideline or subvert development. Further, the mod-
alities of delivering foreign assistance are accused of contributing to these perverse impacts (see
Easterly 2006; Picard and Buss 2009). Radical critiques of development management tar the
discipline with the same antidevelopment brush (see Dar and Cooke 2008).
This chapter opens by briey reviewing the range of perspectives on development management.
The discussion is framed around our model of development management, which denes the
374
discipline in terms of institutional agendas, tools, values, and processes (Brinkerho and Brinkerho
2006). We explicitly recognize the complexities, trade-os, and tensions inherent in the foreign
assistance policy environment where many development managers operate. We then turn to policy
implementation and examine what the development management discipline has to say about
how managers can transform policy reform intent into outcomes.
Perspectives on development management
Dening development management remains problematic for several reasons. We have already
noted the diculty of separating it from its foreign assistance policy environment. Second is the
question of what development is. Third is what, then, is being managed. Fourth is the issue of
what we mean by management. The answers to these questions have occupied theorists and
practitioners for decades, so we can only touch on them in the most cursory manner here.
Regarding the development question, the predominant view is informed by modernization
theory, which (to oversimplify) posits that development is a process that moves countries and
their citizens progressively along a path to Western-style liberal economies and democratic
governance. Modernization involves societal transformations from rural to urban, ascriptive/
personalistic roles to merit/position-based ones, impoverished to wealthier, low levels of health
and education to higher ones, and so on. Besides these material advances (having more),
development is widely seen as being more ; that is, enhancing capacities, fullling potentials,
expanding freedoms, and exercising rights (e.g. Sen 1999). In a much-cited shorthand, the end-
state toward which this modernizing development path leads is Denmark, that is, a stable,
prosperous, and well-managed liberal democracy (Pritchett and Woolcock 2004).
As the dichotomy between developed and developing countries has become less distinct, and
as a middle range of countries such as China, India, and Brazil has emerged, the modernization
paradigm has been increasingly recognized as an artifact of outdated thinking. There are mul-
tiple paths to development, and issues of politicscontestation for power and patronage among
elitesand of identityhow people dene themselves relative to language, religion, family,
and culturegure strongly in determining what those paths are and where they lead. The innate
superiority of Western-style modernization has been increasingly questioned, particularly in light
of the global economic crisis, climate change, and the perceived failure of the United States and
its allies to achieve quick success in rebuilding Iraq and Afghanistan.
As for the third question, whether these twin transformations of having and being more
can be managed depends upon the conception of change that underlies them. Donor approaches
to development, implicitly and explicitly, reect the idea that societal change is both amenable
to planning and intentional direction, and can be usefully guided and supported by external actors.
The alternative view is that change is historically and institutionally embedded in a given societys
individual trajectory, and is in essence emergent and not easily subject to manipulation. Man-
agement is only possible, at best, at the margins, and is not accessible to outsiders except in the most
supercial ways. The experience of the international community in fragile and post-conict
states, such as Liberia, Afghanistan, and Iraq, has provided traction for this standpoint.
Regarding what is management in the international development context, in line with the
modernization paradigm, early answers focused on the technical tasks associated with Weberian
bureaucracies; for example, the classic public administration tasks encapsulated in the acronym,
POSDCORB (planning, organizing, stang, directing, coordinating, reporting, and budgeting),
coined in 1937 by Luther Gulick and Lyndall Urwick, and on designing and operating the
organizational systems to enable managers to carry them out (see the overview in Esman 1991).
Later conceptions of management were, and remain, heavily inuenced by the New Public
Development management and policy implementation
375
Management (NPM), again drawing on models from industrialized countries and transferring
them to developing societies (see Brinkerho 2008). In the donor-funded international develop-
ment arena, the tools and techniques of data gathering, project/program design (e.g. the Logical
Framework), and monitoring and evaluation are well recognized dening features of management.
With the replacement of modernizations single path to development by what Woolcock
(2009) terms multiple modernities and the focus on development as an indigenous, emergent
phenomenon, management has expanded beyond administrative technologies and routines, to
address reform, change processes, participation, learning, and local adaptation. Fowler (1997),
writing about nongovernmental organizations engaged in international development, talks about
management as striking a balance between the demands of donor-driven technocratic pro-
cedures and requirements, and the rights and needs of the poor and marginalized. In another
example of an expanded conception of management, Andrews et al. (2010) consider leadership
for change management as paramount, and see the leaders role as creating space where change
can happen.
A multidimensional denition of development management
As the above brief review demonstrates, a single, agreed-upon denition of development man-
agement would be dicult to come up with, and in fact, this is the case. Previously, we have
sought to clarify the meaning of development management by characterizing it as encompassing
four dimensions: a means to institutional agendas; a set of values; a planning and management
toolkit; and processes that both support the agency of development actors and reconcile competing
interests (Brinkerho and Brinkerho 2006).
A means to institutional agendas
While donor agendas may predominate, due to their associated funding, they exist alongside
those of national and local public ocials, citizen groups, and private sector actors. Each of these
interest groups may apply development management tools and processes to enact their particular
values and further their particular agendas. Thus development management is not restricted solely
to donor-designed and -funded initiatives. This is a particularly important observation when
considering how development management relates to policy implementation.
A set of values
With the expanded notions of what constitutes development and the inclusion of identity in its
denition, the values dimension of development management becomes especially salient. Values
associated with development management include empowerment, participation, a focus on the
poor and disadvantaged, self-determination (commonly operationalized as country ownership),
and, more recently, sustainability. Responsiveness to the needs and desires of recipient country
governments and their citizens also requires respect for and incorporation of national values,
culture, and identity. These increasingly overlap with aspirations encompassed in liberal values
such as human rights and basic freedoms (e.g. speech, assembly, religion).
Planning and management toolkit
Development management as a toolkit incorporates all of the basic tools supportive of public policy
and public administration, as well as those more specically designed to support development
Brinkerhoff and Brinkerhoff
376
processes. These include analytic tools drawn from political science and human behavior, as well
as management tools deriving from strategic management, budgeting, and evaluation. Tools, in
and of themselves, are value-neutral instruments. Through their application in the service of
particular institutional agendas and values, however, they lose their neutrality.
Processes
The results of the application of management tools depend largely on the processes through
which they are applied. That is, tools may be selected and modied to support particular agendas
and values, but it is in their application that values, in particular, will be made manifest. Thus,
the process dimension of development management self-consciously considers the politics of
competing values and agendas and power dierentials. The process dimension is specically struc-
tured to bring into consideration the desires, needs, and values of those aected by development
plans, programs, and investments.
Development management debates
Because of the complexities in dening development, management, and development man-
agement, there are competing perspectives on the discipline. Our multidimensional framework
recognizes these complexities, and seeks to capture the tensions and disconnects among them.
The key disconnect is between development management as a means to implement institutional
agendas and the other three dimensions. Our view is that through a commitment to pro-poor
and empowerment values, and the application of participatory processes and interest mediation,
this disconnect does not necessarily undermine the possibilities for achieving positive policy out-
comes. Development management can serve the aims and intents of reformers and activists. Donor
practices and procedures are not always the straitjacket that critics perceive them to be
(Brinkerho and Ingle 1989).
This view places us in the reformist camp, which recognizes the political realities of foreign
assistance, globalization, and national politics, and the limitations of externally supported socio-
economic change. The reformist outlook critiques development management in practice, while
still believing in its actual and potential contributions to desired development outcomes. The
radicalist/rejectionist camp, on the other hand, holds that development management is so inti-
mately connected with neocolonialist power relations and managerialist control that actions
taken by development managers are invariably detrimental to the interests of developing
countries, and particularly of the poor residing in those countries (see Gulrajani 2010; Mowles
2010). Table 28.1 illustrates these two competing perspectives on development management
using our four development management dimensions.
For each of the dimensions of development management, the radicalist/rejectionist perspec-
tive focuses on their oppressive nature, and their contributions to reinforcing political and
bureaucratic power imbalances and inequalities. The history of foreign assistance conrms that
bad things have indeed been done in the name of international development, and that tech-
nocratic managerial hubris has been a contributing factor. We argue, however, that the con-
clusion to be drawn is not to throw the management baby out with the development
bathwater, but precisely to apply development management in the service of those actors
who seek to confront the ills identied by the radicalist/rejectionist nger pointers.
We are not alone in making this argument. The results of a survey of development man-
agement scholars and practitioners reinforces the activist orientation in favor of empowering
local actors to pursue country-led development strategies and objectives, and of seeking to
Development management and policy implementation
377
inuence donor agency practices and procedures to correct power imbalances (Brinkerho and
Brinkerho 2010). Gulrajani (2010) elaborates the contours of non-managerialist develop-
ment management, and both Mowles (2010) and Abbott et al. (2007) stress the role of joint
learning, values, negotiation, and adaptation in dealing with the power imbalances inherent in
development and its emergent, unpredictable nature.
We see some encouraging signs of changes. For example, current foreign assistance policies
(e.g. the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Developments Paris Principles that stress
country ownership and alignment with indigenous systems) and practices (e.g. cash-on-delivery
aid, and budget transfers) are reshaping the management environment for development, placing
more emphasis on the role of country actors as development managers. While the Paris Principles
have been criticized in some quarters as largely rhetoric, nonetheless there have been some
operational changes on the ground in response to them. For example, in Liberias health sector,
the health minister has gotten buy-in from a range of international donors for his sector plan,
and the donors have committed to a pooled funding arrangement where the minister retains
control over the funds in the implementation of the programs that they support.
Development management and policy implementation
The evolutionary trajectory of scholarship and practice related to the policy process and policy
implementation in the global South closely tracks that of development management. The resulting
conuence provides the rationale for development managements relevance in implementing
policy. Three parallels are pertinent to the discussion here. First is the source of policy concepts,
models, analytic tools, and practical advice. The policy literature has originated largely in indus-
trialized countries, principally the US and the UK, which raises the same transferability issue
that development management has debated. The evolution in both literatures has been a gra-
dual recognition of the fallacies of institutional isomorphism and of the need for contextual
understanding and adaptation to individual circumstances.
Second, very similar to thinking about development planning, where the transformation of
plans into actions and results was given short shrift, the classic policy literatures stages heuristic
treated implementation as (a) a separate step in the policy process, and (b) a black box that
Table 28.1 Competing perspectives on development management
Development Management
Dimensions
Reformist perspective Radicalist/rejectionist perspective
Institutional agenda Equitable growth, MDGs, good
governance, rights-based
approaches, enhanced
capacities
Neo-colonialist replication of
Northern dominance over the global
South
Values Bottom-up empowerment,
pro-poor, pluralism, country
ownership
Top-down imposition of Western
paradigms and universal
performance metrics
Tools Responsive planning and
management for efciency and
effectiveness
Technocratic, managerialist
instruments of control
Process Participation, agency, social
accountability
Co-optation, lip-service to disguise
power imbalances
Source: Authors
Brinkerhoff and Brinkerhoff
378
faithfully translates policy objectives into outcomes. Pressman and Wildavskys classic book (1973)
started to unpack the black box, and helped to launch the US policy implementation literature.
Within a few years, international donors discovered and debated the implementation and
sustainability gaps in development projects and programs.
The third parallel is the eventual acknowledgment that, while the technical content of policies is
important to achieving desired policy outcomes, their implementation is strongly inuenced by
bureaucratic and political factors. Having the right policy is not sucient, and in fact what may be
technically optimal (right) is in many cases likely to be bureaucratically and/or politically
infeasible (e.g. Mazmanian and Sabatier 1989). This realization gave rise to the literature on
policy advocacy, coalitions, and networks. In the international development arena, the mismatch
between technical and politico-bureaucratic factors became increasingly clear during the period
beginning in the 1980s when the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund were pursuing
structural adjustment policies and encountering problems. Development management scholars
and practitioners focused on these factors as well (Grindle and Thomas 1991; Brinkerho and
Crosby 2002; Brinkerho 2008).
Framing international development policy implementation
The focus on the policy implementation gap revealed some important features that distinguish
implementing policies from project and program management. The following discussion draws
upon Brinkerho and Crosby (2002), whose book encapsulates the ndings of an extensive
applied research eort on policy implementation in developing countries.
Policy implementation is not a linear, coherent process. With policy implementation, change is often
multidirectional, fragmented, frequently interrupted, and unpredictable. How to sequence
actions, what to pay attention to, and who to include can be hard to determine, and can vary
over the life of the policy change process.
Most policies require the concerted actions of multiple agencies and groups. Even if one of them is
nominally the lead agency, in reality no individual entity is in charge of policy implementation.
Authority and responsibility are dispersed among the actors involved.
Policy implementation is often highly political. Policies usually involve the imposition of costs on
some societal groups as well oering advantages to others, which creates winners and losers, and
makes reforms highly contentious. Current policy equilibriums favor the powerful that benet
from them; these actors are usually well positioned to defend the status quo and resist change.
The resources required to implement policies may not be readily available. Projects and programs
have dedicated budgets, but policiesparticularly at the start of a reformoften lack the
resources needed for implementation. Making progress means lobbying for new funding,
identifying existing sources of implementation support, and negotiating for resource reallocation.
In response to these identied characteristics of policy implementation and building on the
policy implementation literature, plus action research and technical assistance in approximately
30 countries, Brinkerho and Crosby (2002) developed a framework that parses implementation
into six roughly sequential tasks. These are posited as an iterative succession through which
managers need to cycle repeatedly during the life of a given reform:
1 Creating legitimacy, getting the policy accepted as important, desirable, and worth achiev-
ing, is the rst implementation task. Legitimization means getting buy-in from the right
people in the country to push the reform process forward. An important outcome of this
Development management and policy implementation
379
task is the emergence of a policy champion (an individual or group who believes in the
policy) to take on leadership for the subsequent implementation tasks.
2 Building constituencies, or gaining active support for a proposed policy from groups that see
the reform as desirable or benecial, is the second implementation task. This support needs to
translate into commitment to take actions that will help to achieve the policys objectives. As
well as establishing coalitions of supporters, constituency building seeks to reduce or deect
the opposition of groups that see the proposed reform as harmful or threatening. This task must
often be pursued throughout implementation to assure ongoing support and to resist derailment.
3 Accumulating resources means ensuring that present and future budgets and human resource
allocations are sucient to support implementation requirements. Accomplishing this task
can involve, for example: lobbying constituencies to contribute resources, negotiating with
ministries for budget line-item funding, designing new resource allocation systems, and/or
setting up public-private partnerships.
4 Modifying organizational structures is the fourth policy implementation task. This entails
adjusting the objectives, procedures, systems, and structures of the agencies responsible for
policy implementation. Sometimes this task can also include establishing new organizations
to coordinate the various entities with a role in implementation.
5 Mobilizing resources and actions builds upon the favorable constituencies assembled for the
policy (Task 2) and marshals their commitment and resources (Task 3) to engage in concrete
eorts to make change happen. Its focus is on identifying, activating, and pursuing action
strategies. It brings together mobilized constituencies and resources, and within the orga-
nizational structures created, develops and carries out the steps necessary to translate intent
into results.
6 Monitoring impact, or setting up systems to monitor implementation progress, is the nal
policy implementation task. Monitoring systems not only alert decision-makers to imple-
mentation snags, but also inform them of the intended and unintended impacts of
implementation eorts.
Managing policy implementation
Brinkerho and Crosby argue that each of these tasks calls for explicit managerial attention, and
that failure to do so is a major contributor to the slippage between policy intents and imple-
mented outcomes. Development managements dimensions are visible in each of the implementa-
tion tasks, though one particular dimension may be more signicant to some tasks than others.
Institutional agendas and values, for example, come to the fore in the legitimization task. If
disagreements around these are not suciently resolved, they complicate or may even preclude
the constituency building and resource accumulation necessary to policy implementation.
Managing each of the tasks necessarily confronts competing institutional agendas and values
whose eective resolution most often occurs through process interventions aimed at reaching
agreement and specifying shared objectives. Where top-down decision-making is prevalent, two
outcomes are likely: rst, agreements and objectives may lack the broad buy-in necessary for
eective implementation follow-through, and/or second, agreements and objectives may need
to be revisited later in the implementation task sequence, resulting at best in delays or, at worst,
an impasse. An important consideration for development managers is expanding access to decision-
making, reected in sensitivity to which stakeholders gain a seat at the table and whose
priorities and purposes are ultimately served. Todays development policy emphasis on the
Millennium Development Goals and poverty alleviation highlights equity, representativeness,
and responsiveness.
Brinkerhoff and Brinkerhoff
380
Development managers use a variety of diagnostic and analytic tools to pursue the policy
implementation cycle. They assess constituency preferences, identify organizational and political
constraints, ag points of agreement/disagreement, develop work plans, and so on (e.g. using
stakeholder mapping, strengths-weaknesses-opportunities-threats (SWOT) analysis, responsibility
charts, etc.). In keeping with the values of empowerment and ownership, development man-
agers apply the tools through participatory processes (see, for example, Blackburn and Holland
1998). Participation, as both a value and a management process, is a core feature of development
management.
Participation in policy implementation, however, becomes problematic in the particular context
of developing countries, with their varying degrees of dependence upon international donors
for resources, policy advice, and technical assistance, where external actors play a major role by
virtue of their ability to drive policy agendas and the resources they command. This feature
brings us back to the radicalist/rejectionist critique discussed above, which holds that managing
policy implementation under these conditions replicates existing international power relations,
reinforces the dominance of the industrialized West, and is antithetical to the interests of recipient
countries and their poorest populations. Our reformist perspective characterizes the elements of
this critique as risks rather than certainties, and argues that the risks can be mitigated through
attention to our development management dimensions during policy implementation to increase
the chances that:
policies incorporate institutional agendas that balance donor and country interests, including
those of poor and marginalized citizens;
the values policies enact reect national values and identities;
management tools serve to support responsiveness to country-driven policy priorities as well
as donor accountability;
processes of engagement facilitate putting local actors in the drivers seat and building their
capacities.
The predominant inuence of donor-driven development policy design and implementation
makes such risk-mitigating eorts challenging to say the least. As Mowles (2010: 156) observes,
Strategic planning, log frames, and ideas of transformational management are so ubiquitous
that it would be impossible to proceed without engaging with them. The trick for develop-
ment managers is to employ the tools and the language of the dominant discourse to recalibrate
the power distributions among the actors involved. These distributions are not simply between
donors and country/local actors, but among local interest groups as well. Which local actors, for
example, should gain access to the drivers seat? Experience shows that in many countries the
more powerful and better-o groups tend to occupy the available societal space in ways that
preclude change (see Andrews et al. 2010). Policies intended to be pro-poor are likely to be
watered down so as to include some benets for the better-o, and/or to have those benets
diverted away from the poor during implementation (see Gillespie et al. 1996). The dilemma is
not just a matter of striking a balance between the power and interests of donors and local
actors, but in reconciling the multiple modernities and associated interests of a broad range of
local actors.
Conclusion
Our starting point for this chapter was a characterization of development management as geo-
graphically bounded through its association with the poor countries of the global South, and
Development management and policy implementation
381
operationally circumscribed through its connection to foreign assistance and international donor
practices. Yet, poverty, social exclusion, pandemic diseases, food insecurity, political instability,
and debt crises are recognized as aecting all countries to varying degrees. Policies and programs
to address these issues no longer distinguish the developed from the developing world, leading to
what some consider a convergence between the global North and South (see Mosley and
Dowler 2003). The implication for development management is that its relevance is no longer
geographically restricted; and its tools, processes, and values, and its explicit attention to whose
agendas policy implementation serves render it broadly applicable beyond the international
donor-funded realm.
In this sense, we see development management as having come full circle. From its birth as a
subdiscipline of US/UK-based public administration, and drawing from that body of scholarship
and practice to application in developing countries, it now oers experience, tools, and lessons
that can inform poverty-focused change management and policy implementation in countries in
the global North. As industrialized countries have increasingly turned to the non-prot and
private sectors for social services through contracting out, the dynamics of the design and nancing
of those services more closely resemble the donor-funded international development arena of
projects and programs than meets the eye.
Bibliography
Abbott, D., S. Brown, and G. Wilson. 2007. Development management as reective practice, Journal of
International Development 19(2): 187203.
Andrews, M., J. McConnell and A. Wescott. 2010. Development as Leadership-led Change: A Report for the
Global Leadership Initiative. Washington, DC: World Bank.
Blackburn, J. and J. Holland (eds) 1998. Who Changes? Institutionalizing Participation in Development.
London: Intermediate Technology Publications.
Brinkerho, D.W. 2008. The state and international development management: Shifting tides, changing
boundaries, and future directions, Public Administration Review 68(6): 9851002.
—— and M. Ingle. 1989. Integrating blueprint and process: A structured exibility approach to development
management, Public Administration and Development 9(4): 487 503.
—— and B.L. Crosby. 2002. Managing Policy Reform: Concepts and Tools for Decision-Makers in Developing
and Transitioning Countries. Bloomeld, CT: Kumarian Press.
—— and J.M. Brinkerho. 2006. International development management in a globalized world,inE.Otenyo
and N. Lind (eds) Comparative Public Administration: The Essential Readings. Amsterdam and Oxford:
Elsevier Press, 83163.
Brinkerho, J.M. and D.W. Brinkerho. 2010. International development management: A northern
perspective, Public Administration and Development 30(2): 102 15.
Dar, S. and B. Cooke (eds) 2008. The New Development Management: Critiquing the Dual Modernization.
London: Zed Books.
Easterly, W. 2006. The White Mans Burden: Why the WestsEorts to Aid the Rest Have Done So Much Ill
and So Little Good. New York: Penguin Press.
Esman, M. 1991. Management Dimensions of Development: Perspectives and Strategies. West Hartford, CT:
Kumarian Press.
Fowler, A. 1997. Striking a Balance: A Guide to Enhancing the Eectiveness of Non-Governmental Organizations
in
International Development. London:
Earthscan Publications.
Gillespie, P., M. Girgis, and P. Mayer. 1996. ‘“This great evil: Anticipating political obstacles to development,
Public Administration and Development 16(5): 43153.
Grindle, M.S. and J.W. Thomas. 1991. Public Choices and Policy Change: The Political Economy of Reform in
Developing Countries. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Gulrajani, N. 2010. New vistas for development management: Examining radical-reformist possibilities
and potential, Public Administration and Development 30(2): 12436.
Mazmanian, D.A. and P.A. Sabatier. 1989. Implementation and Public Policy. Lanham, MD: University Press
of America.
Brinkerhoff and Brinkerhoff
382
Mosley, P. and E. Dowler (eds) 2003. Poverty and Social Exclusion in North and South: Essays on Social Policy
and Global Poverty Reduction. London: Routledge.
Mowles, C. 2010. Post-foundational development management: Power, politics and complexity, Public
Administration and Development 30(2): 13649.
Picard, L.A. and T.F. Buss. 2009. A Fragile Balance: Re-examining the History of Foreign Aid, Security, and
Diplomacy. Sterling, VA: Kumarian Press.
Pressman. J.L. and A.B. Wildavsky. 1973. Implementation. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Pritchett, L. and M. Woolcock. 2004. Solutions when the solution is the problem: Arraying the disarray in
development, World Development 32(2): 191212.
Sen, A. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Random House.
Thomas, A. 1999. What makes good development management? Development in Practice 9(12): 917.
Woolcock, M. 2009. The next 10 years in development studies: From modernization to multiple modernities,
in theory and practice, European Journal of Development Research 21(1): 49.
Development management and policy implementation
383
Part VIII
Understanding the
evaluation process
29
Six models of evaluation
Evert Vedung
Evaluation dened
Evaluation is an activity aimed at distinguishing the precious from the worthless, the acceptable from
the unacceptable, the bene cial from the detrimental. In present-day public sector management,
however, evaluation has acquired more specic and narrow meanings. Here, evaluation is a mechanism
for monitoring, systematizing, and grading ongoing or just nished government interventions
(organizations, policies, programs, projects, activities, their eects, and the processes preceding these
eects, perceptions of intervention content included) so that public ocials and other stakeholders
in their future-oriented work will be able to act as responsibly, creatively, equitably and economically
as possible. In this chapter, the following minimal denition of evaluation will be adopted:
Evaluation is careful assessment of the merit, worth, and value of organization, content,
administration, output, and eects of ongoing or nished government interventions, which
is intended to play a role in future, practical action situations.
Merit criteria that evaluations use
In order to perform evaluation, descriptions, however exact, of the phenomena to be assessed
are not enough: evaluators also need criteria of merit, worth and value.
Suppose that a municipal anti-smoking campaign targeted at secondary school students adopts
as its goal that 5 percent of smoking students shall quit smoking within three months after the
completion of the campaign. In addition, suppose that an evaluation is launched four months after
the end of the campaign to nd out whether the campaign did achieve its own goals. In this
case, the merit criterion is the campaigns own goal: 5 percent of the smoking students shall quit
smoking within three months after the completion of the campaign. An evaluation model taking
goals as evaluative criteria is using the goal-attainment model.
The evaluation models included in this chapter are the most important ones in the eld. A
taxonomy is presented below:
1 goal-attainment model;
2 side-eects model;
387
3 relevance model;
4 client-oriented model;
5 stakeholder model;
6 collegial models: peer review, self-evaluation.
Evaluation models organized according to their criteria of merit constitute a fairly varied group.
In addition to the standard goal-attainment model, the taxonomy embraces the side-eects model,
the relevance model, the client-oriented model, the stakeholder model, and collegial models
combining peer review with self-evaluation.
1
One obvious set of models will not be covered here: economic models. In addition to substantive
values, economic models focus on cost aspects of public interventions. The two basic variants
among economic models are the productivity and the eciency models. Eciency models are
divided into cost-eectiveness and cost-benet. However, for reasons of space they are excluded
from this chapter.
Adierent possibility would be to organize the survey according to methodology to be used
in ascertaining intervention eects. This methods-driven point of view is pursued by the present
movement for evidence-based policy and public administration. Models are ordered according
to strength of designs for impact assessment (experiments, quasi-experiments, time-series, process
tracing, etc). I have not chosen this option either.
Another signicant dimension is subject matter to be appraised. Since the focus here will be
on public sector interventions, subject matters are commonly divided into intervention results
and intervention processes. Intervention results mean outcome eects, i.e. those consequences
that the intervention, at least to some extent, directly or indirectly has produced in society or
nature. In addition to members of the target group actually reached, results include target group
responses to the intervention in terms of, e.g. attitudes, factual and valuational utterances, and
actions suggested or actually taken. Intervention processes usually include procedures and practices
preceding results, occurring in implementation between intervention adoption and intervention
results. Naturally, processes do not include targets reached, target responses and consequences
beyond those responses, because all that is included in intervention results.
There are many other possible dimensions that might be used to classify models. Data assembly
methods is one (documentary, interrogatory or observational methods). Here, these possible
dimensions will be discussed now and then under each evaluation model but they are not used
to classify them.
My review will treat the models in the order shown above.
Goal-attainment model (effectiveness model)
An approach on long standing is goal-achievement evaluation, also known as goal-attainment
evaluation and eectiveness evaluation. The two basic ingredients of goal achievement evalua-
tion are goal-attainment measurement and intervention impact assessment. In goal-attainment
measurement the key question is: are the results in accord with intervention goals? And the impact
assessment issue can be formulated thus: are the results produced by the intervention?
Goal-attainment evaluation is a paragon of simplicity and lucidity. Its rst step involves
identifying the intervention goals, teasing out their actual meaning and rank order, turning
them into measurable objectives, and determining to what extent they are realized in practice.
The second step implies ascertaining the degree to which the intervention has promoted or
dampened goal realization. The plain anatomy of the goal-attainment model is outlined in
Figure 29.1.
Vedung
388
The strength and shortcomings of the goal-attainment model
In earlier literature, public sector evaluation was goal-attainment appraisal, period. Since then,
however, quite a few other merit criteria have been suggested and used. There are, however,
several worthwhile reasons in favor of goal-attainment assessment of public sector interventions.
The argument from representative democracy is one.
2
In a democracy, all power belongs to the people. Yet, due to lack of competence and time,
the people cannot make all the complicated decisions concerning the well-being of citizens.
The people do not have time to participate in hundreds of thousands of decisions. And they do
not have the necessary competence to make wise decisions on, for instance, placement of
patients in line for surgery, or day-to-day care for ailing senior citizens in public sector homes
for the elderly. For these reasons, the citizenry must elect political representatives to make the
decisions for them. But representatives in political assemblies do not have the time or compe-
tence to make all decisions. They must delegate their power to governments to make decisions
for them. But governments do not have time and the specic knowledge necessary, so they in
turn have to delegate to civil servants and professionals to take decisions, and so on. The public
sector is made up of long chains of principal-agent relationships.
If an agency adopts a program in order to reach some goals, these goals derive their legiti-
macy from the fact that the agencys decision-making authority has been delegated to it by the
government and that the government, in turn, has received its authority to do so from parlia-
ment, and parliament, in turn, from the people. It is a merit of the goal-attainment model that
it recognizes this democratic aspect of public sector goals.
In sum, the goal-attainment model scores an important point with respect to its tilt toward
representative democracy and the parliamentary chain of control. On the other hand, the goal-
attainment model also suers from persistent shortcomings. The most signicant general reasons
against the goal-attainment model are the haziness argument, and the unintended side-eects
argument.
The haziness argument maintains that intervention goals are decient as criteria of merit due to
their obscurity. There are two kinds of goal obscurity: goal indeterminateness and goal catalogs.
Occasionally, programs are based on indeterminate goals. Particular goals may be ambiguous and
carry two or more meanings. Yet ambiguity in this sense of dual meanings is exceptional in
policy and administrative language, and barely bothers evaluators. More uncertainty is caused by
vagueness. A goal is vague if it does not delineate clearly cases where it is or is not applicable.
The outer border delimiting the extension of a vague word is so fuzzy that within a certain
range it is impossible to know what is included in the extension and what is not. Rampant in
political rhetoric, vagueness is one favorite expedient to settle political conicts through
semantic formulas without really resolving them.
Figure 29.1 Goal-attainment model
Six models of evaluation
389
The second major obscurity is produced by goal catalogs. Most large social reforms contain
impressive directories of diverse goals. While a single goal may be hailed as the major one, it is
often maintained that this one must be balanced against all the others, maybe including poten-
tially conicting ones. But the necessary trade-os between the several goals are not indicated,
which makes it impossible to elicit from such lists of goals one distinct, transparent, expected
outcome. Thus, program goals do not oer any safe guidance for continued data assembly. They
are neither specic nor lucid enough to be usable as value criteria against which to measure
intervention successes and failures.
The goal-haziness argument reveals an important mist between the requirements of the
goal-attainment model and the way public policies, programs, and activities are often com-
posed. If elected ocials and program planners have not specied individual goals into measurable
objectives, and if they have not balanced the various stated goals into one global outcome or
output measure, the goal-attainment evaluator cannot summarize her ndings into a completely
value-neutral evaluative judgment. She can do so only after she has claried the goals and
prioritized among them in a fashion that will cast doubts on the objectivity of the whole
enterprise.
The second general counter-argument, about unintended side-eects, is in my view the crucial
one. Public sector interventions, in social security and social work for instance, invariably lead
to consequences which were not foreseen in the original decision situation. Were the evaluators
to conne themselves to ascertaining the achievement of premeditated goals, the search for
serendipitous results or unanticipated side-eects outside the goal area would not be included in
the evaluation process. The evaluation ndings would exhibit a tunnel vision of events, and
produce a biased, if not fundamentally wrong, picture of what the intervention has attained. In
all likelihood, a program generating some interesting spin-o eects must be better than a
program producing several undesirable spillovers.
In sum, the major strength of the goal-attainment model is grounded in the theory of repre-
sentative democracy. Yet, it has problems with hazy goals and goal catalogs, pervasive as we all
know in public policy. The most compelling rebuttal, however, emanates from the models
blindness to side-eects.
At this point, I would like to present a model that expressly considers the weighty side-eects
argument, while retaining the fundamental goal-orientation of the goal-attainment model: the
side-eects model.
Side-effects model
The side-eects model implies a widening of the subject-matter of the goal-attainment model in
the sense that search for results in the target area is supplemented by search outside the target area
for side-eects. The underlying idea is that public interventions may produce other things than
intended results which, in turn, constitute reasons for new interventions. Interventions beget
interventions.
The role of heat pumps in Swedish energy production is an illustrative case of a solution
turned into a problem in need of a solution. From the 1970s, government subsidies were dis-
embursed for the installation of heat pumps for the retrieval of the enormous amounts of waste
energy produced by the paper and pulp industry along the northern coast of the Gulf of
Bothnia as a solution to the oil and nuclear power problem. The rapid dissemination of heat
pumps was a consequence of government subsidization. After some years, it was discovered that
the heating medium, CFCs (freons), in the heat pumps might leak into the atmosphere and,
over time, damage the stratospheric ozone layer protecting the earth from dangerous ultraviolet
Vedung
390
radiation. A small part of this damage can be regarded as an unforeseen and unintended side
eect of Swedish government support of heat pumps. From the mid-1980s, the heat pumps
turned into an environmental problem that needed to be solved politically.
From the interventionist point of view, a side eect can be dened as at least a partial
consequence of the intervention, which cannot be included among the desired main eects.
Main eects are those actual, expected and wanted consequences, which at least are partly
produced by the intervention. Side-eects can be unanticipated but also anticipated and con-
sidered in calculations preceding decisions to adopt policies. They may be benecial as well as
detrimental.
Public interventions may also create perverse eects. Perverse eects run exactly counter to the
very intentions of the intervention instigators. Since these impacts occur in the target area, they
are not side-eects. Neither are they main eects, since they are not coveted by the policy
instigators. Perverse eects are also dierent from null eects. Null eects mean that interventions
produce no impacts at all on their targeted areas. In the perverse eects case, consequences are
produced but entirely contrary to the ones intended.
Since perverse eects and null eects occur in the targeted areas, the goal-attainment model
with all its attention directed at what happens in these particular elds has no problem with
handling them. But this also means that the model cannot discover and ascertain side-eects
because they fall outside the targeted sectors. This task is left to the side-eects model.
Evaluators and policy-makers should pay attention to side-eects because by-products,
whether detrimental or benecial, are crucial factors in every inclusive judgment of the opera-
tion of an intervention. Should it turn out that side-eects, which have been known, discussed,
and positively valued in advance, have not materialized in spite of the fact that the program has
been on the books for the intended period of time, this ought to have consequences for any
appraisal of it.
If the totality of eects of a government intervention inside and outside its targeted area were
to be investigated, the structure of the evaluation on the outcome side might be as shown in
Figure 29.2.
I strongly commend side-eects to goal-attainment evaluation. Indeed, the major rationale
for doing public sector evaluation in the rst place is that state actions to some extent are
unpredictable and regularly result in side-eects not originally foreseen. It is an important duty
of evaluation to map and assess the worth of these side-eects.
Figure 29.2 Side-effects model with specied pigeonholes for side-effects
Six models of evaluation
391
Also, in terms of merit criteria, the side-eects model engenders an extension of goal-attainment
in that intervention goals stated in advance are supplemented with merit criteria for side-eects.
If some eects are not foreseen, the criteria and standards for judging merits and demerits of
these eects are not pre-specied either. Therefore, pre-specied goals are insucient as instru-
ments of judging unanticipated side-eects is concerned. A feasible solution is the following.
Aside from mapping the main eect and comparing it with the pre-specied goals, the eva-
luator may also chart the side-eects but leave it to the commissioners and other users of the
evaluation to ascertain their value and carry out the overall, global assessment of the program ex
post facto. Attention to unanticipated side eects forces evaluators to use other merit criteria than
initially incorporated into the intervention.
Relevance model
In the relevance model, solving the underlying problem is the merit criterion against which the
worth of the intervention is assessed. Is the intervention bearing on, connected with or perti-
nent to the solution to or at least the alleviation of the problematic matter in hand? If all or part
of the problem has been solved by the intervention, the intervention is successful; if not, it is a
failure (more in Vedung 2009: 116.).
The underlying problem is a complex criterion. Which underlying problem is at stake? As a
rst cut, the answer is the problem embedded in the intervention, namely the problematic
situation that the intervention purports to attack. But of course there are others, to be omitted
in this brief overview.
To be relevant, what does it mean? Pertinent to the problematic matter in hand would be one
reasonable clarication. Yet, pertinence is not enough. To some degree, a relevant intervention
must also be adequate, useful, sucient and proper for the task at hand.
What should be relevant to the underlying problem? The intervention, of course, or more properly
its agreed-upon goals and policy instruments. These relevance issues can be explored early on, that
is once the intervention is adopted but not yet implemented, by reference to scientic ndings
and tested experience. Another possibility would be outputs. A third would be intervention eects
obtained out there in the community. Eect relevance should be studied when the intervention
has been implemented and in operation for some time. Are the impacts then achieved relevant
to the solving of the problem that the intervention is supposed to attack?
Eect relevance seems very close, if not similar, to goal achievement (eectiveness). Yet, they
are dierent. The change in the state of aairs referred to by a goal need not be identical to a
change in the underlying problem. The goal of an information campaign may be to reduce pur-
chases of alcoholic beverages while the underlying problem is to reduce prevalence of alcohol-
related illnesses. But purchases may be down while alcohol-related illnesses are up due to increased
purchases abroad or on international ights.
Here we leave the models using merit criteria derived from the intervention as such: the
goal-attainment, the side eects and the relevance model. Now we will address actor models.
Specic to actor models is that their evaluative criteria are taken from the agents concerned. We
will discuss the client-oriented model, the stakeholder model and the collegial model.
Client-oriented model
The client-oriented model allows members of the interventions target group to perform the
evaluation on the basis of their own merit criteria. Issues at stake are whether the public inter-
vention (1) in terms of its content, (2) during the process up to its delivery, (3) in the delivery
Vedung
392
proper, (4) as regards client responses, or (5) through its eventual outcome eects achieves the
quality that clients deem reasonable, or require or want to see. Clients are asked to pass judgment
on service accessibility (process up to points of delivery), scope and quality of service provision,
or service eects on the recipients themselves (impact at outcome level). As merit criteria, the
client-oriented model may use participant desires, wishes, requests, demands, goals, concerns,
expectations, and so on.
3
The term client denotes the recipients of public interventions. Prisoners in jails, pupils of public
schools, patients in county hospitals, elderly people receiving municipal home care, book-borrowers
in municipal libraries and passengers on municipal buses and trains are examples of clients
(addressees, participants, targets, consumers).
Several approaches might be considered client-oriented. Think about a contrived example
concerning client satisfaction with public-sector services. During 2006 60 percent of parents in
the city of Helsinki, Finland, were satised with the daycare that their children received in
municipal daycare centers. Two years later, the number had dropped to 50 percent. In January 2009
members of the city council expressed concerns about the unexpected plunge. The council
unanimously decided to set 75 percent parent satisfaction as the goal to be achieved in 2011. In
2012 a new study demonstrated that in 2011 65 percent of the parents were satised. Admittedly,
both the 2008 and the 2012 studies are client-oriented. Are they client-oriented evaluations?
The answer is yes. User satisfaction is a client-oriented value criterion. Interestingly, the 2012
study might be considered a goal-attainment evaluation as well, since 75 percent parent satisfaction
was a goal set by the city council.
There are more advanced forms of client-oriented evaluation where clients are much more
implicated. Let me reason from the case where the evaluation is rst, commissioned by the admin-
istrators, and second, planned to involve the service users much more than merely asking them in a
questionnaire about their service satisfaction. In this case, the clients themselves are encouraged to
select the aspects of the intervention, its implementation and outcomes on which to pass judg-
ments. For instance, clients may judge intervention output, service availability, service quality, or
even service process and service administration. Is the core service tailored to meet the demands
of the clients? Are the encounters of the clients with the service employees respectful? These are
two questions that might be answered by the service users in their self-reports. The clients may also
choose to raise the causal issue, that is, estimate intervention impacts on themselves or on the
client community in general.
Currently, the client-oriented evaluation model is employed in numerous contexts such as
nursing homes for the elderly, public housing, mental health, public utilities, recreation, and
physical health services, where clientele participation is crucial to the operation of the services.
Client-oriented models are used to evaluate library services, arts, zoos, and museums. It is a favorite
with educators. At universities, students are routinely requested to share their opinions of courses,
reading lists and lectures. They are asked to rate their teachers abilities to organize the course
contents, to stimulate and promote altercations, to stir student motivation and critical thinking,
and to show concern and enthusiasm for the students.
Pros and cons of client-oriented evaluation
Client-oriented evaluation is justied in several ways. Some philosophers ground it in political
ideologies engendering that public administration produces goods and services for customers in
the market place. They claim that customer pressures expressed through attitudes and suggestions
for improvement via evaluations toward service providers, service management and decision-
makers will lead to improvement of not only the core service, but also of service processes,
Six models of evaluation
393
service delivery, service eects, and customer satisfaction. Through client-oriented evaluation,
public services will become more clearly geared toward the wishes and expectations of the users.
Yet, the customer parallel cannot be pushed too far, since the client notion includes partici-
patory and deliberative aspects. The participatory feature suggests that clients are also citizens
who may voice their complaints and desires to the evaluators and service providers, and to some
extent inuence and take responsibility for service content. The deliberative feature engenders a
discursive, reasoning, and learning-through-dialogue countenance, which may educate service
providers to pay heed to client concerns and clients to become better citizens: the consumer as
citizen rather than the consumer as customer.
4
Client-oriented evaluation may increase the legitimacy of the intervention. If clients are asked
for their opinions and have some inuence on intervention formation, processes and outputs,
their acceptance of the system will probably increase. In addition, client-oriented evaluation may
foster eectiveness and eciency because concentration on clients may force service providers
and managers to do away with many preoccupations besides providing good services.
But evaluators must be aware of the tendency of the clientele to exaggerate complaints in
order to get more service. Clients may also nurture scal illusions. Greater client involvement in
evaluation may surrender power to groups with narrow vested interests.
The client-propelled model may supplement the previously presented approaches, since it
poses other problems. The requirement that the civil service must be responsive to client concerns
is sound, but within limits. It can never take precedence over the requisite that front-line operators
should follow the directives of their hierarchical administrative superiors, and indirectly political
bodies like parliament, the municipal council, and, ultimately, the citizens as a collectivity, whose
votes have determined the composition and general policy direction of these bodies. The elderly
in a community who enjoy municipal social home aid cannot take decisions that run counter to
the rules of the agents and principals in the representative chain of control. They cannot uni-
laterally lower the service fees, for instance. Evaluation models grounded in representative democ-
racy must take precedence over client-oriented models. Client criteria are reasonable to use, but
within limits; they must be balanced against other criteria like goal-attainment and professional
norms for service excellence.
Stakeholder model
In stakeholder evaluation claims, concerns and issues of the various aected actors serve as merit
criteria when interventionstheir contents, processes, outputs, outcomes, and organization
are assessed and evaluated (Vedung 1998: 73.). Stakeholders might be dened as groups or
individual actors that have some interest vested in the intervention to be evaluated or its out-
come eects. Interest may be measured in terms of money, status, power, face, opportunity or
other coin, and may be large or small, as constructed by the groups in question (Guba and Lincoln
1989: 51). This is quite dierent from using prexed objectives as merit criteria, as in goal-
attainment evaluation. Stakeholder evaluation, however, does resemble the client-oriented model,
the major dierence being one of scope: while the client-driven model is basically concerned
with one group of aected interests, the stakeholder model is geared to all of them.
An overview of conceivable stakeholders in local social welfare interventions is presented in
Figure 29.3.
Stakeholder evaluation can proceed in dierent ways. The stakeholders may constitute them-
selves as the evaluation team and carry out the evaluation. The evaluation may also be con-
ducted by particular evaluators, who elicit the views of the stakeholders. In the sequel, I shall
reason from the case that stakeholder evaluation is carried out by particular evaluators.
Vedung
394
Stakeholder-based evaluation starts by evaluator mapping the major groups who are involved
or thought to have an interest in the content, execution, results, and organization of the inter-
vention. The evaluator identies the people who initiated, hammered out, funded, and adopted
the intervention, that is basically the politicians. She identies those who are charged with its
implementation: senior, middle, and junior managers, sta, and front-line operators, who actually
deliver intervention output. She singles out the interventions primary clients and the clients
associations. She identies relatives and relatives associations. She may also include lay people.
And she searches for those who know that they have a stake in the intervention but prefer to keep
a low prole and those who are unaware of the stake they hold.
Advocates of stakeholder models nurture a strong penchant for qualitative, interactive data
assembly methodology. The evaluator must talk to the stakeholders to elicit their narrative his-
tories and observational data, which in turn should be allowed to aect the evaluators next step
in the search procedure. After a while, she might discover both the purported and the genuine
aims of the intervention, and what concerns various stakeholders nurture regarding it. With time,
the evaluator gets more involved and can start to determine which dimensions and concerns of
the stakeholders should be included in the study. Only then can she take a stand on what the
outline of the evaluation should be.
It is typical for the stakeholder model that the evaluator is permitted to search rather extensively
for the dimensions and the crucial concerns on these dimensions. The idea is that the evaluator
must be responsive to the issues and concerns of the aected people and let these govern the
next step in the investigatory enterprise. Through interactive communication she is supposed to
nd out which stakeholder dimensions and concerns are to be taken seriously and probed more
deeply. The evaluation design will be gradually determined. Stakeholder evaluation is responsive
evaluation.
To elicit nal data on stakeholder concerns, advocates of stakeholder models prefer stake-
holder self-observation and sustained interviewing to questionnaires, documentary methods, and
Figure 29.3 Potential stakeholders in local social welfare interventions
Six models of evaluation
395
evaluator observation. In-depth interviewing of individual targets is one favored technique. In
social service and social work, distribution of self-report instruments that clients, parents, relatives
and other stakeholder networks can easily complete themselves is used. In some cases, client-
oriented evaluators endorse focus group interviewing which allows for group deliberations among the
participants and between the participants and the evaluator. The evaluator tries to create forums
of debate to promote deliberative richness. This will support the development of new ideas,
service concepts, solutions, and technologies. It might also, as a side-eect, educate participants
to become better citizens in the future.
After data are amassed and processed, the reporting of ndings, which might vary from one
stakeholder to another, will commence. The key word seems to be portrayals, that is, infor-
mation-rich characterizations using pictures, anecdotes, thick descriptions, and quotes. The
comprehensive holistic view mediated through a portrait is important. Normally, several criteria
of merit, standards of performance on these criteria and several comprehensive assessments will
be included.
Upsides and downsides of stakeholder evaluation
Stakeholder models have several advantages of which four will be mentioned here.
The democratic arguments for the stakeholder model depart from participative and deliberative
points of view. True, democracy means that citizens in general elections vote for competing
elites that are supposed to make decisions on their behalf (representative democracy). Yet, the citizenry
should also be able to partake in nal public decision-making between elections (participative
democracy). Furthermore, discussion, dialogue and debate are also important democratic values
because they help people to form and rene their beliefs and preferences (deliberative democracy).
The stakeholder model satises these participative and deliberative values somewhat more than
the goal-achievement and the side-eects models.
According to the knowledge argument, avoiding intervention insights, which those involved
indubitably have, would be foolish of evaluators. Stakeholders nurture convictions about inad-
vertent side-eects, sophisticated implementation barriers, and outright cheating which may
furnish evaluators with ideas about topics for further investigation. Since stakeholder-orientation
will bring up more aspects of the subject-matter for discussion, the quality of the evaluation
ndings will increase. All in all, it is easy to agree with the recommendation that almost every
evaluation ought to begin with the determination of relevant actors and rounds of interactive
data assembly.
Findings from goal-attainment and side-eects evaluations, carried out with quantitative metho-
dology and with no interactive involvement of stakeholders, seem have little impact. The stake-
holder approach increases the chances that issues of genuine interest to concerned parties will be
addressed. It brings to light information that meets the real requirements of the dierent stake-
holders, thereby enhancing the probability that the ndings actually will be put to use. This is
the utilization argument in support of stakeholder evaluation.
Finally, the stakeholder models might promote compromises, and forestall political struggle. Sta-
keholder assemblies are consensus-building mechanisms. They are vehicles for shaping agreement
on the results of earlier eorts, and most importantly, proposals for future action. Consensus
building and the rendition of legitimacy to fundamental decisions are considered great advantages
of stakeholder evaluation.
There are also obvious drawbacks with stakeholder models. Stakeholder evaluations are inordinately
impractical and resource-demanding, since several stakeholding constituencies must be contacted and
nurtured.
Vedung
396
Stakeholder models are fuzzy. They provide no authoritative answer to the question of who
the stakeholders are. Furthermore, all the stakeholding audiences, however selected, are treated
as equals. But in a representative democracy, elected politicians must carry more weight than
administrators or experts and even clients on the substantive matters under consideration. The
stakeholder model embodies no priorities among the stakeholders. Like client-oriented evaluation,
stakeholder evaluation must work within the frames xed by representative democracy.
While hazy in its contours, impractical and resource-demanding, the stakeholder model carries
some important merits. Utilization and compromise arguments speak in its favor. Another strong
reason for it is the knowledge argument: it can be used as a search strategy at the start of the
evaluation in order to get a quick and provisional grasp of the meaning, implementation and
outcome of the intervention.
Finally, a case from deliberative and participatory democracy can be made for stakeholder models.
Through the use of the stakeholder approach, aected interests can deliberate public aairs and
learn to become better citizens in the future. They can participate and inuence the nal outcome.
On the other hand, this must take place within the connes set by representative democracy.
Collegial models: peer review, self-evaluation and combinations thereof
Collegial evaluation models imply that personnel of the pertinent agency are entrusted to
evaluate the performance of their colleagues in some other agency or branch of the public
sector using their own professional criteria of merit and standards of quality.
The most celebrated collegial model is the peer review approach, in which the evaluation is
conducted by an external collegium, which by denition is an assembly of professional equals.
Ideally, these equals should be somewhat better in their area of expertise than the colleagues they
are invited to assess. In this way, lawyers evaluate lawyers, scientists scientists, surgeons surgeons,
nurses nurses, and so on.
Self-evaluation is another form. Then, the professional herself evaluates her own performance
or professionals in an organization together evaluate their organizations performance. Often
self-evaluation is combined with external peer review.
Collegial models are constantly used in evaluation of research and higher education. They are
very much based upon dialogue, discussion and deliberation. The procedure usually starts with
self-evaluation. The professionals to be evaluated carry out an appraisal of their own performance,
of their research project, education program, or university department. They discuss strengths,
weaknesses, opportunities and threats (the so-called SWOT scheme). Then, external renowned
scientists and educators of the particular eld are assigned to assess the quality and relevance of
evaluatee work. These peers base their preliminary assessment on the written self-evaluation and
site visits with dialogues. Then evaluatees are given the opportunity to comment on the eva-
luators reports before they are nalized; all in all, the evaluators listen to the evaluatees and
solicit their opinions.
We might wonder what collegial models have to do with public sector evaluation. These
models seem kilometers away from the arena of policy-making and program enactment. The
answer is embodied in the principle of the profession-driven public sector. In some areas of
public life, goals are so complex and techniques so dicult that political ocials have found it
wise to leave the shaping and debating of them to well-educated professionals. Architects, judges,
professors, doctors, veterinarians, and engineers would be cases in point. Hence, it is also con-
sidered natural to delegate ex post evaluation to the professions. But since these professionals
work in the public sector, peer review must be regarded as an evaluation model on a par with
the other models used in public life.
Six models of evaluation
397
Let me illustrate this evaluation prototype with the Swedish National Agency for Higher
Education former strategy for evaluation of research and education at the state universities in
Sweden. The agency once instituted the following ten-steps evaluation policy:
1 The Board adopts a comprehensive evaluation policy: during the upcoming six-year period,
all universities and colleges in the country will be evaluated on a rotational basis.
2 The Board decides in broad terms about groups of evaluations: e.g. research in all the
university departments of social work will be evaluated next year.
3 For every particular evaluation, the Board appoints a project manager (project group)
within the agency and a number of qualied external evaluators who receive introductory
information.
4 Each department of social work performs a self-evaluation departing from the national
agencys special requirements. An important feature of these requirements is that evalua-
tion items ought to be placed under three headings: (i) preconditions for research, (ii)
research processes, and (iii) research ndings. The self-evaluations follow the SWOT
scheme, i.e. strengths, weaknesses, opportunities, and threats.
5 The external experts familiarize themselves with the subject-matter by consulting self-
evaluations, research reports, CVs and other relevant materials from the departments to be
evaluated.
6 External assessments are carried out through site visits. In all, evaluatees, researchers and
research groups make presentations for and participate in discussions with the external
assessors. The expert panels are confronted face-to-face with the evaluated researchers.
The experts observe, listen, ask questions, discuss and take notes.
7 The external assessors compile preliminary assessments for each department, to which the
departments in question are asked to respond.
8Anal report is prepared by the external evaluators, and the project manager formulates a
nal assessment on the basis of which the National Agency Board decides on measures
such as cancelation of examination rights.
9 Follow-up conferences are arranged, where each department is informed about the particular
assessments performed by the external reviewers.
10 One year later, the Board carries out a follow-up to verify that recommended measures
are taken.
Central to collegial evaluation is selection and application of evaluative criteria and standards for
estimating the quality of preconditions, processes and ndings. For this, the professionals them-
selves are particularly suitable, because these assessments require specialist knowledge. In addition,
quality criteria are complex by being associated with specic methodological approaches. Fur-
thermore, due to knowledge growth, yardsticks as well as professional approaches are continually
changing in the disciplines. Add to this that quality criteria are often communicated orally only
in the relevant professions as tacit knowledge. This tacit knowledge must be brought forward
through penetrating dialogues among groups of colleagues.
A second strength is that site visits are short and therefore inexpensive. On the other hand,
the evaluation may still become expensive through consultant fees, travel expenses, and because
it takes time to complete the nal report.
One weakness with short site visits and self-evaluations is that evaluatees may be tempted to
show up facades and erect Potemkin villages.
Collegial models frequently produce shaky results. Matched panels use widely dierent merit
criteria and performance standards and reach miscellaneous conclusions. However, in technically
Vedung
398
complex elds, collegial evaluation is probably the nest method available to judge the quality
of what is produced.
Final note on choice among the six evaluation models
This chapter has provided a broad overview of the evaluation landscape from a narrow but man-
ageable perspective. Since evaluation is a normative, value-laden enterprise, I have organized the
survey by merit criteria used in various evaluation models. Six such models have been reconstructed.
An evaluation model is as a template based on one, two, three and even more dimensions
indicating in a general way how an evaluation can be done
As an innovation in 1950s and 1960s evaluation was equated with the goal-attainment model.
Owing to sharp criticism, this model was pushed into the background in the discourse, but
hardly in practice. Since 1980, however, it has experienced a renaissance in the discussion, partly as
a feature of so-called performance management. In addition, thanks to the so-called evidence-
based wave that presently dominates the evaluation discourse, the goal-attainment model (sometimes
under the designation eectiveness evaluation) has become even more important.
The major downside of goal-attainment evaluation is its inability to take account of unfore-
seen side eects. For this reason the side-eect model is recommended. The side-eects model
is the goal-attainment model expanded into (1) an all-eects model using (2) merit criteria
articulated expost in addition to pre-ordained goals.
In contrast with the goal-attainment model, the relevance model uses solution of underlying
problems as merit criterion. This approach provides evaluators with a critical edge in allowing them
to question the goals in case the intervention achieves its goals without solving the problem.
The stakeholder model has become popular particularly since 1970. Since full objectivity is
impossible to reach in evaluative work, its proponents argue that providing multiple images of
reality from dierent perspectives is an appropriate approach.
Collegial models take the quality criteria of one group of stakeholdersthe relevant profes-
sionalsas their bases for assessment. These criteria are dicult to grasp, constantly changing and
often embedded into the professions as tacit knowledge. A collegial evaluation starts with the
evaluatees performing a self-assessment followed by an external evaluation carried out by inde-
pendent highly qualied colleagues. The collegial models are assumed to capture and appreciate
complex qualities of dicult policy areas like surgery, engineering, basic research, and so on.
Since about 1980 client-oriented evaluation has come to the fore especially within health
care, culture, transportation, services and education. The philosophy is that the citizen is a cus-
tomer whose needs should be considered so that public services become more accustomed to
client wishes. Indirectly this also increases the eciency and legitimacy of the system.
The client-oriented model may conict with the goal-attainment, side eects and relevance models,
all of which derive their legitimacy from representative democracy. Since representative democracy
is the basic form of government in Western nations, the client model as well as the stakeholder
model must work within the limits set by the representative system. In this way the information
produced by the client model may supplement information produced by the other models.
Each evaluation model provides partial perspectives and answers only. For this reason, combinations
of several models are commended.
Notes
1 Besides a new text on the relevance model, the chapter is an abbreviated and reworked version of
Chapter 4 in my book Public Policy and Program Evaluation (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers,
Six models of evaluation
399
paperback 2009 (1998), www.transactionpub.com/cgi_bin/transactionpublishers.storefront). For footnotes,
see this book.
2 Several other reasons for and against are presented in Vedung [1998]2009: 40.
3 Actually, there is also a school of thought which uses client needs as a point of departure for client-oriented
evaluation. To simplify I have avoided the needs issue here.
4 My extensive experience as an evaluation instructor has taught me to emphasize the dierence between
intervention clients (intervention participants, addressees) and evaluation clients (evaluation users). The
evaluation client is the person, group, or agency that has commissioned the evaluation of an intervention
or is supposed to use its ndings, whereas the intervention client is the intended or actual recipient of
the intervention.
Bibliography
Bardach, Eugene. 2011. A Practical Guide for Policy Analysis: The Eightfold Path to More Eective Problem
Solving. Washington, DC: CQ Press.
Guba, Egon G. and Yvonna S. Lincoln. 1989. Fourth Generation Evaluation, 1st edn. Thousand Oaks, CA:
Sage.
Hansen, Hanne Foss. 2005. Choosing evaluation models: A discussion on evaluation design, Evaluation
11(4): 44762.
Hansen, Morten Balle and Evert Vedung. 2010. Theory-based stakeholder evaluation , American Journal of
Evaluation 31(3): 295313. Available at: http://evi.sagepub.com/content/16/3/263.full.pdf+html
Preskill, Hallie and Darlene Russ-Eft. 2004. Building Evaluation Capacity: 72 Activities for Teaching and
Training. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Rossi, Peter E., Mark W. Lipsey and Howard E. Freeman. 2004. Evaluation: A Systematic Approach, 7th
edn. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Russ-Eft, Darlene and Hallie Preskill. 2009. Evaluation in Organizations: A Systematic Approach to Enhancing
Learning, Performance, and Change, 2nd edn. New York: Basic Books.
Stuebeam, Daniel L. 2000. Foundational models for 21st century program evaluation, in Daniel L.
Stuebeam, George F. Madaus and Thomas Kellaghan (eds) Evaluation Models: Viewpoints on Educational
and Human Services Evaluation. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 3384.
Vedung, Evert. [1998]2009. Public Policy and Program Evaluation. New Brunswick: NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Available at: www.transactionpub.com/cgi_bin/transactionpublishers.storefront.
——. 2010. Four waves of evaluation, Evaluation 16(3): 26377. Available at: http://evi.sagepub.com/
content/16/3/263.full.pdf+html
Wholey, Joseph S., Harry P. Hatry and Kathryn E. Newcomer. 2010. Handbook of Practical Program Evaluation.
3rd edn. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Vedung
400
30
Policy feedback and learning
Patrik Marier
Introduction
This chapter tackles two subelds that have recently grown in importance in the analysis of public
policy: policy feedback and policy learning. While policy learning is a potential outcome resulting
from policy feedback, the latter is not essential for learning to occur. In fact, relative to the well-
focused literature on policy feedback, this chapter illustrates that the literature on policy learning
is extremely diverse and encapsulates a myriad of concepts, actors, and learning mechanisms.
This chapter is divided into two sections. The rst denes, analyzes and explains how policy
feedback and policy learning are employed in the study of public policy. The second section discusses
the mechanisms and tools that facilitate or impede policy learning, with a particular attention
given to commissions.
What is policy feedback and policy learning?
This section discusses both subelds and how they matter when it comes to evaluating policy
and fostering or hindering policy change. Each subeld is dened, analyzed and explained via
these lenses. Special attention is put onto the dierent epistemological roots associated with
these concepts and how this impacts the analysis of public policy.
Policy feedback
Nearing the end of her high school life, Isabelle must decide what subject she will study as a
senior. Should she follow in the footstep of her parents and study chemistry or pursue her
dreams of becoming a historian? She opts for the later and selects a wide range of social science
courses rather than studying chemistry and physics. According to students of policy feedbacks, Isa-
belle has made a crucial decision on her future. If she pursues this path in university, she might
end up being a history professor at a high school or university in the future. Like so many students,
however, she could change her mind. The literature on policy feedback would stress that this
outcome would be far more likely during her rst year of university than after completing her
graduate studies in history. The costs of reversing back to chemistry increase every year while
401
she remains on the history path. Expressed dierently, a decision taken at t
1
alters the calculus for
options at t
2
, which becomes more and more entrenched further in time.
This is, in a nutshell, the logic underpinning policy feedbacks. It explains why we continue
to employ a QWERTY keyboard instead of the vastly superior Dvorak model (David 1985)
and, more controversially, why Americans do not have a universal health system (Hacker 2002).
Each action building on a prior policy decision, akin to Isabelle following more history courses,
generates positive feedback because it strengthens the importance and value of earlier decisions
and, as importantly, increases signicantly the cost of reversal. Economists refer to this as increasing
returns (Pierson 2000; Arthur 1994), while similar phenomena have been discussed in policy
studies under the umbrella of policy succession (Hogwood and Peters 1982) and policy inheritance
(Rose 1990).
In political science, policy feedback owes its origin to the argument that policies create
politics (Lowi 1969; Schattschneider 1935) and the historical institutionalism school (Pierson
1993). Policy feedbacks are also more common than in economics for multiple reasons (see
Pierson 2004 for an in-depth discussion). First, policy reversal is more dicult to enact with
political institutions than markets where underperforming rms and products are replaced by
new rms and/or products. Consumers can choose the product or service they desire while
public goods tend to be compulsory and exhibit non-excludability (ibid.: 301). Second, public
policies tend to empower beneciaries resulting in the creation of interest groups to safeguard
these new benets (Skocpol 1992). Interest groups are particularly important in political science
since citizens, contrary to consumers, are engaged infrequently with the political system (Pierson
2004). Third, new policies often result in the creation of bureaucratic organization whose very
existence is tied in to the success and expansion of specic programs (Derthick 1979). This
results in policy professionals highly committed to protecting their program (Ross 2000: 18).
Finally, studies have demonstrated that voters are more likely to remember negative experiences
such as cutbacks than positive news like the creation of a program (Weaver 1986)
With the past playing such a predominant role, particular attention is given to the initial
adoption of policies, formative moments (Rothstein 1992), and critical junctures (Collier and
Collier 1991), which represent exceptional moments where opportunities arise to challenge pre-
existing policy legacies. Although the concept of critical junctures seems reminiscent of King-
dons (2003) window of opportunity, these moments are far more exceptional and infrequent
than what students of agenda-setting suggest (Hacker 2002) since they tend to require events
such as wars, regime changes, or major economic recessions.
Central to the study of policy feedback is the concept of path dependence, which is dened
succinctly by Hacker as being developmental trajectories that are inherently dicult to reverse
(2002; 54; see also Kay in this volume). According to Pierson (2004: 44), there are four key
features associated with path dependence processes. First, multiple outcomes are possible at the
initial stage. This is where an actual path is created. Many comparative studies begin with a
similar critical juncture and explain divergent outcomeS as a result of having opted for dierent
paths. For example, Weir and Skocpol highlight that the lack of a cross-alliance between the labor
and agrarian movements in the US explains why the Swedish Social Democratic party, built upon
such a cross-alliance, has been much more successful in implementing a generous and encom-
passing social agenda (Weir and Skocpol 1985). Second, the starting point for a path may be a
relatively minor event. In his study of the American welfare state, Hacker points to a 1974 last-
minute amendment to the Employee Retirement Income Security Act (ERISA) bill that is at the
origin of a weakening of employers pension plans (2004: 2545). Third, when an event occurs
and in which sequence events occur matter greatly. This is because earlier events are far more
important than those occurring at a later date. For example, countries who succeeded in
Marier
402
introducing a value-added tax during the golden age of the welfare state have been able to diversify
their source of revenue and obtained better protection against retrenchment (Kato 2003). Fourth,
once a process is well established, the policy output is likely to remain quite stable and very resistant
to change. In the comparative welfare state literature, multiple debates in the past 20 years have
actually been focused on whether or not the welfare state is an immovable object (Pierson 1998).
In policy studies, the logic of policy feedback and the concept of path dependence have enjoyed
tremendous appeal to explain the evolution and strong stability of many social policies such as
pay-as-you-go pension programs. The adoption of social security during the great depression
has actually been utilized to describe and compare six streams of policy feedback (Béland 2010).
Policy feedback from social security has resulted in the creation of future beneciaries who are
now well organized within the AARP (Pierson 1994), in the mobilization of the electorate
(Campbell 2003) and in the expansion of the social security administration, which has played a
key role in promoting and expanding the program (Derthick 1979). Other important elements
point to its stability. Potential reformers not only have to tackle the mobilized beneciaries and
the Social Security Association, but also issues related to the so-called double payment pro-
blem. After years of contributions, there is a strong sense of entitlement embedded with current
and past contributors. With past contributions utilized to provide pension bene ts to the pre-
vious generation, the introduction of privately funded pension plans requires contributions to
be made to both public schemesto honor prior commitmentsand private schemes to build
up assets in the funded scheme (Myles and Pierson 2001). The American political institutions,
riddled with veto points, also makes it extremely dicult to build a coalition to reform social
security (Pierson, 1994).
More recently, the literature has evolved by stressing that a distinction should be made between
positive and negative policy feedback. The later stresses the the consequences of policies that
tend to undermine rather than reinforce the political, scal, or social sustainability of a particular
set of policies (Weaver 2010: 137). Although not identied as such by many authors, negative
policy feedback constitutes a strong impetus for policy learning (see the section below). For
example, the adoption of monetarism in the UK, which is presented as a case of learning
leading to a paradigm shift (Hall 1993) has also been conceived as a response to negative policy
feedback associated with Keynesianism (Pemberton 2000; Greener 2001). Another interesting
development in the literature on policy feedback has been linked to policy instruments and
policy change. For example, Hacker (2004) develops four kinds of policy change (drift, con-
version, layering, and revision) depending on the number of veto players in the political arena
and the level of policy discretion coupled with its support coalitions. These policy changes are
associated with a dierent use of policy instruments.
Critics of policy feedback have emphasized two key points. First, with an underlying
assumption that policies create politics, the latter is marginalized. While the political orientation
of policy actors may matter when a policy is created, the importance of partisanship decreases to
the point where political leadership, and conict, no longer plays a vital role once a policy or
policy constellation has matured (Ross 2000; Korpi and Palme 2003; Peters et al. 2005). Second,
and reminiscent of previous debates surrounding incrementalism, the policy feedback literature
has diculties accounting for change. Incremental change, which can accumulate and represent
a substantial policy departure, remains largely ignored (Hinrichs and Kangas 2003; Djelic and
Quack 2007; Kay 2005). Most of the attention is given to patterns of persistence and institu-
tionalization, which is often reected in the selection of cases (Peters et al. 2005). The special
attention given to pension policy is a case in point. With high sunk costs, long term commit-
ments, well-established pension agencies and a growing cohort of politically active beneciaries,
it possesses the core attributes to justify the claims of policy feedback arguments.
Policy feedback and learning
403
Policy learning
The analysis of learning has preoccupied researchers in a wide variety of disciplines such as psy-
chology, education, economics, sociology and business. As a result, it is not surprising to notice
that there are multiple conceptualizations and foci surrounding policy learning (Bennett and
Howlett 1992; Dolowitz and Marsh 2000; Marsh and Sharman 2009; Braun and Gilardi 2006;
Radaelli 1995; Evans and Davies 1999). Nonetheless, a common point of departure in public
policy is to dene policy learning as a process of updating beliefs about key components of
policy (Radaelli 2009: 11467). This denition encapsulates all kinds of knowledge that can be
acquired by various learning mechanisms, which reects the eclectic environment of policy-
makers. In this brief overview of policy learning, the focus is primarily on studies that employ
the following concepts: lesson-drawing, social learning, organizational learning, policy transfer,
emulation, adaptation, and policy diusion.
Despite the diversity surrounding policy learning, there are core elements unifying the lit-
erature that also distinguishes it from other public policy writings. First, there is a prevalence on
the importance of knowledge within the policy-making process at the expense of other factors
such as politics, institutions, values, or agendas (Radaelli 1995). As stressed by Heclo in his
classical study of social policy-making in Sweden and the UK, politics nds its sources not only
in power but also in uncertainty policy-making is a form of collective puzzlement on societys
behalf; it entails both deciding and knowing (1974: 3045). As such, there is an underlying
assumption that policy-makers can draw lessonsgood and badfrom a variety of sources to
replace or improve public policies and programs (Rose 1991). Borrowing originally from the
diusion of technological discoveries, the literature on policy diusion assumes that good inno-
vations travel and it tends to focus on the determinants that facilitate or impede di usion and
the actual rate of diusion with the so-called S-shape pattern (Walker 1969; Berry and Berry
2007; Weyland 2007).
Second, an underlying assumption in the literature is that learning must occur without coercion
(Freeman 2006), although this is not embraced in some studies on policy diusion and transfer
where learning is not a precondition to the adoption of a policy by a host country (Dolowitz
and Marsh 1996). Thus, learning is a co-operative undertaking, albeit sometime highly com-
petitive (Dunlop and James 2007). While there are dierent forms of learning in public policy,
like social learning (Heclo 1974; Hall 1993), organizational learning (Hedberg 1981; Levitt and
March 1988; March 1991) and even political learning (May 1992), a core assumption remains
that there is an exchange of information between various actors, organizations, and govern-
ments resulting in valuable lessons. As in the classroom, neither the importer nor the exporter of
lessons is passive and both parties engage in meaningful exchanges for learning to be successful.
There are varying degrees of engagements and this results in a broad theoretical and empirical
focus stressing multiple facets of this exchange such as the underlying conditions pushing a
group, organization, or country to seek out a lesson (Rose 1991; Bennett 1997; Bennett 1991),
the mechanism or underlying structural conditions favoring the transfer or diusion of a lesson
(Walker 1969; Berry and Berry 2007; Shipan and Volden 2008), and the motivations of the
exporter of lessons (Orenstein 2008; Brooks 2004).
Third, although rarely expressed so explicitly, policy learning assumes that the knowledge
acquired is fungible (Rose 1993: Chapter 6) and easily accessible (Bennett 1991: 51). Beyond its
intrinsic appeal, policy learning involves the translation of a lesson into practice and it is important
to distinguish between the knowledge of a (foreign) program, the utilization of that knowl-
edge and the adoption of the same program (Bennett 1991). A number of contributions have
expanded the boundaries of knowledge utilization recently with, for example, contributions on
Marier
404
the use of second-hand experience (Barzelay 2007) and on the importance of symbolic knowledge
utilization where knowledge serves the purpose of increasing the legitimacy of an organization
rather than improve its performance (Boswell 2008). Adaptation remains particularly important
if one is concerned with policy transfer and diusion. For example, the success of the World
Bank in pension policy is largely attributed to the development of a model that was highly
permutable resulting in its adoption in a high number of countries (Orenstein 2008).
Beyond traditional institutional barriers, the type of policy instruments matters greatly when
it comes to exporting a lesson or policy in another jurisdiction. Contrary to programs with
strong policy feedbacks, like national health care services, regulations are highly fungible. In an
analysis of policy diusion between Sweden and Finland, Karvonen (1981) emphasizes that the
most identical policies adopted from Finnish authorities are regulations and that policy diusion
in the United States are facilitated by their strong preferences for regulations.
The fourth commonality is the broad acknowledgment that not all information is of equal
value or weight in the learning process. This can be as a result of the quality of the information
or simply because of the standing of the individual or group communicating the information,
such as experts in an epistemic community (Haas 1992; Ruggie 1975). There is also evidence
suggesting that the political orientation of a government matters. For example, right-wing gov-
ernments are more likely to acquire information and learn from other right-wing governments
in the American states (Robertson 1991). Gilardi (2010) goes further by demonstrating a dier-
entiation in what is being studied with right-wing governments focusing on policy information
related to their re-election and left-wing governments preoccupied mostly by policy eects.
Organizational learning provides another interesting example of how a certain kind of infor-
mation dominates the learning process. Within organizations, lessons from previous experiences
are deeper than those originating from practice. These are rooted in history, where previous
experiencesand the interpretation of these experiencesshape a collective memory (Levitt
and March 1988). This has a dual impact; it can ensure that failed alternatives are not attempted
again but it can also prevent policy alternatives to emerge.
Finally, there is an underlying assumption that learning leads, at the very least, to a policy
reassessment, but often in policy change. In the case of policy diusion, this also takes the form
of convergence, as more and more jurisdictions adapt an innovation (but see Radaelli 2004). An
extensive search for lessons is often triggered when the status quo is no longer an option (Rose
1991: 10). The importance of knowledge is important for both problem recognition and the
development of an alternative. In ways reminiscent of the policy entrepreneur in Kingdon (2003),
groups empowered by their expertise often seek to demonstrate the failing of a policy arrangement
while actively promoting a solution. These actors can be endogenous or external to the jur-
isdictions receiving the lesson and they include civil servants (Hall 1993; Heclo 1974; Etheredge
and Short 1983), elected ocials (Grossback et al. 2004; Gilardi, 2010; Marier 2008), policy
entrepreneurs (Mintrom 1997), policy networks (Coleman et al. 1997; Haas 1990; Evans and
Davies 1999), international organizations (Cao 2009; Orenstein 2008), economists (Marko and
Montecinos 1993), and public inquiries (Bradford 1998; Inwood 2005; Marier 2009).
Policy learning also occurs during the normal operations of government (Etheredge and Short
1983), which often results in incremental change. Bureaucrats learn from the policy itself and
make adjustments to improve it (Heclo 1974; Lindblom 1959). Within this context, learning often
results in change of the rst and second order, which consists of ne-tuning previous policies
and attempting to use new instruments to achieve policy goals (Hall 1993). The long-term
eects of learning by doing may result in a competency trap where most learning happens
while exploiting current practices at the expense of exploring better or more ecient alter-
natives (March 1991). It is far easier to improve what has been used rather than assimilate new
Policy feedback and learning
405
learning. However, the more one invests in improving current practices, the less likely is an
organization willing to adopt better alternatives especially if the implementation costs are substantial.
The end result is the persistent use of sub-optimal procedures (Levitt and March, 1988).
Interestingly, the inability of a public administration to absorb, gather, and analyze lessons can
be at the origin of a diusion or transfer. This can be as a result of past policy failures, limited
policy capacity or lack of time. In her comparative study of Estonia and Latvia, Tavits (2003)
demonstrates that Latvia embraced the Swedish pension reform because its public administration
did not have the capacity and condence from the public to enact its own, following past
economic policy failures while Estonian authorities had high condence in the ability of their
civil servant to devise a good pension system of their own. The adoption of Western policies in
Meiji Japan occurred because there was an urgent need to develop policies quickly (Westney,
1987). In his analysis of pension privatization diusion in Latin America, Weyland (2005) argues
that the newfound knowledge does not even have to be well anchored within the policy elites.
The perception of a highly successful policy in a neighboring jurisdiction may be sucient to trigger
its widespread adoption because of the cognitive heuristics utilized by most policy-makers.
Three important criticisms of the literature on policy learning concerns its diversity, issues
related to the so-called Galtons problem and the marginalization of politics. First, the multi-
plicity of concepts related to learning and divergence related to the independent and dependent
variables continue to plague the literature (Eyestone 1977; James and Lodge 2003). The ways in
which a policy or lesson is dened is crucial. A closer inspection of programs and instruments
can reveal that a diusion process is no longer present because an adopted policy bears little resem-
blance to the one enacted by leaders (Clark 1985). Underpinning these debates is the continuous
divide between qualitative and quantitative studies (Marsh and Sharman 2009). The quantitative
corpus relies on event history analyses to study the diusion of a policy innovation (Collier and
Messick 1975; Walker 1969; Berry and Berry 2007). The theoretical knowledge and techniques
originating from these studies have also been applied to study the diusion of policies across
nations such as the liberalization of the economy (Simmons and Elkins 2004), the privatization
of pensions (Brooks 2005), and hospital nancing (Gilardi et al. 2009). As such, most of these
studies are interested primarily in explaining what characteristics account for the adoption of a
lesson or innovation from another jurisdiction. According to Howlett and Rayner, in spite of
improved quantitative techniques, confusion remains with regards to what is changing and what
is being diused (2008: 387) with Rose expressing disbelief about the lack of attention given to
the content of the programs diused (1993: 25).
The body of work relying primarily on qualitative research designs and comparative case
studies has focused mostly on lesson-drawing (Rose 1991), transfers (Dolowitz and Marsh 2000;
Radaelli 2000), emulation (Westney 1987) and adoption (Bennett 1997) of policies, programs
and/or instruments across jurisdictions. Contrary to studies on diusion, these contributions pay
closer attention to the decision-making process, the relationship between the actors involved
and the motivations that push a state to learn from abroad. However, as in the case of policy
diusion, there is also a lack of communality among these studies concerning the conceptualiza-
tion of learning, the dependent and independent variables. The later is quite important since
few studies have stressed that learning from abroad should be considered as an independent
variable to explain policy change.
Second, Galtons problem where the motivations and sources behind the adoption of a policy
can be endogenous rather than from an independent lesson remains an important issues in policy
learning, but particularly in policy diusion where the adoption of an innovation from an
external source is the primary element under investigation (Braun and Gilardi 2006). There is a
need to demonstrate that a policy changeor a very dierent kind of policy changecould
Marier
406
not have occurred without the presence of learning (Bennett and Howlett 1992: 290) or the
presence of a leader in policy diusion. In a policy environment where information is easily avail-
able, this is increasingly problematic and dicult to disentangle. Thus, the distinction becomes
much more of an issue related to whether knowledge from another source is being utilized or not
and in conjunction with what other sources of knowledge. There are still a lot of improvements
needed to understand how governments are learning from one another (Grossback et al. 2004).
Third, as in policy feedback, critics have mentioned the marginalization of politics. For example,
the epistemic community approach overstates the importance of uncertainty and knowledge
and the ability of policy-makers to act without the help of experts (Dunlop 2009). Politicians
have multiple tools at their disposal to counter or minimize the inuence of an epistemic com-
munity or network of experts, such as adding experts from another eld in consultative bodies
and empowering the expertise that closely resembles their own policy preferences. The ability
to navigate throughout the policy process is also an important form of knowledge that is often
ignored; this form of knowledge is possessed primarily by politicians. In a nutshell, the translation
of learning into policy remains a highly political aair. A potent combination to enact policy
change includes the expertise in both knowledge and process (Marier 2008) or at least connections
to both kinds of experts (Mintrom 1997).
Defeating the policy feedback and policy learning barriersthe role
of commissions
1
Both policy feedback and policy learning tend to underscore the capacity to enact policy change.
While these limitations are more obvious in the case of policy feedback, policy learning also
faces important hurdles such as the institutionalization of professional groups who often dene
who is an expert if not expertise itself (Abbott 1988; Eisner 1993), a bias towards learning from
experience in organizations (Levitt and March 1988), and the traditional political barriers asso-
ciated with the policy-making process such as veto players (Tsebelis, 2002) and veto points
(Immergut 1992). This also includes the organizational structure of government, which is not a
monolithic institution but rather a collection of various agencies and departments with their
own organizational culture and operating procedures. Once a practice has been adopted among
various departments and agencies to handle a specic policy issue, exceptional circumstances are
necessary to alter this relationship.
In order to foster policy learning in this environment and shift discussions away from those
engendered by policy feedbacks, governments may employ other sources of knowledge, such as
the open method of coordination in the case of the European Union (de la Porte and Nanz
2004; Jacobsson 2004; Kerber and Eckardt 2007; Nedergaard 2006), think tanks (Weaver 1989;
Stone and Garnett 1998), and commission of inquiries. This section focuses on the latter.
Commission of inquiriesexpanding the learning potential of government
The creation of a commission, dened as a body to which some task has been referred or
committed by some person or body (Wheare 1955: 6), by a government can result in a transfor-
mation of the policy landscape if it is set up to encourage policy learning. There are multiple
objectives associated with the creation of a commission that actually runs counter to fostering a
learning environment. A government may actually want to delay a discussion on a controversial
subject (ibid.: 912), to drum up support for its own projects (Bulmer, 1983), or even to avoid blame
in the enactment of unpopular measures. Commissions are more potent when they are created
to fulll learning objectives such as enhancing knowledge, facilitating political compromise and
Policy feedback and learning
407
educating the general population (Marier 2009). First, a key underlying theme in the policy learn-
ing literature is the search to curb the level of uncertainty in public policy. Contrary to what is
available within individual ministries under normal circumstances, commissions possess the resour-
ces and the time to perform an in-depth assessment of policies (Olsen 1983; Bradford 1998). In
a nutshell, they operate in a privileged environment, away from the traditional bureaucracy,
allowing them to explore and innovate (Sheri 1983). As a result, commissions have the capacity
to tackle complex issues and relationships within the policy space and provide recommendations
to resolve ongoing problems (Bulmer 1993).
With these assets, commissions can play a critical role in facilitating learning to improve all
forms of policy knowledge. This goes beyond policy prescriptions since the ideas and paradigms
they promote can remain in public debates for years (Jenson 1994). An excellent example is the
McDonald Commission, which altered profoundly the economic policy goals of the Canadian
government. Prior to its creation, only a small number of senior government bureaucrats, a
fraction of the business community, and mainstream economists supported a continental economic
strategy in Canada (Inwood 2005: 309). The McDonald Commission led Canadian authorities
to embrace free trade with the United States and abandon a long-standing national approach to
economic development, which facilitated a paradigm shift (ibid.).
The second learning objective of a commission is to facilitate the negotiation of a political
compromise surrounding a controversial issue. Some political institutions, such as the Joint
Committees in the United States, perform this role to a certain extent. However, commissions
are notorious for granting a voice to multiple groups beyond organized political parties and for
having far more latitude with regard to the elements under discussions. The presence of strong
parliamentary commissions in Norway and Sweden, where experts and politicians interact, have
represented an important forum to generate compromises among political parties, labor unions
and employers associations (Heclo 1974; Premfors 1983; Olsen 1983). As such, a government
may want to utilize a commission to test the feasibility of an idea that requires more analysis and
see whether it can be supported by other key stakeholders (Bulmer 1983). A recent example of
a commission created with the purpose of facilitating the acquisition of knowledge and securing
a political compromise is the Swedish working group on pensions, which was composed primarily
of politicians and experts drawn from the civil service (Marier 2008).
Third, commissions can be established to educate the public about controversial policy issues,
such as the use of nuclear energy. Commissions are utilized to debunk beliefs and advertise recent
research in the policy area under study (Chapman 1973: 184). In these instances, a successful
commission alters the policy discourse by marginalizing prior beliefs and reassessing problems and
solutions (Inwood 2005).
The policy impact of commission
A commission has the capacity to expand signicantly the knowledge possessed by public
authorities. However, the learning experience itself does not guarantee a transformation of public
policies. It is important to distinguish between the acquisition of knowledge and the actual
impact of a commission on policy. A lot of learning can take place and the commission may have
no policy impact. Many variables are involved in the translation of the knowledge acquired
during the workings of a commission into a new policy beyond the institutional barriers gen-
erated by political systems. The rst key hurdle is the simple fact that commissions recom-
mendations are usually nonbinding. Political authorities have the ability to dismiss or ignore the
ndings of a commission. That being said, it is important to note that recommendations from
commissions may be di cult to ignore since they can set policy discussions moving forward
Marier
408
(Bulmer 1983: 663), especially if there is unanimous support among commission members (Park
1972) and stakeholder groups.
Second, the ability of a commission to reshape the policy space is constrained by the terms of
reference. For example, the inuence of a commission will likely be stronger if a government
asks for measures to reform a policy rather than providing an assessment. The terms of reference
represent an important tool possessed by government to steer discussions, but there is no guar-
antee that commissions recommendations will please a government since the workings of a
commission can diverge signicantly from governments expectations resulting in unexpected
ndings and recommendations (Jenson 1994: 54).
Finally, the number of individuals involved in a commission and their respective aliations
plays an important role in determining whether the solutions proposed will have broad appeal
and whether the commission will have the capacity to challenge existing policies. Based on the
literature on veto players (Tsebelis 2002), a commission with a very large membership repre-
senting very divergent interests is unlikely to yield recommendations that have far-reaching
consequences on current policies. In fact, it is more likely that they would produce a report
with a lot of dissension and minority opinions. Therefore, commissions with a small member-
ship are preferable, if the goal is to stimulate learning and bring about policy recommendations
that dier from current practices. Who is selected in these commissions matters greatly. Gov-
ernments can select members who are clearly identied with a policy position or associated with
the government. However, such commissions are unlikely to generate the kind of recommen-
dations that would obtain broad political support and succeed in altering the point of view of
key political players. The most potent commissions, in terms of having the highest likelihood of
generation recommendations that could potentially alter the policy landscape, tend to be the
ones with a small independent membership composed of recognized experts in the eld.
A good example of a recent commission that features all three elements stated above is the
latest British Pension Commission. The three members were not linked to any political party;
they included an individual with ties to the business sector, one with union ties and a university
professor. As a result, they had broad political support for their activities. They worked closely
with governmental ocials to generate an exhaustive assessment of British pension policy and
clear policy directions to resolve its shortcomings. Many of their recommendations were
implemented (Marier 2009).
Conclusion
As demonstrated in this chapter, there is a rich and burgeoning literature on policy feedback and
policy learning. The former has generated multiple studies to explain why policy reform remains
so dicult once a policy or program has been put in place. The emerging literature on negative
policy feedback brings hope that the literature will slowly shy away from focusing primarily on
stability of policy structures (Weaver 2010). The literature on policy learning is highly diversi-
ed, but remains committed to few core elements such as the importance of knowledge in
public policy, the acquisition of knowledge and how individuals and/or organizations learn.
Recent eorts to categorize the literature (Dunlop and Radaelli 2011) and engage in dialogues
to clarify concepts, variables and expectations (Marsh and Sharman 2009) are promising since
the eclectic nature of the literature is both its primary asset and weakness.
Policy feedback and policy learning actually have a lot in common when it comes to describing
the process within which governmental authorities learn from the enactment of policies and
programs and make incremental adjustments as a result. Within the policy learning literature,
organizational learning is consistent with the literature on positive feedback where self-reinforcing
Policy feedback and learning
409
mechanisms entrench programs further at the expense of competing policy proposal. However,
the literature on policy learning assumes that learning can be much broader and emphasizes
policy change while policy feedback stresses mostly the lack of change.
Many of the references discussed in this chapter refer to pension policy because this policy
area illustrates well the dierences between policy feedback and policy learning. On one hand,
there is a wealth of contributions related to the lack of reforms in the pension systems of
advanced industrialized countries. Learning is extremely limited and policy feedbacks are respon-
sible for the limited reforms or the status quo. Pensions represent the case by excellence for
policy feedback with high sunk costs, large upcoming cohorts of beneciaries, and broad pop-
ular appeal. On the other hand, the literature on policy learning, and particularly contributions
on policy diusion, has emphasized rapid change and the adoption of pension privatization in a
growing number of countries, often spearheaded by international forces. However, these pat-
terns of diusion do not apply to advanced industrialized countries (Brooks 2005). One would
be led to conclude that policy learning remains marginal when there are strong policy feedback
eects. However, as demonstrated in the later part of this chapter, the creation of commissions
is one of the tools that can be utilized by policy-makers to enhance learning beyond the incre-
mental options generated by the interpretation of actors involved in managing public programs,
which are strongly associated with policy feedback.
The marginalization of politics and the measurement of policy change remain two core issues
within both the policy feedback and policy learning literature. First, very few contributions
have truly integrated traditional political variables, such as the political orientation of a govern-
ment, within their contributions on learning (but see Gilardi et al. 2009; Robertson 1991) and
policy feedback. The interpretation of a lesson or policy feedback is highly political and who is
in power should matter. For a broader appeal in political science, some notions of political
leadership, choice and interest need to be included in both cases moving forward (for policy
feedback see Ross 2000). Second, a recurring problem in policy studies is to measure change.
The literature on policy feedback has brought back discussions akin to those that were prevalent
in debates surrounding incrementalism (Dempster and Wildavsky 1979) while some contributions
in policy learning have overemphasized the place of learning and/or the extent to which lessons
from abroad are truly exported (Clark 1985; Howlett and Rayner 2008). These issues are unlikely
to nd a satisfying resolution, but a better acknowledgment of these issues would go a long way
to foster a genuine dialogue among researchers in both policy feedback and policy learning.
Note
1 This section draws from Marier (2009).
Bibliography
Abbott, A. 1988. The System of Professions: An Essay on the Division of Expert Labor. Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Arthur, W.B. 1994. Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Barzelay, M. 2007. Learning from second-hand experience: Methodology for extrapolation-oriented case
research, Governance 20: 52143.
Béland, D. 2010. Reconsidering policy feedback: How policies aect politics, Administration and Society
42: 56890.
Bennett, C.J. 1991. How states utilize foreign evidence, Journal of Public Policy 11: 3154.
—— 1997. Understanding ripple eects: the cross-national adoption of policy instruments for bureaucratic
accountability, Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 10: 21333.
Marier
410
—— and M. Howlett. 1992. The lessons of learning: Reconciling theories of policy learning, Policy Sciences
25: 27594.
Berry, F.S. and W.D. Berry. 2007. Innovation and diusion models in policy research, in P.A. Sabatier
(ed.) Theories of the Policy Process, 2nd edn. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Boswell, C. 2008. The political functions of expert knowledge: Knowledge and legitimation in European
Union immigration policy, Journal of European Public Policy 15: 47188.
Bradford, N. 1998. Commissioning Ideas: Canadian National Policy Innovation in Comparative Perspective, Toronto:
Oxford University Press.
Braun, D. and F. Gilardi. 2006. Taking Galtons problem seriously: Towards a theory of policy diusion,
Journal of Theoretical Politics 18: 298322.
Brooks, S.M. 2004. What was the role of international nancial institutions in the diusion of social
security reform in Latin America?, in K. Weyland (ed.) Learning from Foreign Models in Latin American
Policy Reform. Washington, DC: Woodrow Wilson Center Press.
—— 2005. Interdependent and domestic foundations of policy change: the diusion of pension privatization
around the world, International Studies Quarterly 49: 27394.
Bulmer, M. 1983. Introduction: commissions as instruments for policy research, American Behavioral Scientist
26: 55967.
—— 1993. The Royal Commission and departmental committee in the British policy-making process,in
B.G. Peters and A. Barker (eds) Advising West European Governments: Inquiries, Expertise and Public Policy.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Campbell, A.L. 2003. How Policies Make Citizens: Senior Political Activism and the American Welfare State.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cao, X. 2009. Networks of intergovernmental organizations and convergence in domestic economic
Policies, International
Studies Quarterly 53: 1095130.
Chapman,
R.A. 1973. Commissions in policy-making, in R.A. Chapman (ed.) The Role of Commissions in
Policy-Making. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Clark, J. 1985. Policy diusion and program scope: research directions, Publius 15: 6170.
Coleman, W.D., G.D. Skogstad and M.M. Atkinson. 1997. Paradigm shifts and policy networks: cumulative
change in agriculture, Journal of Public Policy 16: 273301.
Collier, D. and R.E. Messick. 1975. Prerequisites versus diusion: Testing alternative explanations of
social security adoption, The American Political Science Review 69: 1299315.
—— and D. Collier. 1991. Shaping the Political Arena: Critical Junctures, the Labor Movement, and Regime
Dynamics in Latin America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
David, P.A. 1985. Clio and the economics of QWERTY, American Economic Review 75: 3327.
de la Porte, C. and P. Nanz. 2004. The OMC: A deliberative-democratic mode of governance? The cases
of employment and pensions, Journal of European Public Policy 11: 26788.
Dempster, M. and A. Wildavsky. 1979. On change, or there is no magic size for an increment?, Political
Studies 27: 37189.
Derthick, M. 1979. Policymaking for Social Security. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Djelic, M.-L. and S. Quack. 2007. Overcoming path dependency: Path generation in open systems,
Theory and Society 36: 16186.
Dolowitz, D. and D. Marsh. 1996. Who learns what from whom: A review of the policy transfer literature,
Political Studies 44: 34357.
—— and
D. Marsh.
2000. Learning from abroad: The role of policy transfer in contemporary policy-making,
Governance 13: 524.
Dunlop, C.A. 2009. Policy transfer as learning: Capturing variation in what decision-makers learn from
epistemic communities, Policy Studies 30: 289311.
—— and O. James. 2007. Principal-agent modelling and learning: The European Commission, experts
and agricultural hormone growth promoters, Public Policy and Administration 22: 40322.
—— and C.M. Radaelli. 2011. Systematizing policy learning: From monoliths to dimensions, European
Consortium for Political Research, Joint Session Workshop, St. Gallen.
Eisner, M.A. 1993. Bureaucratic professionalization and the limits of the political control thesis: The case
of the federal trade commission, Governance 6: 12753.
Etheredge, L.S. and J. Short. 1983. Thinking about government learning, Journal of Management Studies
20: 4158.
Evans, M. and J. Davies. 1999. Understanding policy transfer: A multi-level, multi-disciplinary perspective,
Public Administration 77: 36185.
Policy feedback and learning
411
Eyestone, R. 1977. Confusion, diusion, and innovation, American Political Science Review 71: 4417.
Freeman, R. 2006. Learning in public policy, in M. Moran, M. Rein and R.E. Goodin (eds) The Oxford
Handbook of Public Policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gilardi, F. 2010. Who learns from what in policy diusion processes?, American Journal of Political Science
54: 65066.
——, K. Fuglister and S. Luyet. 2009. Learning from others: The diusion of hospital nancing reforms
in OECD countries, Comparative Political Studies 42: 54973.
Greener, I. 2001. Social learning and macroeconomic policy in Britain, Journal of Public Policy 21: 13352.
Grossback, L.J., S. Nicholson-Crotty and D.A.M. Peterson. 2004. Ideology and learning in policy diusion,
American Politics Research 32: 52145.
Haas, P.M. 1990. Saving the Mediterranean: The Politics of International Environmental Cooperation. New York,
Columbia University Press.
—— 1992. Introduction: Epistemic communities and international policy coordination, International
Organization 46: 135.
Hacker, J.S. 2002. The Divided Welfare State. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
—— 2004. Privatizing risk without privatizing the welfare state: The hidden politics of social policy
retrenchment in the United States, American Political Science Review 98: 243 60.
Hall, P.A. 1993. Policy paradigms, social learning, and the state: The case of economy policymaking in
Britain, Comparative Politics 25: 27596.
Heclo,
H. 1974. Modern Social
Politics in Britain and Sweden. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Hedberg, B. 1981. How organizations learn and unlearn, in P.C. Nystrom and W.H. Starbuck (eds)
Handbook of Organizational Design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hinrichs, K. and O. Kangas. 2003. When is a change big enough to be a system shift? Small system-shifting
changes in German and Finnish pension policies, Social Policy and Administration 37: 57391.
Hogwood, B.W. and B.G. Peters. 1982. The dynamics of policy change, Policy Sciences 14: 22545.
Howlett, M. and J. Rayner. 2008. Third generation policy diusion studies and the analysis of policy
mixes: Two steps forward and one step back?, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 10: 385402.
Immergut, E.M. 1992. Health Politics: Interests and Institutions in Western Europe. Cambridge Cambridge
University Press
Inwood, G.J. 2005. Continentalizing Canada: The Politics and Legacy of the Macdonald Royal Commission.
Toronto, University of Toronto Press.
Jacobsson, K. 2004. Soft regulation and the subtle transformation of states: The case of EU employment
policy, Journal of European Social Policy 14: 35570.
James, O. and M. Lodge. 2003. The limitations of policy transfer and lesson drawing for public policy
research, Political Studies Review 1: 17993.
Jenson, J. 1994. Commissioning ideas: Representation and Royal Commissions, in S.D. Phillips, (ed.)
How Ottawa Spends 19941995: Making Change. Ottawa: Carleton University Press.
Karvonen, L. 1981. Semi-domestic politics: Policy diusion from Sweden to Finland, Cooperation and
Conict 16: 91107.
Kato,
J. 2003. Regressive Taxation
and the Welfare State: Path Dependence and Policy Formation. Cambridge
Cambridge University Press.
Kay, A. 2005. A critique of the use of path dependency in policy studies, Public Administration 83: 55371.
Kerber, W. and M. Eckardt. 2007. Policy learning in Europe: The open method of co-ordination and
laboratory federalism, Journal of European Public Policy 14: 22747.
Kingdon, J.W. 2003. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. New York, Longman.
Korpi, W. and J. Palme. 2003. New politics and class politics in the context of austerity and globalization:
Welfare state regress in 18 countries, American Political Science Review 97: 42546.
Levitt, B. and J.G. March. 1988. Organizational learning, Annual Review of Sociology 14: 31940.
Lindblom, C.E. 1959. The science of muddling through”’, Public Administration Review 19: 7988.
Lowi, T.J. 1969. The new public philosophy: interest group liberalism, The End of Liberalism: Ideology,
Policy, and the Crisis of Public Authority. New York: Norton.
March, J.G. 1991. Exploration and exploitation in organizational learning, Organization Science 2: 7187.
Marier, P. 2008. Empowering epistemic communities: Specialised politicians, policy experts and policy
reform, West European Politics 31: 51333.
—— 2009. The power of institutionalized learning: The uses and practices of commissions to generate
policy change, Journal of European Public Policy 16: 1204 23.
Marko, J. and V. Montecinos. 1993. The ubiquitous rise of economists, Journal
of Public Policy 13: 3768.
Marier
412
Marsh, D. and J.C. Sharman. 2009. Policy diusion and policy transfer, Policy Studies 30: 26988.
May, P.J. 1992. Policy learning and failure, Journal of Public Policy 12: 33154.
Mintrom, M. 1997. Policy entrepreneurs and the diusion of innovation, American Journal of Political Science
41: 73870.
Myles, J. and P. Pierson. 2001. The political economy of pension reform, in P. Pierson (ed.) The New
Politics of the Welfare State. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nedergaard, P. 2006. Which countries learn from which? A comparative analysis of the direction of
mutual learning processes within the open method of coordination committees of the European Union
and among the Nordic countries, Cooperation and Conict 41: 42242.
Olsen, J.P. 1983. Organized Democracy: Political Institutions in a Welfare State: The Case of Norway. Bergen:
Universitetsforlaget.
Orenstein, M.A. 2008. Privatizing Pensions: The Transnational Campaign for Social Security Reform. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Park, Y.H. 1972. The government advisory commission system in Japan, Journal of Comparative Administration
3: 43567.
Pemberton, H. 2000. Policy networks and policy learning: UK economic policy in the 1960s and 1970s,
Public Administration 78: 77192.
Peters, B.G., J. Pierre and D.S. King. 2005. The politics of path dependency: Political conict in historical
institutionalism, The Journal of Politics 67: 1275300.
Pierson, P. 1993. When eect becomes cause: Policy feedback and political change, World Politics 45:
595628.
—— 1994. Dismantling
the Welfare State?
Reagan, Thatcher, and the Politics of Retrenchment. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
—— 1998. Irresistible forces, immovable objects: Post-industrial welfare states confront permanent austerity,
Journal of European Public Policy 5: 53960.
—— 2000. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, American Political Science Review
94: 25166.
—— 2004. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Premfors, R. 1983. Governmental commissions in Sweden, American Behavioral Scientist 26: 62342.
Radaelli, C.M. 1995. The role of knowledge in the policy process, Journal of European Public Policy 2: 15983.
—— 2000. Policy transfer in the European Union: Institutional isomorphism as a source of legitimacy,
Governance 13: 2543.
—— 2004. The diusion of regulatory impact analysis: Best practice of lesson-drawing?, European Journal
of Political Research 43: 72348.
—— 2009. Measuring policy learning: Regulatory impact assessment in Europe , Journal of European Public
Policy 16: 114564.
Robertson, D.B. 1991. Political conict and lesson-drawing, Journal of Public Policy 11: 5578.
Rose, R. 1990. Inheritance before choice in public policy, Journal of Theoretical Politics 2: 26391.
—— 1991. What
is lesson-drawing?, Journal of
Public Policy 11: 330.
—— 1993. Lesson-Drawing in Public Policy: A Guide to Learning across Time and Space. Chatham, NJ: Chatham
House.
Ross, F. 2000. Interests and choice in the Not quite so new politics of welfare, West European Politics
23: 1134.
Rothstein, B. 1992. Explaining Swedish corporatism: The formative moment , Scandinavian Political Studies
15: 17391.
Ruggie, J.G. 1975. International responses to technology: Concepts and trends, International Organization
29: 55783.
Schattschneider, E.E. 1935. Politics, Pressures and the Tari: A Study of Free Private Enterprise in Pressure Politics,
As Shown in The 19291930 Revision of the Tari. New York: Prentice Hall.
Sheri, P.E. 1983. An Anglo-American comparison: Does social science contribute eectively to the work
of governmental commissions?, American Behavioral Scientist 26: 66980.
Shipan, C.R. and C. Volden. 2008. The mechanisms of policy diusion, American Journal of Political Science
52: 84057.
Simmons, B.A. and Z. Elkins. 2004. The globalization of liberalization: Policy diusion in the international
political economy, American Political Science Review 98: 17189.
Skocpol, T. 1992. Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Political Origins of Social Policy in the United States.
Boston: Belknap Press.
Policy feedback and learning
413
Stone, D. and M. Garnett. 1998. Introduction: Think tanks, policy advice and governance, in D. Stone,
A. Denham and M. Garnett (eds) Think Tanks Across Nations. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Tavits, M. 2003. Policy learning and uncertainty: The case of pension reform in Estonia and Latvia, The
Policy Studies Journal 31: 64360.
Tsebelis, G. 2002. Veto Players: How Political Institutions Work. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Walker, J.L. 1969. The diusion of innovations among the American states, The American Political Science
Review 63: 88099.
Weaver, K. 2010. Paths and forks or chutes and ladders? Negative feedbacks and policy regime change,
Journal of Public Policy 30: 13762.
Weaver, R.K. 1986. The politics of blame avoidance, Journal of Public Policy 6: 37198.
—— 1989. The changing world of think tanks, Political Science and Politics 22: 56379.
Weir, M. and T. Skocpol. 1985. State structures and the possibilities for Keynesian responses to the Great
Depression in Sweden, Britain, and the United States, in P.B. Evans (ed.) Bringing the State Back In.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Westney, D.E. 1987. Imitation and Innovation: The Transfer of Western Organizational Patterns to Meiji Japan.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Weyland, K. 2005. Theories of policy diusion: Lessons from Latin American pension reform, World
Politics 57: 26295.
—— 2007. Bounded Rationality and Policy Diusion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wheare, K.C. 1955. Government by Committee. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Marier
414
31
Randomized control trials
What are they, why are they promoted as the
gold standard for causal identication and
what can they (not) tell us?
David Fuente and Dale Whittington
Introduction
Over the past decade scholars, research practitioners, and donors have shown an increasing interest
in using randomized control trials (RCTs) to evaluate the eectiveness of a wide range of social
and infrastructure programs in developing countries. Much as in medicine where randomized
control trials are standard practice, the policy community has turned to RCTs in response to
increasing calls for evidence-based policy. As a result, quasi-experimental approaches to program
evaluation have come under increasing scrutiny and been strongly criticized by advocates of
RCTs. In fact, in some policy and scholarly circles the term RCT has become nearly synonymous
with rigorous and has been hailed as the primary, if not sole, arbiter of hard evidence in the
policy process.
The use of RCTs to assess social policy is not new. Fisher (1935) described the use of a
randomized experimental design to evaluate the response of agricultural elds to a variety of
inputs. In the 1980s labor economists used RCTs to assess the eectiveness of large-scale
workforce training programs in the United States (e.g. Bloom et al. 1993; Doolittle and Traeger
1990; LaLonde 1986). Over the past decade, a new generation of development economists has
adapted and expanded the tools developed by labor economists and applied them in novel ways
to study the impact of a wide range of development programs, including de-worming (e.g. Miguel
and Kremer 2004); educational interventions (e.g. Kremer 2003; Todd and Wolpin 2006); micro-
nance (e.g. Banerjee et al. 2010; Giné et al. 2006); and point-of-use water treatment (e.g.
Kremer et al. 2009; Ahuja et al. 2010). These advances are well reected in the work of the
Abdul Latif Jameel Poverty Action Laboratory (J-Pal)
1
based at MIT, with oces in Africa, Europe,
Latin America, and South Asia as well as Innovations for Poverty Action.
2
These organizations
have collectively executed dozens of RCTs in developing countries across the globe.
Proponents of RCTs often have been vocal critics of past approaches to formulating devel-
opment policy and strong advocates for the broader use of RCTs to identify development
interventions that work. For example, Banerjee (2007) has accused the World Bank of lazy
415
thinking for not ensuring that its policy advice to developing countries is supported by a strong
(RCT) evidence base. Similarly, Duo (2004) has called RCTs in development an interna-
tional public good and been a strong advocate for the broader funding of RCTs by the
international donor community.
3
While scholars at the forefront of the RCT resurgence have
been a prominent voice in academic journals, they have also taken their message to nontechnical
audiences in a series of books (e.g. Banerjee and Duo 2011; Karlan and Appel 2011) and made
spirited calls for the wider use of RCTs in the popular media (Banerjee 2006; Glennerster and
Kremer 2011; Das et al. 2011).
4
The recent surge in the use of RCTs to evaluate development programs has improved the
practice of program evaluation and yielded important and interesting empirical results. At the same
time it has spawned a vibrant debate about whether, as their advocates suggest, evidence from
RCTs should occupy a privileged position in the hierarchy of knowledge used to shape public
policy. This has rekindled old debates ignited by LaLonde (1986) about the relative merits of
RCTs compared to other modes of social inquiry.
5
The most recent incarnation of the RCT
debate has been primarily between economists and has occurred largely in professional meetings
and on the pages of academic journals. Three prominent examples of this debate include the
exchanges between Banerjee (2005), Bardhan (2005), Mookherjee (2005), Kanbur (2005), and
Basu (2005) in the journal Economic and Political Weekly; Angrist and Pischke (2010); Heckman
(2010) and Keane (2010) in the Journal of Economic Literature; and a separate exchange between
Deaton (2010) and Imbens (2010).
To date, the debate among economists about the relative merits of RCTs has largely been
technical in nature. As a result, the broader implications of the debate for policy scholars and
development practitioners are often obscured. This chapter provides an overview of this debate
and oers guidance to policy scholars on the circumstances in which RCTs can be most useful
in policy research.
The current dialog about RCTs is often narrowly pitched as a debate between experimental
and quasi-experimental approaches to program evaluation or structural and reduced form methods
in economics. This chapter does not compare alternative approaches to program evaluation that
are used in economics. Rather, we provide an overview of the arguments typically advanced for
and against the use of RCTs in policy research. Because the arguments for RCTs are typically
more familiar to policy professionals, the chapter spends more time highlighting factors that
complicate claims of RCTs superiority. We do this not to advocate for one form of program
evaluation over another, but to provide policy professionals a more nuanced understanding of
both the strengths and limitations of RCTs. Clearly, if a researcher is interested in estimating a
causal impact of a particular intervention, and they have sucient funding to conduct an experi-
ment, they can wait a long time for results, and the intervention can be randomized (ethically
and practically), it is hard to imagine a situation in which the researcher would choose a quasi-
experimental research design rather than an RCT. However, there are many potentially interest-
ing policy questions, types of interventions, and contexts in which a researcher or policymaker
might need to use alternative approaches. This chapter provides researchers and policy-makers
with a framework for thinking about what RCTs can and cannot contribute to important
public policy debates.
The chapter is organized as follows. The second section presents the standard motivation for
RCTs and discusses the core strength of RCTs in relation to other modes of program evalua-
tion. Section three outlines the common critiques of RCTs and draws attention to the type of
policy questions to which RCTs are well suited. Section four concludes with a discussion of
factors researchers, policy-makers, and donors should consider when assessing whether or not
RCTs can best advance their policy or research agenda.
Fuente and Whittington
416
Randomized control trials: what are they, what can they tell us, and why
are they promoted as the gold standard in causal identication?
Research and formal program evaluation that seeks to establish causal inference between a program
intervention and observed outcomes faces the classical counterfactual problemnamely what the
outcomes for program participants would have been without the program. For example, to identify a
causal connection between the use of a particular point-of-use (PoU) water treatment technology
in a sample of households and reduced incidence of diarrheal disease, one needs to know the number
of episodes of diarrheal disease the same households would have experienced over the same time
period in the absence of the program. Since in this example an individual household would have
either used the PoU water treatment technology or not, the counterfactual required for causal
inference is not observable. That is, we cannot simultaneously observe the same household both with
and without the PoU technology. The fundamental challenge of program evaluation is to construct
a close approximation of this unobservable counterfactual. This requires a control group, which in
the absence of a program or treatment would have similar outcomes to the treatment group.
In order for the control group to represent a valid approximation of the counterfactual required
to identify a causal relationship, the treatment and control groups must be suciently similar in
both observable and unobservable ways. If this condition is not met, the researcher cannot deter-
mine whether the dierence in observed outcomes between the treatment and control groups is
attributable to the program intervention (treatment) or to preexisting dierences between the two
groups. In general, quasi-experimental research methods (e.g. propensity score matching, regression
discontinuity design, etc.) seek to construct control groups using observable characteristics. RCTs,
on the other hand, construct the counterfactual via randomization into a treatment group.
For example, suppose we are interested in understanding the impact of a particular PoU water
treatment technology on diarrheal disease, measured by the number of episodes of diarrheal
disease per person per month in a household.
6
Let Y
i
C be the number of episodes of diarrhea
for a given household i per month in the absence of the PoU water treatment (the control group)
and Y
i
T the episodes of diarrhea per month in the same household with water treatment (treat-
ment group). To identify the causal impact of the PoU water treatment technology on diarrheal
disease, we would want to measure the average impact of the PoU treatment technology on all
households in the program, which can be written as follows:
E½Y
i
T Y
i
C
7
ð1Þ
However, we cannot observe household i both with (Y
i
T) and without (Y
i
C) the PoU treat-
ment technology at the same time. One might try to study a large sample of households, half
with the PoU treatment technology and half without it (each of these quantities is observable)
and calculate the average number of episodes of diarrheal disease per person per month in each
group. This would provide us the dierence between the average number of episodes of diar-
rheal disease conditional on household i having the PoU treatment technology, E[Y
i
T|T], and
the average number of episodes of diarrheal disease conditional on household i not having the
PoU treatment technology, E[Y
i
C|C] represented in equation 2:
E½Y
i
TjTE½Y
i
CjCð2Þ
Ideally one would like information on what would have happened to households in the treat-
ment group if they were not provided with the PoU treatment technology. Let E[Y
i
C|T] be
Randomized control trials
417
the average number of episodes of diarrhea in households in the treatment group if they did not
receive the PoU treatment technology. Simply adding and subtracting E[Y
i
C|T] from equation
2 this yields:
E½Y
i
TjTE½Y
i
CjTE½Y
i
CjCþE½Y
i
CjTð3Þ
The second and fourth terms cancel out and therefore do not aect the equation. Because the
expectation operator is linear, we can rewrite equation 3 as:
E½Y
i
T Y
i
CjTþ½E½Y
i
CjTE½Y
i
CjCð4Þ
The rst term of equation 4 is the treatment eect we are interested in measuring. In our example,
it represents the average eect of the PoU water lter on households in the treatment group.
The second term is selection bias
8
namely preexisting or systematic dierences between house-
holds in the treatment and control groups. However, recall that we do not observe E[Y
i
C|T]
(households in the treatment group without the PoU water lter). Thus, it is dicult to
determine the magnitude or sign of the selection bias and whether estimates of program impact
reect the true program impact, selection bias, or a combination of both. To get accurate esti-
mates of the programs causal impact, researchers face the burden of either estimating the
selection bias and correcting it, or arguing that selection bias does not exist.
With a large sample, if households are randomly assigned to treatment and control groups
they will on average (in expectation) be identical with respect to their observable and unob-
servable characteristics. Thus, under ideal conditions, randomization addresses selection bias by
ensuring that the treatment and control groups would have the same outcomes on average in
the absence of the intervention. More formally, in theory randomization should ensure that the
dierence in average observed outcomes between the treatment and control groups equals the
average of the dierence between the observed outcome for households in the treatment group
and what the outcome for those households would have been in the absence of treatment.
Namely that:
E½Y
i
TjTE½Y
i
CjC¼E½Y
i
T Y
i
CjTð5Þ
In our example, this implies that the treatment and control groups would experience the same
number of cases of diarrheal disease on average without the PoU treatment technology, i.e. that
the control group is a valid counterfactual for the treatment group.
Equation 5 provides information about the average eect of the treatment on households in
the treatment group (often referred to as average treatment on the treated), but not about the
potential impact of the treatment on households in the control group or about the potential
impact on the population in general.
9
If the random assignment is executed correctly and if the
research participants comply with their assignments, the average eect of treatment on households
on the treatment group should equal the average eect of the treatment on households in the
control group. Similarly, the estimate of program impact obtained from equation 5 will only be
representative of the potential impact of the program on an individual randomly chosen from
the general population if the study sample is representative of the larger population.
By construction, RCTs provide information on the average (mean) treatment eects of a pro-
gram or intervention. They do not provide information on the impacts on specic individuals
Fuente and Whittington
418
or on the general population. Rather, RCTs provide an estimate of the average impact of an
intervention on a random person drawn from the study sample.
Under ideal conditions randomization addresses the problem of selection bias. Equation 4
states that selection bias is the average dierence in outcomes between the treatment group and
control group in the absence of the intervention. (Recall that the former is the unobservable
counterfactual and the latter is the observed outcome for the control group.) Randomization
removes selection bias by ensuring that any potential bias in the sample is evenly distributed
between the treatment and control groups (Heckman and Smith 1995: 89).
RCTs provide information on the mean overall impact of a project or intervention after the
program participants and perhaps broader context has dynamically adjusted to the impact. As
noted by Duo et al. (2008) this is distinct from the program impacts holding all else constant,
which is required to estimate the welfare-theoretic consequences of a program.
Under ideal conditions, RCTs provide a means to cleanly estimate the causal impact of a
particular treatment. However, they do not prima facie provide information about the causal
mechanisms that link the treatment to the observed outcome.
Arguments for RCTs
Based on the strong methodological results discussed above, proponents argue that RCTs should
be viewed as the gold standard for identifying causal impact and given special consideration in
the policy arena.
10
Indeed Banerjee (2006) states [w]hen we talk of hard evidence, we will
therefore have in mind evidence from a randomized experiment. Proponents highlight two
main reasons why RCTs are superior to other modes of inquiry. First, they argue that RCTs
have the strongest internal validity of any impact estimation method (Banerjee 2005; Angrist
and Pischke 2010; Duo et al. 2008). Second, they assert that RCTs are based on fewer and less
complicated assumptions than other methods and produce clean estimates of average program
impacts RCT (Banerjee and Duo 2009; Duo et al. 2008). Therefore, proponents claim that
RCTs provide information about program impacts that are more accessible to the policy com-
munity than many quasi-experimental methods, which often employ complex econometric
techniques and rely on untestable assumptions. Each of these arguments is considered below.
Strong internal validity
Empirical results from program evaluations are generally judged on two criteria: internal validity
and external validity. Internal validity refers to the degree to which one accurately measures the
true program impact in the study population. External validity refers to the degree to which the
ndings of a study can be generalized to populations not explicitly included in the study, whether
in the same or other geographical locations and cultural contexts. Proponents of randomized
experiments suggest that RCTs provide the highest degree of internal validity of any impact
estimation method (see Duo et al. 2008 for a detailed discussion of the RCTs, quasi-experimental
methods, and internal validity).
Under ideal conditions, randomization ensures that the treatment and control groups are iden-
tical on average with respect to both observable and unobservable characteristics. In contrast,
because all aspects of the treatment and control groups are not observable, quasi-experimental
methods cannot guarantee that the treatment and control groups are on average identical along both
observable and unobservable dimensions. Therefore, unlike RCTs, quasi-experimental methods
cannot ex ante eliminate selection bias and thus may yield estimates of program impact that are
biased by preexisting or fundamental dierences between the treatment and control groups.
Randomized control trials
419
Parsimony
Proponents of RCTs also argue that RCTs are more parsimonious than quasi-experimental
methods and thus are better suited to impact evaluation of public policy programs. They argue
that because RCTs are based on fewer (and more plausible) assumptions than quasi-experimental
methods and report average program impacts, they are more accessible to policy-makers who
may lack the technical training to interpret the results of quasi-experimental studies or discern
the quality of these results. Banerjee and Duo state:
most evaluations of social programs focus exclusively on the mean impact. In fact, one of
the advantages of experimental results is their simplicity: They are easy to interpret because
all you need to do is compare means, a fact that may encourage policy-makers to take the
results more seriously.
(2009: 169)
11
Under ideal conditions, RCTs are in fact based on fewer assumptions than quasi-experimental
methods. Unlike quasi-experimental methods, which rely upon untestable assumptions about
the independence of the treatment and important factors (individual or contextual) that may
inuence treatment outcomes in the treatment and control groups (i.e. the presence of selection
bias), RCTs rely on the apparently simple concept of randomization to address selection bias.
The arguments in support of RCTs are simple, intuitive, and powerful. This in part explains
why RCTs have received renewed attention from both the academic and policy communities.
Despite the compelling logic behind RCTs, there has been considerable debate regarding the
relative merits of RCTs. The following section provides an overview of the critiques commonly
levied against RCTs.
Critiques of RCTs
Critics of the RCT paradigm typically do not argue that quasi-experimental methods or other
modes of inquiry are theoretically better suited to answer questions related to causal inference than
RCTs. Rather the critiques take two primary forms. First, critics of the RCT paradigm assert
that due to a number of practical issues associated with implementing RCTs or any type of
program evaluation, the ideal conditions from which RCTs derive their relative strength rarely
hold. Critics therefore argue that despite the clear theoretical strengths of RCTs, they do not deserve
a special place in the hierarchy of program evaluation methods. This argument is not unique to
the application of RCTs to social and development policy. Discussing the relative merits of
RCTs in the medical eld, Kramer and Shapiro state, [t]he model of methodological rigor
represented by the RCT invites close scrutiny for any departures from the ideal (1984: 2744).
Second, critics assert that even if the ideal conditions for an RCT can be approximated or even
met in practice, RCTs are well suited to answer only a small subset of questions of potential
interest to policy-makers and scholars. This section rst considers common practical issues
associated with the implementation of RCTs and the challenges these issues raise for RCTs and
then turns to the scope of problems that RCTs are well suited to answer.
Practical considerations and departures from ideal conditions
In the face of budgetary, cultural, and political constraints, researchers face the challenge of ensuring
that the design and implementation of a program evaluation meet the conditions required for
Fuente and Whittington
420
their methods to yield accurate, reliable results. Thus, researchers must pay attention to any
ways the execution of their research design may deviate from the ideal in both anticipated and
unanticipated ways. Because RCTs share this challenge with other modes of inquiry, critics
claim that the practical diculties associated with implementing RCTs undermine their relative
strength over other methods used to identify causal eects. This sentiment is perhaps best
reected by Deaton who states that:
Conducting good RCTs is exacting and often expensive, so that problems often arise that
need to be dealt with by various econometric or statistical xes. There is nothing wrong
with such xes in principle but their application takes us out of the world of ideal
RCTs and back into the world of everyday econometrics and statistics. So that RCTs, although
frequently useful, carry no special exemption from the routine statistical and substantive
scrutiny that should be routinely applied to any empirical investigation.
(2010: 447)
There are a number of issues that can potentially compromise the internal validity of RCTs,
undermine their apparent simplicity, and limit their external validity. These include, but are not
limited to: randomization bias, substitution bias, and treatment compliance; practical diculties
associated with the randomization process; limitations on sample size; and selection issues.
12
Treatment Compliance, Substitution Bias, and Randomization Bias
For RCTs to provide unbiased estimates of the average treatment eects, the following three
conditions must hold: (1) individuals in the treatment group must comply with their assignment
(treatment compliance); (2) randomization cannot alter participants behavior (no randomization
bias); and (3) the control group must comply with their assignment (no substitution bias). Violations
of these assumptions complicate causal inference from randomized control trials.
13
Let us rst consider the issue of treatment compliance. While researchers clearly hope that
individuals assigned to the treatment group will comply with their assignmentnamely parti-
cipate in the program or accept the experimental treatmentthis cannot be taken for granted.
Returning to our PoU water technology example from the second section, consider a situation
in which a researcher is interested in identifying the impact of a PoU water lter on reducing
incidence of diarrhea among poor households. Ideally the researcher randomly assigns house-
holds in the study area to a treatment and a control group. The researcher then provides the
PoU water lter as well as a set of common user instructions to households in the treatment
group, and tracks the number of episodes of diarrhea in each household in both the treatment
and control groups over the duration of the study period.
There are numerous plausible reasons why households in the treatment group may not
comply with their assignment. First, some households may nd the PoU water lter incon-
venient to use and decide not to use the lter or use it only rarely, perhaps when guests visit the
house. Second, some households may not like the taste of the ltered water and again decide
not to use the lter. Third, some of the households who like the taste of the ltered water and
nd it easy or acceptable to use, may simply not operate the lter correctly and thus continue to
drink water that is eectively untreated.
14
In each of the above examples, households will not be in compliance with their assignment
to the treatment group and unadjusted estimates of program impact will be biased. Thus
researchers must adjust their estimates using various statistical techniques to obtain unbiased
estimates of the program outcome. Here, researchers can no longer estimate the average
Randomized control trials
421
treatment eect, but must estimate intent to treat (ITT), treatment on treated (TOT), and local
average treatment e ects (LATE). As noted by Deaton (2010) above, in principle there is nothing
wrong with using econometric techniques to correct such biases. However, when there is
noncompliance among the treatment group, the experiment deviates from the ideal conditions
from which RCTs derive their comparative strength.
Similarly, in order to obtain unbiased estimates of average treatment eects in an RCT, the
process of randomization cannot, in theory, aect the behavior of individuals in the treatment
and control groups (randomization bias). With respect to the treatment and control groups, this
refers to the well-known threats of Hawthorne and John Henry eects,
15
respectively. Medical
trials seek to eliminate the possibility of randomization bias through a double blind process
where neither the researcher nor participants know their treatment status (Deaton 2010). How-
ever, this is often not possible in the context of policy-relevant RCTs or social experiments.
Referring to Fischers (1935) seminal presentation of the randomized experimental design in
agricultural productivity research, Heckman (1992) quips that while plots of land do not respond
to their treatment status, people do (quoted in Deaton 2010). In our hypothetical PoU water
lter experiment, households who have consented to participate in the experiment will clearly
know whether or not they have received a water lter.
16
Closely related to John Henry eects, substitution bias presents a threat to the internal
validity of RCTs. Substitution bias occurs when individuals assigned to the control group seek
close or exact substitutes for the intervention delivered in the experiment to the treatment
group. In the PoU example, households assigned to the control group may suspect that because
some households are receiving PoU water lters, their water must be dirty. This may prompt
some households in the control group to either purchase some form of water purication tech-
nology or begin to boil their water. If this occurs, the control group no longer reects the
counterfactual situation required for causal inference. As with noncompliance among households
in the treatment group, substitute-seeking behavior by households in the control group will bias
estimates of a programs average treatment eects. In the case of noncompliance among the control
group, estimates of program eects will be biased downward (Heckman and Smith 1995).
Treatment compliance and randomization bias are well known to scholars and practitioners of
program evaluation, and there are widely accepted means of addressing these issues. For example,
in the presence of potential endogeniety caused by treatment noncompliance or randomization
bias, the researcher can use the randomized assignment as an instrumental variable for treatment
status in a regression to obtain an estimate of the Local Average Treatment Eect (LATE).
17
The estimate of the LATE provides a means of identifying a causal eect of a given treatment.
However, when participants do not comply with their treatment assignments or the process of
randomization inuences participants behavior, the experiment no longer complies with the ideal
conditions from which it derives its strong internal validity relative to other modes of program
evaluation. This presents challenges to both the parsimony and internal validity of RCTs. With
regard to parsimony, Heckman and Smith suggest, [i]n the presence of randomization bias, the
meaning of an experimental impact estimate would be just as dicult to interpret honestly in
front of a congressional committee as any non-experimental study (1995: 93).
Selection issues in RCTs
Researchers who seek to identify a causal relationship between a program and an observed out-
come must also be aware of the threat from selection issues. In theory, the randomization pro-
cess ensures that any bias between the treatment and control groups is averaged out. While this
is technically correct, the randomization process removes selection bias among the individuals
Fuente and Whittington
422
(households) who participate in the study. In order for the results of a RCT to be applicable to
the broader population from which the study sample was drawn, the sample must be reective
of the broader target population of an intervention. Researchers cannot assume a priori that the
sample of individuals who participate in a given study is representative of the broader target
population.
Standard research ethics dictate that researchers must obtain informed consent from participants
in a research study. Thus, it is plausible that some individuals in the broader target population
may not consent to participating in an RCT. In the PoU water lter example, some households
may be suspicious of a new technology or simply not want to be inconvenienced by repeated
visits from a research team. These households may not consent to participating in the study. If
this situation occurs, the researcher cannot guarantee that households that agree to participate in
the study are representative of the broader target population of interest.
18
Indeed, in the context
of medical trials, Kramer and Shapiro (1984) note that individuals are more likely to participate
in observational (quasi-experimental) studies than in RCTs (in Heckman and Smith 1995).
In general, the researcher can check whether participants are similar to the broader population
in terms of observable socioeconomic and demographic characteristics. However, the researcher
cannot rule out the possibility that the two populations dier systematically in unobservable
ways. This raises many of the same challenges for RCTs inherent in quasi-experimental research
methods.
This type of selection issue will not necessarily be a concern for all RCTs. For example, policies
or programs may target individuals who want to participate in a program. This type of intervention
relies explicitly on voluntary participation and is quite common for a wide range of social
policies. In these instances, an oversubscription research design, in which willing participants are
assigned to the control group by a random denial or postponement of treatment, can yield
unbiased estimates of the treatment eects on the target population of interestnamely those
who are inclined to participate in a given program or seek a given treatment.
There is a second type of selection eect that has received relatively less attention in the litera-
ture: selection among the partner organization(s) who implement RCTs. Heckman and Smith
(1995) provide a detailed discussion of this issue in the context of the Job Training Partnership
Act (JTPA) in the United States, where there was a 90 percent refusal rate among potential
implementing agencies who feared that randomizing service delivery would impact their per-
formance benchmarks (see also Allcott and Mullainanthan (2011) and Deaton (2010) for a dis-
cussion of selection issues among implementing partners). In the context of social or development
policy, researchers often work with a partner organization such as a nongovernmental organi-
zation (NGO) who will implement and administer the program or treatment under considera-
tion. Potential implementation partners face a range of incentives that will inuence whether or
not they agree to participate in an RCT.
Additionally, for obvious reasons researchers typically would like to partner with agencies or
organizations that are capable of delivering the program or treatment in a high quality manner
and closely following the research protocol. As a result, in developing country contexts researchers
often partner with prominent NGOs or government agencies under specic directive to parti-
cipate in the RCT. Clearly an NGO or government agency that values highly such academic
collaboration may not be representative of the broader population of agencies or organizations
who might be called upon to implement a particular program. Therefore, the researcher cannot
rule out the possibility that the estimated program impact is not related to particular characteristics
of the implementation partner or how the program was implemented.
Another concern is that sta of an NGO that can deliver the intervention eciently and
eectively are likely to believe strongly in the eectiveness of the treatment, and may
Randomized control trials
423
communicate this to participants. This type of implementation diers markedly from a double-
blind design and threatens the internal validity of an experiment. In a recent working paper, Allcott
and Mullainanthan (2011) show evidence of partner selection bias in two sets of well-regarded
RCTs, one set examining the response of residential energy use to information on household
consumption and one set exploring the impact of micronance in developing countries.
In some instances, selection eects among implementation partners may not threaten the
internal validity of estimates derived from RCTs. However, they do raise concerns about the
external validity of some experimental ndingsnamely whether or not researchers or policy-
makers could expect roughly the same result if the program was scaled from a pilot program
implemented by a competent partner to a broader program implemented by partners of varying
ability or quality (Deaton 2010; Rodrik 2008).
Heterogeneity: parsimony reconsidered
Critics of RCTs also question the ability of policy-makers to understand the relative merits of
experimental and quasi-experimental techniques. Heckman and Smith (1995) point out that a
criterion of simplicity or parsimony would argue for simple before-and-after research designs
(without randomization).
Critics of RCTs also claim that their proponents mistake apparent simplicity for real simplicity
(Heckman and Smith 1995; Deaton 2010). In theory RCTs are based on a relatively simple set
of assumptions. However, in practice, addressing the challenges associated with implementing
RCTs and developing robust estimates of program impact are both complex and technical.
As a result of this complexity, critics of RCTs claim that there is no a priori reason to believe
that the assumptions and techniques employed to estimate program impacts from experimental
studies are more plausible or less complex than those used in quasi-experimental studies.
The issues of treatment compliance and randomization bias discussed above provide examples
of how practical challenges associated with implementing RCTs can compromise the types of
inference one can draw from them. There two other important issues where this becomes
apparent: (1) basic heteroscedasticity in the error term in the regression used to estimate pro-
gram eects;
19
and (2) the use of baseline surveys and statistical controls to sharpen estimates of
program impact and reduce the required sample size.
Under ideal conditions, one can estimate the impact of the program intervention from
experimental data using the following simple model:
Y
i
¼ þ T
i
þ "
i
ð6Þ
Where Ti is a dummy variable that represents whether individual i was randomly assigned to the
treatment group, randomization ensures that essential assumptions of the Gauss-Markov theorem
are met, so one can develop an unbiased estimate of β by ordinary least squares (OLS). The para-
meter estimate of β is the program impact we seek to estimate (Duo et al. 2006; Deaton 2010).
Citing Fisher (1935), Deaton (2010) emphasizes that randomization plays two fundamental roles.
First, randomization ensures that the mechanism governing selection into the treatment group is
the same as the mechanism governing selection into the control group. This is what allows ran-
domization to eliminate selection bias. Second, randomization provides a probability law that
enables us to judge whether the dierence between the two groups is signicant (ibid. 442).
Thus, while randomization allows the researcher to obtain unbiased estimates of program impact
(the parameter estimate for β from equation 6) using OLS, this does not necessarily imply that
Fuente and Whittington
424
the parameter estimate is statistically signicant, namely that one would reject the null hypothesis
that there is no treatment eect (Ho: β = 0). This can only be established by statistical inference,
which requires one to calculate the standard error of the parameter estimate of β.
In order for OLS to yield correct standard errors for parameter estimates, one must assume
that the error term is homoscedasticthat each observation has equal variance for all factors not
explicitly included in the model. As Deaton (2010) suggests, there is no a priori reason to believe
that the treatment and control groups in the sample have equal variance or that the act of ran-
domization itself did not aect the variance of each group. Thus, in order to have condence
that the statistical inference from the OLS regression is correct, one must either invoke the
assumption of homoscedasticity or correct for heteroscedasticity. The latter can be accomplished
using standard econometric techniques. However, critics of the wholesale promotion of RCTs
claim that assuming homoscedasticity in the error term or correcting for heteroscedasticity using
econometric techniques compromises the claim that RCTs are based on more plausible
assumptions and are less technically complex than quasi-experimental methods.
Also, RCTs can require large sample sizes to obtain the statistical power needed to identify
program treatment eects at a level convincing to policy-makers. This can be expensive. To
reduce the required sample size and hence the cost of a RCT, researchers often conduct base-
line surveys to obtain covariates to include in the regression equation used to estimate program
treatment eects. The basic justication for this practice is that including covariates that are
unrelated to the treatment but related to the outcome variable reduces the standard errors of the
parameter estimates and thus reduces the required sample size (Deaton 2010; Duo et al. 2008).
The general form of the resulting regression equation is:
Y
i
¼ α þ β1T
i
þ γX
ij
þ υ
i
þ ω
ij
ð7Þ
where X
ij
is a vector of individual and/or group control variables over individuals i and groups
j, γ is a vector of parameters associated with X
ij
, and υ
i
+ω
ij
represents the compound error term
after controlling for X
ij
.
Conducting baseline surveys and including covariates in the regression used to estimate average
treatment eects raises two issues that complicate RCTs claim to parsimony. First, covariates must
be specied ex ante. Otherwise, including covariates in the regression equation opens up the
possibility of searching for a good specication after the RCT is implemented (Deaton, 2010;
Duo et al. 2008). This raises similar concerns as post-trial subgroup analysis.
20
Second, when treat-
ment eects are heterogeneous across the study population, including covariates in the regression
equation will yield consistent, but not unbiased, parameter estimates of the average treatment
eect (Deaton 2010).
21
Biased yet consistent parameter estimates are typically not a concern in large
samples. However, as Deaton notes, in small samples the bias may be substantial (ibid.: 444).
Scope of questions RCTs are well suited to answer
Up to this point in the chapter, we have discussed the basic rationale for RCTs, the core
arguments advanced by proponents of RCTs, and the various ways in which RCTs can deviate
from ideal conditions in practice. Each of these topics, while important, examines RCTs on
their own turf, that is in problem contexts that are conceivably well suited to them. As Imbens
notes conditional on the question, the methodological case for randomized experiments seems
unassailable (2010: 14). We now directly consider the scope of policy questions RCTs are well
suited to answer. This issue is well recognized in the program evaluation literature, but has
Randomized control trials
425
received relatively little attention in the current debate about the relative merits of RCTs or
from policy analysts.
Even the most ardent advocates of RCTs acknowledge that experimental methods can be
used to answer only a small subset of potentially important policy questions. Banerjee and Duo
state that, we [must] not forget that there are a lot of important questions that randomized experi-
ments cannot answer (2009: 152). Critics of RCTs have decidedly stronger feelings about the
value of RCTs in scholarly and policy discourse. Indeed Heckman and Smith state that experi-
mental data provide no answers to many of the questions of interest to program evaluators
(1995: 86). Similarly, Deaton argues:
[t]he price for [the success of RCTs] is a focus that is too narrow to tell us what works in
development, to design policy, or to advance scientic knowledge about development
processes. Project evaluation using randomized controlled trials is unlikely to discover the
elusive keys to development, nor to be the basis for a cumulative research program that
might progressively lead to a better understanding of development.
(2010: 3)
Policymakers and policy analysts need a clear, nuanced understanding of the scope of questions
that RCTs are well suited to answer and the types of questions they cannot address. We highlight
below a number of considerations about the type of questions RCTs can address.
Average impact vs. distributional concerns
Policymakers are usually interested in the distribution of outcomes across the target population.
Distributional impacts that might be of interest to policy-makers include but are surely not
limited to: outcomes by income decile, percent of participants who experienced positive program
outcomes, the median (rather than mean) program impact, and so on.
22
In many circumstances,
a policymaker would not want to implement a program that bestowed large benets on a small
subset of the population while inicting harm on the rest of the population. However, without
additional assumptions, statistical adjustments, or a research design specically targeted toward
identifying program impacts on dierent groups, RCTs typically cannot provide insight into the
distributional impacts of a policy or program (Heckman and Smith 1995; Heckman and Vytlacil
2001; Heckman 2010; Deaton 2010; and Rodrik 2008).
Causal mechanisms: why and how vs. whether and how much
Under the most favorable conditions RCTs provide an accurate, reliable means of identifying
the causal eect of a policy or program. RCTs can identify whether or not a program works
(has positive outcomes for program participants) and provide an estimate of the magnitude of
the treatment eect (how much). However, RCTs do not provide insight into how or why a
program works. That is, RCTs do not provide insight into the causal mechanisms that drive
program outcomes among a certain population.
23
This is particularly problematic for Deaton
who states:
RCTs of what works, even when done without error or contamination, are unlikely to be
helpful for policy, or to move beyond the local, unless they tell us something about why
the program worked, something to which they are often neither targeted nor well-suited.
(2010: 448).
Fuente and Whittington
426
Policy-makers need to understand why a program works in a specic context or location in order
to assess whether it is likely to work elsewhere.
24
In other words, they need some assurance of
not only a programs internal validity, but also its external validity.
Similarly, RCTs do not provide information on why individuals might choose to participate
in a particular program or accept a particular treatment. For programs that rely upon voluntary
participation, policy-makers need to understand the factors that inuence individuals decisions
about whether or not to opt into a voluntary program or use a particular technology. For example,
in our example of a PoU water lter, policy-makers or donors may want insight into why
households might agree, or continue, to use PoU water lters or be willing to pay for them.
25
RCTs cannot provide this information. However, these perspectives are essential for policy-
makers or donors to assess whether or not a program to market or distribute water lters is likely to
be eective in a particular context and, perhaps more importantly, identify ways in which they
can increase the uptake and usage of the lter.
RCTs are only well suited to interventions that can be randomized
Policy researchers can only use RCTs if the interventions of interest can be randomized. There
are a number of types of development programs that are amenable to randomization. Examples
include insecticide-treated bed nets, point-of-use water lters, improved cookstoves, nancial
products among micronance customers, and so on. However, many types of policy interven-
tions cannot be eectively randomized for practical or ethical reasons. Indeed Banerjee states,
there are times when randomized experiments are simply not feasible, such as in the case of
exchange rate policy or central bank independence: it clearly makes no sense to assign countries
exchange rates at random as you might assign them ip charts (2006: 8).
Let us again consider PoU water lters and their impact on diarrheal disease reduction. As a
practical matter, researchers may be able to randomize the distribution of PoU water lters to
communities and particular households within communities. Indeed, a researcher could dis-
tribute multiple types of PoU lters randomly among sample households to determine which
type of lter is more eective in reducing the episodes of diarrhea per household per month in
the study population. However, what if the researcher were interested in determining the
eectiveness of large dams on economic growth? It is impossible to imagine a situation in which
randomizing such large-scale infrastructure projects would be politically feasible or ethically
appropriate.
This raises a broader issue. If RCTs are the gold standard for causal identication, how does a
researcher or policy-maker compare two interventions when one intervention is relatively easy
to randomize (e.g. PoU water lters) and another is much more dicult (e.g. piped and sewerage
networks)? From a policy perspective it would not make sense to limit the policy choice set to
interventions than can be randomized. However, it is not immediately clear on what basis one
can compare two interventions if the eectiveness of the interventions cannot be determined by
comparable or epistemologically acceptable methods.
Value in rening a single parameter
RCTs can provide insight into the eectiveness of a particular intervention, i.e. whether or not
an intervention works and to what degree. However, this is only one of numerous pieces of
information a researcher needs to know to conduct meaningful policy analysis. For example,
suppose a researcher was interested in conducting a benet cost analysis of competing health
interventions, including PoU water lters (e.g. Whittington et al. 2009 and Jeuland and
Randomized control trials
427
Whittington 2009). The researcher would need to calculate the economic value of the reduc-
tions in mortality and morbidity associated with the use of the water lter. To estimate the
economic benets of mortality reduction associated with a reduction in diarrheal disease due
to the use of the PoU water lter the researcher could use the following equation from
Whittington et al. (2012):
Mortality Benefits ¼ Pop
I
Eff
CFR
VSL ð8Þ
Where Pop is the number of individuals in the target population, I is the incidence of diarrheal
disease in the target population, E is the eectiveness of the PoU lter in reducing diarrheal
disease, CFR is the case fatality rate for diarrheal disease in the target population, and VSL is the
value of statistical life in the target population. Often little is known about the exact values of
the following parameters for a given study location: I, E, CFR, and VSL. RCTs can provide
insight into the eectiveness of PoU lters (E). However, in many instances researchers know
the most about the eectiveness of a given intervention. They are far less certain about the
values of I, CFR, and the VSL for the study population (Whittington et al. 2012). Because the
mortality benets are the product of the ve parameters, the uncertainty about parameter values
(or error) is multiplicative. Thus, there is limited value in spending time and resources rening a
single parameter valuee.g. eectivenesswhen the values of the other parameters are less
well known or highly uncertain.
Categories of policy questions RCTs are well suited to answer
Despite that fact that RCTs can provide strong internal validity for the identication of the
causal eects of an intervention, they do not provide researchers information required to answer
a number of questions of potential interest to policy-makers. Heckman (2010) provides a useful
framework for thinking about the types of questions to which RCTs are well suited. Heckman
(ibid.) states that there are three types of policy questions in which policy-makers might be inter-
ested. First, policy-makers might want to evaluate the impact of interventions that have been or
will be implemented. Typically these types of interventions represent an incremental, or marginal,
change from existing policies. Second, policy-makers might be interested in predicting the impacts
of an intervention originally implemented in one context in another context.
26
Third, policy-
makers might be interested in predicting the impact of an intervention that has never been
experienced. This refers to policies that do not represent an incremental change from an existing
policy context, e.g. interventions to mitigate climate change.
In general, RCTs are well suited to answer the rst type of policy questioni.e. where the
intervention has been implemented or represents an incremental change from the existing policy
context. RCTs may also be useful in helping to predict the impact of policies implemented in
one context where such a policy has not been implemented in the past. However, because RCTs
do not prima facie have strong external validity, they do not have a comparative advantage over
other methods with respect to their ability to answer this type of policy question (Heckman
2010). Similarly, RCTs do not provide information that can help predict the consequences of
policies that that never been experienced.
We would add a fourth type of policy situation where RCTs provided limited value or
insucient information. RCTs do not provide insight into whether an intervention should be
implemented in a given context nor how to choose between multiple interventions that work.
This is well reected in Das et al. who state:
Fuente and Whittington
428
[R]andomized control trials typically tell you what would happen if you were to intervene.
For instance, what would happen if the government were to provide free access to water.
[sic] Randomized control trials do not tell you whether you should intervene.
(2011)
Whether or not to implement a particular policy or program is a normative question that is
typically addressed through the lens of welfare economics and benet-cost analysis. Evidence
from RCTs can certainly contribute to such analysis but is not a substitute for it.
Summary and conclusions
Faced with very real monetary, political, and temporal constraints, researchers and policy-makers
should have a clear sense of the types of questions to which RCTs are well suited. In this
chapter, we discuss a set of fairly simple questions that policy professionals can use as a guide to
determine whether or not RCTs are well suited to their own research question or policy problem.
First, policy professionals must ask the basic question of whether they are interested in iden-
tifying the causal impact of a policy or program and estimating the magnitude of this impact. If
not, RCTs will not be of use to them. If so, RCTs may provide a useful means of obtaining
this information. Whether or not this is the case will depend on a number of other factors,
which are addressed in the questions that follow.
Second, policy professionals must ask whether or not they are interested in identifying why
or how a program works, namely the causal mechanism behind program outcomes. Under-
standing why or how a program works can provide policy professionals with a sense of whether
or not a policy or intervention is likely to work in a population or setting that diers from the
particular context of the study. Guided by theory, RCTs can be designed to explore competing
hypotheses about causal mechanisms. However, they cannot provide this information without
an explicit research design to do so and do not necessarily have a comparative advantage over
other modes of social inquiry in this regard.
Third, the policy professional must ask whether or not the policy or intervention of interest
can be randomized. As a practical matter only certain types of policies or interventions can be
randomized. Recalling our water treatment example, it may be possible to randomize the distribu-
tion of PoU water lters but it is hard to imagine a situation where one could randomize the
provision of large water resources infrastructure such as dams. Similar concerns arise for large reg-
ulatory initiatives designed to improve environmental quality (e.g. air quality). This highlights
two important points. First, RCTs can only be used to evaluate interventions or policies that can
be randomized. Second, policy professionals must think carefully about whether and to what
degree their choice of research methodology constrains their policy or intervention choice set.
Fourth, the policy professional must determine when they need the information. To conduct
an RCT, a researcher must identify a partner organizationtypically an NGO or less often a
government departmentor build the programmatic infrastructure needed to deliver the inter-
vention of interest. This can take a considerable amount of time. More importantly, the potential
impacts of a social or environmental intervention are often not immediate. Thus, even if the
researcher has an implementation partner, the results of the RCT may not be available for
numerous years. If a policy professional needs information on program impacts immediately,
RCTs will be of limited use. Fifth, policy-makers must consider whether the randomization for
the treatment is ethically sound and political feasible.
This chapter discuses the traditional motivation for RCTs and provides policy professionals
with a more nuanced sense of the commonly cited strengths of RCTs as well as their limitations.
Randomized control trials
429
We devoted substantial attention to the limitations of RCTs and how the practical diculties
associated with implementing them can cause RCTs to deviate from the ideal conditions from
which they draw their relative strength. We have done this not to advocate other modes of
program evaluation over RCTs, but to provide policy professionals with a richer sense of factors
that can complicate the ability of RCTs to provide internally valid estimates of program impact.
Perhaps more importantly, this chapter encourages policy professionals to view RCTs in the
broader context of the types of research that can inform public policy. Much of the current
debate about RCTs implicitly assumes that policy professionals seek to identify a causal eect of
a policy intervention or program. While this is certainly an important goal for policy research, it
is not the only one. There are numerous other important questions that public policy research
must answer, including whether or not a particular policy or program should be implemented.
Acknowledgments
We would like to express our appreciation to Dr. Juan Robalino, Director of the Latin Amer-
ican and Caribbean Environmental Economics Program, for his comments and suggestions on a
previous draft.
Notes
1 http://www.povertyactionlab.org/
2 http://www.poverty-action.org/
3 The arguments in favor of RCTs are best reected in Banerjee (2005), Banerjee and Duo (2009),
Duo (2004), Duo et al. (2008), and Angrist and Pischke (2010).
4 Readers interested in a review of the recent books by Banerjee and Duo (2011) and Karlan and
Appel (2011) should refer to Harrison (2011). The full discussion in the Boston Review can be found at:
http://www.bostonreview.net/BR36.2/ndf_behavioral_economics_global_development.php
5 See Handa and Maluccio (2010) for a more recent comparison between experimental and quasi-
experimental methods in the context of PROGRESSA.
6 A number of authors, including Duo et al. (2008), Deaton (2010), and Heckman and Smith (1995)
present similar discussions of causal inference in randomized control trials. We follow the notation in
Duo et al. (2008). Interested readers should refer to Morgan and Winship (2007) for a more detailed
overview of the potential outcomes framework.
7 For nontechnical readers the expectation operator E[ ] can be thought of as a simple mean.
8 This is often referred to as omitted variable bias in the econometrics literature.
9 In other words, it is not clear that: E[Y
i
T|T]- E[Y
i
C|C] = E[Y
i
T-Y
i
C|T] = E[Y
i
T-Y
i
C]. To arrive at
this general conclusion, one must invoke the Stable Unit Treatment Value Assumption developed in
Angrist et al. (1996) (see Duo et al. 2008), which states that the potential outcomes of an individual
are unrelated to the treatment status of any other individual (p. 8). Interested readers should refer to
Morgan and Winship (2007) for a more detailed discussion of the Stable Unit Treatment Value
Assumption.
10 Cartwright (2010) calls into question whether any research method can be considered the gold standard
at all.
11 It is important to note that comparing means is one identication strategy, which one could use with
both observational and experimental data. One could also use a dierence in dierence identication
strategy with RCT data.
12 Readers interested in a more in-depth discussion of these as well as other issues associated with the
implementation of RCTs should refer to Deaton (2010), Rodrik (2008), Heckman and Smith (1995),
Heckman (2010), Imbens and Wooldridge (2009), Imbens (2010), and Duo et al. (2008).
13 If conditions 1 and 3 are violated by the majority of study participants, the study cannot be considered an
RCT at all. However, minor deviations from conditions 1 and 3 are often experienced in real-life eld
situations. It is a matter of judgment as to how severe the violations need to be before one concluded
that the implementation of an RCT protocol failed.
Fuente and Whittington
430
14 These issues are well recognized by scholars who work on this issue. As a result, they pay considerable
attention to obtaining objective assessments of whether or not households are using the water lter, e.g.
conducting tests for residual chlorine in stored water.
15 Hawthorne and John Henry eects threaten the internal validity of social experiments. Hawthorne
eects refer to the fact that the act of participating in a study, or knowledge of being studied, often
inuences the behavior of individuals in the treatment group. (See Gillespie (1991) for a history of the
term Hawthorne eect.) For example, an individual who has been randomly assigned to the treat-
ment group in the hypothetical PoU water experiment scenario may feel fortunate to have been
selected to participate in the program and may wash their hands more often to ensure that they obtain
the maximum benet from the lter. Alternatively, the individual might engage in improved hygiene
practices to give the study team a good impression of them. In these instances, the treatment eect
measured by researchers would include the co-benets of hand washing and the PoU lter, not simply
the PoU lter. Conversely, John Henry eects refer to a situation in which individuals in the control
group change their behavior in response to the experiment or their treatment assignment (Zdep and
Irvine 1970).
16 Note that this would also be an issue with a quasi-experimental research design.
17 For a detailed discussion of LATE see Imbens and Angrist (1994), Heckman (1996), Heckman (1999),
Urzua and Heckman (2009), and Imbens (2010).
18 Recall that randomization addresses selection bias by ensuring that the treatment and control groups
are similar on average along both observable and unobservable dimensions. In this situation, even if the
researcher can conrm that treatment and control groups are similar in observable ways, she cannot
rule out the possibility that those who agree to participate in the study are dierent from those who refuse
to participate in unobservable ways.
19 This issue will also be present in quasi-experimental studies and thus should not be interpreted as a
problem with RCTs relative to other modes of research design. We raise the issue here simply to highlight
a level of complexity that is typically overlooked in discussion about RCTs.
20 Recognizing the threat to the internal validity, proponents of RCTs have openly supported calls for a
RCT registry where experiments would be registered ex ante along with proposed subgroups for analysis
and model specication.
21 See Deaton (2010) for a summary of this issue and Freedman (2008) for a more detailed treatment.
22 See Deaton (2010) for an overview of distributional program impacts and Heckman and Smith (1995)
for a more extensive treatment of this issue.
23 Contrary to the common complaint that RCTs are atheoretical (e.g. Bardhan 2005; Basu 2005; Moo-
kherjee 2005) well-designed RCTs can be used to test hypotheses about competing causal mechanisms.
Deaton (2010) holds up Duo et al. (2009), Bertrand et al. (2010), Giné et al. (2010), and Karlan and
Zinman (2008) as exemplary uses of RCTs to advance economic theory.
24 Pawson and Tilley (1997) present an interesting call for what they term realistic evaluation that
explicitly examines the interaction between context and mechanisms in program outcomes.
25 See Whittington et al. (2012) for a discussion of how uptake and usage can aect the economic
attractiveness of a variety of interventions.
26 This is referred to as benet transfer in the environmental economics literature.
Bibliography
Ahuja, A., M. Kremer and A.P. Zwane. 2010. Providing safe water: Evidence from randomized evaluations,
unpublished working paper. Available at: http://www.economics.harvard.edu/faculty/kremer/les/
ARRE_CLEAN_2010_04_14.pdf
Allcott, H. and S. Mullainanthan. 2011. External validity and partner selection, unpublished working paper.
Angrist, J. and J.S. Pischke. 2010. The credibility revolution in empirical economics: How better research
design is taking the con out of econometrics, Journal of Economic Perspectives 24(2): 330.
——, G. W. Imbens, and D.B. Rubin. 1996. Identication of causal eects using instrumental variables,
Journal of the American Statistical Association 91(434): 44455.
Banerjee, A.V. 2005. ‘“New development economics and the challenge to theory, Economic and Political
Weekly: 43404.
—— 2006. Making aid work: how to ght global poverty eectively, Boston Review 31(4): 79.
—— 2007. Making Aid Work. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Randomized control trials
431
——and E. Duo. 2009. The experimental approach to development economics, Annual Review of Economics
1: 15178.
——and E. Duo. 2011. Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty. Cambridge,
MA: Public Aairs.
——,E.Duo, R. Glennerster and C. Kinnan. 2010. The miracle of micronance? Evidence from a
randomized evaluation, J-PAL Working Paper.
Bardhan, P. 2005. Theory or empirics in development economics, Economic and Political Weekly 40(40):
43335.
Basu, K. 2005. New empirical development economics: Remarks on its philosophical foundations, Economic
and Political Weekly 40(40): 43369.
Bertrand, M., D. Karlan, S. Mullainathan, E. Shar and J. Zinman. 2010. Whats advertising content
worth? Evidence from a consumer credit marketing eld experiment, The Quarterly Journal of Economics
125(1): 263.
Bloom, H., L. Orr, G. Cave, S. Bell and F. Doolittle. 1993. The National JTPA Study: Title IIA Impacts on
Earnings and Employment at 18 Months, Bethesda, MD: Abt Associates.
Cartwright, N. 2010. What are randomized trials good for?, Philosophical Studies 147(1), 5970.
Das, J., D. Shantayana and S. Hammer. 2011. Lost in translation, Boston Review. Available at: http://
www.bostonreview.net/BR36.2/devarajan_das_hammer_behavioral_economics_global_development.php
Deaton, A. 2010. Instruments, randomization, and learning about development. Journal of Economic Literature
48(2): 42455.
Doolittle, F. and L. Traeger. 1990. Implementing the National JTPA Study. New York: Manpower
Demonstration Research Corporation.
Duo,
E. 2004. Scaling up
evaluation, Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics.
——, Pascaline Dupas, Michael Kremer, and Samuel Sinei. 2006. Education and HIV/AIDS prevention:
Evidence from a randomized evaluation in western Kenya, working paper, MIT.
——, R. Glennerster and M. Kremer. 2008. Using randomization in development economics research: A
toolkit, Handbook of Development Economics 4: 3895962.
——, M. Greenstone and R. Hanna. 2008. Cooking stoves, indoor air pollution and respiratory health in
rural Orissa, Economic and Political Weekly 43(2): 716. Available at: http://web.mit.edu/ceepr/www/
publications/reprints/Reprint_205_WC.pdf
——, M. Kremer and J. Robinson. 2009. Nudging farmers to use fertilizer: Evidence from Kenya,
NBER Working Paper, 15131.
Fisher, Ronald A. 1935 (1960). The Design of Experiments. 8th edn. New York: Hafner.
Freedman, D.A. 2008. On regression adjustments to experimental data, Advances in Applied Mathematics 40
(2): 18093.
Gillespie, Richard. 1991. Manufacturing Knowledge: A History of the Hawthorne Experiments. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Giné, X., T. Harigaya (IPA), D.S. Karlan and B. Nguyen. 2006. Evaluating micronance program innova-
tion with randomized control trials: an example from group versus individual lending, Asian Development
Bank Economics and Research Department Technical Note Series 16.
——, D. Karlan and J. Zinman. 2010. Put your money where your butt is: A commitment contract for
smoking cessation, American Economic Journal: Applied Economics 2(4): 21335.
Glennerster, R. and M. Kremer. 2011. Small changes, big results, Boston Review. Available at: http://
bostonreview.net/BR36.2/ndf_behavioral_economics_global_development.php
Handa, S. and J. Maluccio. 2010. Matching the gold standard: comparing experimental and non-experimental
evaluation techniques for a geographically targeted program, Economic Development and Cultural Change
58(3): 41547.
Harrison, G.W. 2011. Randomization
and its discontents, Journal
of African Economies 20(4): 62652.
Heckman, J.J. 1992. Randomization and social policy evaluation, in C.F. Manski and I. Garnkel (eds)
Evaluating Welfare and Training Programs. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 20130.
—— 1996. Randomization as an instrumental variable, The Review of Economics and Statistics 78(2): 33641.
—— 1999. Instrumental variables: response to Angrist and Imbens, The Journal of Human Resources 34(4):
82837.
—— 2010. Building bridges between structural and program evaluation approaches to evaluating policy,
Journal of Economic Literature 48(2): 35698.
——and J.A. Smith. 1995. Assessing the case for social experiments, The Journal of Economic Perspectives
9(2): 85110.
Fuente and Whittington
432
——and E. Vytlacil. 2001. Policy-relevant treatment eects , American Economic Review 91(2): 10711.
Imbens, G.W. 2010. Better LATE than nothing: Some comments on Deaton (2009) and Heckman and
Urzua (2009), Journal of Economic Literature 48(2): 399423.
——and J.D. Angrist. 1994. Identication and estimation of local average treatment eects, Econometrica
62(2): 46775.
——and J.M. Wooldridge. 2009. Recent developments in the econometrics of program evaluation,
Journal of Economic Literature 47(1): 586.
Jeuland, M. and D. Whittington. 2009. Cost-benet comparisons of investments in improved water
supply and cholera vaccination programs, Vaccine 27(23): 310920.
Kanbur, R. 2005. Goldilocks development economics: Not too theoretical, not too empirical, but watch
out for the bears!, Economic and Political Weekly 40(40): 43446.
Karlan, D.S. and J. Zinman. 2008. Credit elasticities in less-developed economies: Implications for
micronance, The American Economic Review 98(3): 104068.
——and J. Appel. 2011. More than Good Intentions: How a New Economics Is Helping to Solve Global Poverty.
New York: Penguin.
Keane, M.P. 2010. A structural perspective on the experimentalist school, The Journal of Economic Perspectives
24(2): 4758.
Kramer, M.S. and S.H. Shapiro. 1984. Scientic challenges in the application of randomized trials,
JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association 252(19):
273945.
Kremer, M. 2003. Randomized
evaluations of educational programs in developing countries: Some lessons ,
The American Economic Review 93(2): 1026.
——, E. Miguel, S. Mullainathan, C. Null and Alix Peterson Zwane. 2009. Making water safe: price,
persuasion, peers, promoters, or product design?, unpublished working paper. Available at: http://ase.tufts.
edu/econ/events/neudcDocs/SaturdaySession/Session17/MKremerMakingWaterSafePricePersuasion.pdf
LaLonde, R.J. 1986. Evaluating the econometric evaluations of training programs with experimental data,
The American Economic Review 76(4): 60420.
Miguel, E. and M. Kremer. 2004. Worms: Identifying impacts on education and health in the presence of
treatment externalities, Econometrica 72(1): 159217.
Mookherjee, D. 2005. Is there too little theory in development economics today?, Economic and Political
Weekly 40(40): 432833.
Morgan, S.L. and C. Winship. 2007. Counterfactuals and Causal Inference: Methods and Principles for Social
Research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pawson, R. and N. Tilley. 1997. Realistic Evaluation, illustrated, reprint edn. London: Sage.
Rodrik, D. 2008. The new development economics: We shall experiment, but how shall we learn?
Faculty Research Working Papers Series, RWP08055.
Todd, P.E., and K.I. Wolpin. 2006. Assessing the impact of a school subsidy program in Mexico: Using a
social experiment to validate a dynamic behavioral model of child schooling and fertility, The American
Economic Review 96(5): 1384417.
Urzua, S. and J.J. Heckman. 2009. Comparing IV with structural models: What simple IV can and cannot
identify, NBER Working Paper 14706.
Whittington, D., W.M. Hanemann, C. Sado and M. Jeuland. 2009. The challenge of improving water and
sanitation services in less developed countries, Foundations and Trends in Microeconomics 4(67), 469609.
——, M. Jeuland, K. Barker and Y. Yuen. 2012. Setting priorities, targeting subsidies among water,
sanitation, and health interventions in developing countries, World
Development (under review).
Zdep, S.M.
and S.H. Irvine.1970. A reverse Hawthorne eect in educational evaluation, Journal of School
Psychology 8: 8995.
Randomized control trials
433
32
Policy evaluation and
public participation
Carolyn M. Hendriks
Introduction
This chapter is concerned with the methods and challenges of evaluating policies through the
participation of aected publics. For this purpose, policy evaluation is understood as an act of
judgment about the performance of a particular policy process, department or program based on
its desirability, worth, or value. Evaluation is the phase of the policy process where there is
ideally an explicit opportunity for learning, reection and improvement. It represents the moment
where the policy cycle ends but also restarts (Althaus et al. 2007). For the most part, this chapter
focuses on policy evaluation as a retrospective (ex post) exercise where past decisions and pro-
grams are formally assessed. Evaluations of this kind might be legally required, or they might be
stimulated by a budget or planning process. In some cases evaluations are triggered by
specic policy events, such as a perceived policy asco or change in political leadership (Bovens
et al. 2006).
The dominant approach to policy evaluation has been inspired by a rationalistic or traditional
model of policy analysis (Bovens et al. 2006). Evaluation of this kind typically sets out to
determine the facts at hand using predetermined evaluation criteria, and attempts to keep values
and ultimately politics out of the equation. In other words, the goal is to assess whether a
program or policy achieved its set objectives (is it eective?), whether it is the best way to achieve
these objectives (is it ecient?) and whether the policy or program is relevant under current
conditions (is it appropriate?) (Althaus et al. 2007). Formal evaluations of this kind often proceed
with an independent body (for example, an audit oce, an ombudsman, a consultant and so on)
establishing the scope of the evaluation, determining the assessment criteria (for example, cost-
eectiveness), then collecting relevant data (often focused on the operation and implementation
of the policy or program), and nally making an objective assessment and recommendations.
The inherent assumption with this more traditional approach to policy evaluation is that the
criteria used are appropriate and measurable, and that the conclusions drawn will be denitive
and uncontroversial.
However, in practice, this kind of systematic and rational assessment of a policy program is
rare (Bovens et al. 2006; OFaircheallaigh 2002). Indeed, policy practice is littered with exam-
ples that demonstrate how policy evaluation is far from value neutral and apolitical. Dierent
434
policy actors will almost always hold competing views on what constitutes policy success and
failure, how it might be judged and what lessons the results imply. This makes evaluation an
inevitably controversial and indeed political process, one that often generates more conict and
contestation than any other stage of the policy process. Even the most low prole and seemingly
uncontroversial policy programs can become political battle grounds when an evaluation process
commences because it triggers a host of questions about how funding is allocated and spent,
who wins and loses, who is accountable and responsible, and it also opens up possibilities for
reframing debates (Bovens et al. 2006).
Given the inherent political nature of policy evaluation in contemporary societies, its practice
is best understood as a process that seeks to reect the plurality of perspectives on any given
policy or program. According to Majone (1989: 183) the imperative is thus less to develop
objective measures of outcomesthe traditional aim of evaluation researchthan to facilitate
a wide ranging dialogue among advocates of dierent criteria. In other words, the evaluative task
involves recognizing the multiplicity of criteria and perspectives on a given issue and helping to
contribute to a shared understanding of the various critical perspectives and of their dierent
functions in the process of public deliberation (1989: 170). This more participatory approach to
policy evaluation requires that policy analysts (such as independent evaluators and public man-
agers) elicit multiple perspectives. In practice, this involves going well beyond engaging diverse
experts and elites, or conducting a simple client satisfaction survey. Ideally participatory policy
evaluation involves engaging a diversity of actors that aect, and are aected by, a policy or program
in the process of evaluation.
The perspective oered in this chapter sits within this participatory or argumentative tradition
of policy evaluation. It views the assessment of any policy performance or program as something
shaped by the underlying assumptions and values of the evaluation process, and those interpreting
the evidence (Fischer and Forester 1993; Majone 1989). The argumentative approach to policy
evaluation takes seriously the role of values in shaping and determining the worth of a policy
program (Stewart 2009a). In other words, policy evaluation involves a process of judgment that
is inherently subjective; it is inuenced by numerous factors such as who is doing the evaluation,
the scope of evaluation, the evaluative criteria used, and the way material is interpreted.
Participation is not a particularly well-understood or articulated theme in the literature on
policy evaluation. This is despite the growing interest in, and practice with, more participatory
and deliberative forms of governing. One reason for this could be that participation is typically
framed as an activity that occurs at the front end of the policy process, for example during agenda-
setting, policy design, and occasionally in decision-making. Yet participation is playing an
expanding role in policy evaluation particularly with the push to create public value, and the
broader trend toward more participatory forms of governing.
In this chapter I consider ex post policy evaluation in light of various themes emerging from
the practice and theory of participatory governance. I focus particularly on how multiple per-
spectives might be brought into the policy evaluation process, and the challenges and politics of
doing so. Consideration is given to both conventional methods of public involvement in policy
evaluation such as citizens surveys and public hearings, as well as more inclusive and delib-
erative forms of citizen engagement. The chapter concludes by discussing some of the particular
challenges of engaging the public in retrospective policy evaluation.
The role of participation in policy evaluation
The idea of participation is not new in discussions on policy evaluation. Indeed, some scholars
have identied participation as a central part of the evaluation process. For example, Guba and
Policy evaluation and public participation
435
Lincoln (1989), view evaluation as a process of encouraging consensus among various stake-
holders. In their methodology (referred to as fourth generation evaluation), stakeholders engage
in a collaborative process, and are empowered to develop and negotiate joint recommendations.
Participation also features as a theme in the work of post-positivist scholars interested in expanding
the argumentative basis for policy analysis (Fischer 1995; Forester 1999; Hajer and Wagenaar
2003b; Majone 1989). Here the emphasis is on policy analysts not so much solving a parti-
cular problem or nding its truth, but in creating interactive settings where policy arguments
and evidence can be exposed to public deliberation. More recently, scholars have argued that
interactive or deliberative forms of policy analysis are essential for making practical judgments in
contexts where governance increasingly involves a complex networks of actors, deep-value plur-
alism and radical uncertainty (Hajer and Wagenaar 2003a). Participation thus becomes central to
the tasks of evaluating how policies work, and how they might be improved. As Hajer and
Wagenaar put it: Whatever knowledge we possess must be assessed for its relevance and usefulness
in interaction with the concrete situation at hand, and that this ongoing process of assessment
occurs in situations of intense social interaction (2003a: 24, emphasis in the original).
Some themes on participatory evaluation have also emerged from the eld of public man-
agement. The push here has been to bring more client focus to the monitoring and assess-
ment of service delivery through consumer involvement. Participation in this context is about
improving knowledge on client needs, increased transparency and improved accountability for
services (Goetz and Gaventa 2001). Some of these imperatives have been promoted under the
banner of certain managerial discourses, such as New Public Management (NPM), which empha-
sizes the importance of service providers satisfying the needs and desires of their clients and con-
sumers (much like customers in the private sector). NPM has promoted passive and one-way
forms of participation, such as satisfaction surveys, that encourage respondents to think as consumers
rather than as citizens (Howard 2010; Parkinson 2004)a theme I return to later.
Participation has also surfaced in recent academic and practitioner discussions on the impor-
tance of public value in public sector management. Public value is a concept that continues to
evolve (see Alford and OFlynn 2009; Jørgensen and Bozeman 2007) but in broad terms it refers to
what the public values (Benington 2009; Horner et al. 2006). The idea of public value emerged
in the US as a construct to help public managers make sense of their policy tasks and to encourage
them to be more responsive to their public constituents (Moore, 1995). The notion of public
value has gained interest in other Western democracies, such as the United Kingdom, where it
is seen as a kind of corrective response to the managerial discourse of NPM (Horner et al. 2006). In
contrast to NPM, the concept of public value does not conate the views and preferences of
consumers and citizens, and in doing so it encourages public managers to listen to the voices of
dierent publics. While some of the literature on public value celebrates public participation,
little detail is given on who should participate in the policy process and how.
Participation has also surfaced in recent discussions on performance management in the public
sector. Measuring the performance of a program, department, or government is an important
component of policy evaluationthough the roots of evaluation research and performance man-
agement are dierent (see Blalock 1999). Performance management is typically aimed at ensur-
ing that public agencies are doing their job in an ecient and productive manner. This is as much
about promoting public accountability as it is about ensuring that governments are eective
service deliverers. Typically performance measures are quantitative, for example, drawn from
budget data or from output measurements such as the units and standard of services provided
(Holzer and Kloby 2005b).
More recently, there has been a call to include citizens directly in the assessment and mea-
surement of government performance. Advocates argue that citizens can help to develop socially
Hendriks
436
relevant measures as well as provide assistance with data collection and service design (Callahan
2000; Ho 2005). Some go further and argue that citizen-led performance management can pro-
mote accountability, and strengthen democracy by fostering trust and social capital (Halachimi
and Holzer 2010). However, like discussions on public value, there has been limited discussion
on the practicalities and politics of engaging citizens in the policy process. This may change as
the practice of citizen engagement in performance management expands. Already in the United
States hundreds of performance projects have been conducted where citizens have been asked
for their feedback on services, or involved in developing performance measures. In most cases
participation appears to involve relatively non-interactive methods such as customer surveys (e.g.
Heikkila and Isett 2007; Holzer and Kloby 2005a, 2005b).
The discussion above reveals that the arguments for greater public participation in policy eva-
luation are mostly couched in epistemic terms. By engaging dierent publics in the evaluation
process, we gain access to new information, alternative knowledge, and values. While this may be
the case, this particular framing of public involvement bypasses a host of democratic and managerial
reasons why participation is becoming such a central theme in contemporary governance.
Broader drivers for public participation in policy
One of the most signicant drivers for participation in public policy is a desire to democratize
the policy process and public services. On one level this is coming from increased demands from
dierent publics to contribute to decisions, services, or policies that they use, fund or support.
Yet on another level there has been a push by some scholars and international bodies such as
the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) to address some of
the democratic decits in the policy process by giving communities the opportunity to partici-
pate in decisions that aect them (Dryzek 2000; Fung 2006b; OECD 2001). When commu-
nities are excluded from contributing to decision-making processes, they are left frustrated and
angry, and question the fairness and authority of the imposed decision (Renn et al. 1995). In
other words they may not accept the legitimacy of the decision, and consent to necessary beha-
vioral or funding changes (Parkinson 2006). Others point to a host of other moral reasons why
the public should have greater say in the policy process. For example, some argue that active citi-
zen involvement in public policy (especially over the long term) can promote more equitable
outcomes and address systemic inequalities in communities (Schneider and Ingram 1997). Par-
ticipation is also said to promote more transparent decision-making, and thereby improve trust
in public institutions and citizenship more broadly (Putnam 1993). These normative arguments
are all relevant to policy evaluation.
Participation has also become a key managerial and administrative theme for many govern-
ments around the world (see OECD 2009). At a minimum, participation may be a necessary
administrative requirement, for example, to fulll certain legal requirements, such as an Envir-
onmental Impact Statement. Alternatively, a participatory process might be conducted to help
prevent or resolve a con ict. For example, since the 1970s consultation exercises have been used
by governments as a means to prevent protest politics and restore trust in political institutions.
A related motive here is to use participation to help share the responsibility for policy outcomes
(including successes and failures) (Head 2007).
Public participation is increasingly advocated as a means to improve the managerial eciency,
service delivery and accountability of government agenciesas discussed above. There has also
been increased recognition that the task of governing is not something that governments do
aloneit requires working with multiple interdependent actors (Wanna, 2009). Participation
promises to improve the problem-solving capacity of governments and other organizations.
Policy evaluation and public participation
437
When dierent actors work together on problems, they have the opportunity to share knowledge
and resources, which can improve the eciency of public programs and services (Kickert et al.
1997; Kooiman 1993). Participatory and collaborative approaches also present decision-makers
with an alternative approach to dealing with the complexities and uncertainties of modern
policy issues (Koppenjan and Klijn 2004).
More ambitious managers and administrators might utilize public participation to catalyze
change, or to shift the nature of the debate. For example, they might turn to more deliberative
processes in order to expand discussion on a controversial policy issue beyond symbols and
narrow interests (e.g. Carson et al. 2002; Einsiedel et al. 2001; Niemeyer 2004).
1
Public adminis-
trators might also seek to overcome some of the limitations of conventional modes of com-
munity involvement (such as opinion polls and pressure group politics), by experimenting with
new participatory processes (Hendriks 2002; Reddel and Woolcock 2003).
Who participates in policy evaluation, and how?
It would be a mistake to interpret participatory policy evaluation as a process in which relevant
experts work together to reach a consensus on the eectivenes of a policy or program. What
this approach bypasses is the important democratic argument underlying participatory policy
evaluation; that the evaluative process (and its outcome) is legitimate to the extent that it
engages those who might be aected by the policy in a process of informed public deliberation
(Dryzek 2000).
One common way to include potentially aected populations in policy evaluation is to target
stakeholder groups (e.g. Guba and Lincoln 1989). This term is typically reserved for identi-
able groups or organizations that have expressed an interest in a policy issue, program, or
proposal. Stakeholders might also be entities that have useful knowledge or perspectives, or the
power and resources to block or promote policy change. Stakeholder engagement of this kind
carries many of the democratic dangers associated with interest group pluralismmost notably that
it tends to privilege institutionalized, well-organized and well-funded interests (Lowi 1969;
Olson 1965). In practice, stakeholder forms of participation tend to restrict debate to a select group
of elites and policy entrepreneurs (Curtain 2006; Hunold and Young 1998).
To address this mobilization bias, some scholars stress the importance of policy analysts lis-
tening to a diversity of voices including the under-represented and marginalized (Dryzek 2010;
Fischer 2000; Forester 1999). A similar idea is promoted by those working from the perspective
of public value who explicitly stress the need for broader public input beyond special interest
groups and experts. For example, Horner et al. (2006: 19) argue that the goal should be about
placing individuals as citizens centre stage of decision-making so that public resources best serve
the publics needs and not the self-interest of public managers, professionals or the interest of one
particular group of citizens. Other scholars have been motivated to make emerging forms of
network governance (which typically involve public, private, and nongovernment representatives)
more inclusive of everyday citizens (Bingham et al. 2005; Hendriks 2008).
Clearly for any given policy issue or program there is a variety of relevant communities and
groups. These publics will be constituted by the particular focus of the evaluation process, as is
the case with all participatory projects (Barnes et al., 2003). It can be useful to think about how
dierent categories of publics might be called upon to contribute to di erent stages of the
evaluation process. Such categories might include (adapted from Salter, 2007):
1 interest groups (including powerful and marginalized groups);
2 specic communities (particular socio-economic, user or disaected groups);
Hendriks
438
3 elite stakeholders (businesses, experts, think tanks, consultants);
4 broader public (lay public, users , taxpayers); and
5 government ocials and departments.
The question of how these various publics might practically engage in policy evaluation is less
straightforward. There is no shortage of participatory mechanisms available for engaging dier-
ent kinds of publics in policy issues (Fung 2006a; Gastil and Levine 2005; Roberts 2004; Smith
2009). Participatory methods are often categorized in terms of a ladder or spectrum of public
participation where mechanisms vary in purpose ranging from informing (for example, open days,
websites and education campaigns) through to feedback and consultation (for example, surveys,
focus groups, and public hearings), through to more interactive and collaborative processes (for
example, advisory committees, citizens juries and partnerships) (see Head 2007; IAP2 2007). In
practice, the most common approach to public involvement in policy evaluation is to invite feed-
back or comments from the public, for example through surveys, focus groups, submissions, and
public hearings. In most of these processes, participation is not particularly interactive and the
scope for broader public input is limited. In some cases participatory processes are attached to
more formal evaluation processes involving experts, such as advisory committees and inquiries
(see Marier: Chapter 30).
In the following sections, I discuss two traditional modes of eliciting public input that are par-
ticularly prevalent in policy evaluationsatisfaction surveys and public meetings. I then take a
brief look at some of the more innovative approaches to public involvement that emphasize
inclusion and public deliberation. To be clear, my purpose here is not to provide a comprehensive
survey of dierent participatory mechanisms, but rather to get a taste of their diversity, and
discuss some of the broader policy and political issues that their use in policy evaluation raises.
Citizen surveys
Citizen- or client-focused surveys constitute a common means to seek feedback on the performance
of policy program, department, or initiative. There are dierent varieties but the most common
format is a satisfaction survey that uses standard survey research methodology where participants
are selected using random sampling and contacted either by mail or phone. In some cases,
citizen satisfaction might be explored using more interactive methods such as focus groups.
Satisfaction surveys are not particularly new to public administration but their popularity has
increased since the 1990s with the greater focus on customer-centered service delivery (Osborne
and Gaebler 1992). In this sense, surveys are seen as a way for public managers to gain insight
into how to improve their services to better meet the needs of their clients and customers (Kelly
2005). Satisfaction surveys also sit well with the discourse on more evidence-based policy-
making because they produce evidence from a technique largely viewed as methodologically
rigorous (Howard 2010).
There has also been a trend toward using citizen surveys as a benchmarking tool to track how
citizens satisfaction levels with public services change over time. In this respect Canada s Citi-
zens First survey has become a particularly inuential model that has been replicated around the
world, providing public managers with data on program eectiveness and citizen demands.
2
Since 1998 Canadian governments have sought the opinions of thousands of citizens on public
services in biennial surveys (for a critical perspective, see Howard 2010).
Satisfaction surveys are an attractive and popular tool for bringing the public into policy
evaluation. They provide a quick barometer of users and their expectations of public services.
However, such surveys represent shallow forms of citizen input, and are a long way from the
Policy evaluation and public participation
439
kind of participatory or deliberative evaluation that some advocate (e.g. Majone 1989). A
central problem is that citizens are given a narrow and passive role as a consumer; it also not
always clear who these consumers are, and how to nd them (Howard 2010). Evaluation sur-
veys of this kind also focus respondents on questions about whether they are satised with a
particular service, but not about broader issues such as their expectations for what the public
service should do, how services should be delivered/provided and who should use them
(Horner et al. 2006).
The data from citizen surveys has often been used to inform education campaigns rather than as
a useful external measure of performance. So, for example, where citizens level of satisfaction
with a service is much lower than the objective administrative performance dataa common
response by public managers is to better inform citizens on quality of services (Kelly and Swindell
2002). More problematic is that satisfaction surveys assume that personal experience and
indeed self-interest is the sole determinant of a users evaluation of a service (Horner et al.,
2006, p. 20). As a result they can unintentionally encourage particular public sector reforms that
are focused on customer service delivery, such as the expansion of consumer choice and the
increasing use of private sector providers (Howard 2010).
Public meetings and hearings
Another prolic form of public involvement used in policy evaluation is the public meeting. In
a typical public meeting, citizens and aected groups are invited to an open gathering to pro-
vide feedback on a specic policy issue, project, or proposal. Usually participation is open to
anyone to attend, and the entire proceedings are ostensibly public”—though size typically limits
numbers (Snider 2003). Meetings vary in their formality, but the general structure involves a
public audience facing a panel of experts and ocials, who may deliver a formal or technical
presentation. Following this, most public meetings allow members of the public to stand up and
briey voice their opinion. Dialogue is typically discouraged both between citizens, as well as
between citizens and ocials (Adams 2004).
Some public meetings might be part of a formal policy evaluation process such as a public
inquiry. In such cases, public meetings that are legally required are referred to as public hearings.
In some countries such as Canada, public hearings are a regular part of formal public inquiries
(see Chapter 30). But as Salter (2007) points out hearings vary considerably depending on how
the public is constituted. Some public hearings call on stakeholder representatives to engage in a
process of interest negotiation, while others invite general members of the public to give personal
testimonies or oer community expertise.
Public meetings remain a popular and often mandated form of public involvement in many
Western democracies (Baker et al. 2005; McComas 2001; Snider 2003). Their practice is also
increasing in more authoritarian contexts such as China (Zhong and Mol 2008). A recent vari-
ety in the UK and Australia is the use of community cabinets where ministers visit dierent
locations in their jurisdictions to take questions from the community (Marsh et al. 2010; Reddel
and Woolcock 2003).
Despite their proli c use, public meetings do not enjoy a good reputation (Heberlein 1976;
Kathelene and Martin 1991). The primary criticism of public hearings is that citizens rarely inu-
ence policy decisions. They are often performed as a minimalist mode of participation where
the focus is on transferring information to citizens rather than consideration of input from the
public. In many cases, meetings are timed too late in the decision-making process where there is
little room to take citizens concerns or ideas into account. For this reason, public meetings are often
experienced as forums for community venting, or opportunities for proponents to announce
Hendriks
440
and defend policies (King et al. 1998: 322). Some argue that public meetings are hollow democratic
rituals for manufacturing legitimacy (Topal 2009).
The participants of public meetings are also criticized on the grounds that they are unrepre-
sentative of the broader community (Roberts 2004). A common observation is that meetings
are typically occupied by people from organized interest groups; and the discussion dominated
by the articulate and those with the most intense feelings (for an overview, see Williamson and
Fung 2004).
Public meetings and hearings are also not particularly deliberative events. Much of their time
is dedicated to technical presentations or speeches. Public input is typically restricted to short
comment sessions in which there is limited or no opportunity for an exchange of arguments.
Agendas are typically set in advance and the scope of discussion tightly controlled by the com-
missioning body. The structure of public meetings also tends to foster adversarial conditions. For
example, contributors from the public typically stand at microphones at the front of the room
facing ocials with their backs to the other public participants (Williamson and Fung 2004).
While public meetings may not be a useful way for citizens to deliberate or directly inuence
policy decisions, some scholars argue that they provide an opportunity for citizens to perform a
number of other political functions. Empirical research nds that public meetings enable citizens:
(1) to send information and signals to decision-makers and the media; (2) to publically support
or shame public ocials; (3) to set the policy agenda; (4) to delay decisions; and (5) to form
networks (Adams 2004). Unlike more structured consultative or deliberative forums (discussed
below), public meetings are open events for anyone to attend, and therefore carry opportunities
for citizens to employ advocacy tactics and political manoeuvring (Adams 2004). In this sense,
public meetings fulll an important democratic role in the policy system by encouraging public
accountability and government responsiveness (Adams 2004; Snider 2003). Others speculate that
public meetings might promote positive rituals that rearm civic values and encourage social
cohesion (McComas et al. 2010).
Over the past decade, various improvements to public meetings have been proposed (e.g. see
Baker et al. 2005), including incorporating more deliberative elements (McComas et al. 2010),
linking them more closely to other forms of citizen engagement (Adams 2004), and utilizing
new forms of information technology to make them more accessible, transparent, and publicly
accountable (Snider 2003).
Innovative forms of public engagement
Many of the limitations identied above with conventional approaches to public engagement
have given rise to a host of innovative ways to involve dierent publics more deeply and
meaningfully in policy issues. A particular emphasis of this innovation has been to diversify the
kinds of participants that engage and their level of participation. I focus here on procedures that
engage everyday citizens in a process of extensive public deliberation. Typically, the citizens
deliberations are independently facilitated, and informed by input from experts and other policy
actors. The essence of the deliberative process is that the discussions and emerging recommen-
dations are based on a thorough consideration of all the arguments in view of the public interest
(Hendriks 2011).
The most popular deliberative process, particularly for local governments, is the citizens jury,
which typically brings together a panel of approximately 20 randomly selected citizens for sev-
eral days to deliberate on a particular policy issue (Crosby and Nethercut 2005). Bigger events
such as deliberative polls can engage hundreds of people in policy deliberations by combining
small and large group discussions (Fishkin 2009). Even larger is the 21st Century Town Meeting
Policy evaluation and public participation
441
model in which thousands of people can participate (often in multiple venues) with the aid of
networked computers and polling key pads (Lukensmeyer et al. 2005). Participants work in small
groups of around ten but are also collectively linked up to a central database for large-scale
dialogues. Some innovative deliberative procedures, such as citizens assemblies have been speci-
cally designed to connect to formal institutions of representative democracy, such as parliaments
and referenda (Warren and Pearse 2008).
Deliberative forms of public participation have been applied in most Western democracies on
a range of issues including urban planning, energy, gene technology, health care, housing, nuclear
waste, consumer protection, and indigenous aairs (Gastil and Levine 2005; Goodin and Dryzek
2006; Hajer 2005; Hendriks 2005; Johnson 2009; Parkinson 2004).
Notwithstanding the growth of deliberative governance, its practice faces some signicant
challenges. One of the key limitations with deliberative procedures to date is their lack of
institutionalization. In practice surprisingly few deliberative projects are connected to, and have
an impact on, existing governance arrangements (e.g. Goodin and Dryzek 2006). The most well-
documented case is the British Columbia citizens assembly which considered electoral reform
(Warren and Pearse 2008). Limited institutionalization has implications for the sustainability of
public deliberation because it relies on actors outside the state to instigate and fund projects
(Williamson and Fung 2004). Indeed, the most innovative participatory projects (in terms of out-
reach and scale) in the United States, and in Australia have been instigated and funded by various
non-state actors such as foundations, academics, entrepreneurs, think tanks and nongovernmental
organizations (NGOs). But the promotion of public deliberation by non-state actors can be
viewed as an important part of democratizing the policy process. Indeed these participatory
projects represent insisted spaces used by non-state actors to build community capacity or
evaluate projects or their own internal decision-making processes (Carson 2008).
Another important limitation of deliberative governance is that its practice does not typically
extend into the realm of policy evaluation. To date most deliberative forms of public engage-
ment have been used in the early stages of policy development, for example, to assist citizens to
dene policy problems and/or to develop future policy scenarios or prioritize policy options
(Hartz-Karp 2005). Typically citizens have limited opportunity to deliberate on the eectiveness
of a particular policy program and its implementation. Indeed, there are only a few documented
cases where the deliberative process has given citizens the opportunity to not only set the policy
agenda, but also to monitor and evaluate progress on proposed strategies or goals. For example,
Fung (2003) describes a community policing project in Chicago in which there were extensive
ongoing deliberations with opportunities for participants to review policies and recommend
changes. A number of participatory budgeting projects have also provided opportunities for
citizens to evaluate policy programs in the context of allocating and monitoring funds for local
infrastructure and public services (Baiocchi 2005; Johnson 2009).
Innovative forms of public engagement have also taken place on the web in the form of
e-governance. Governments are increasingly placing services online and encouraging citizens to
provide feedback. Social media technologies such as Twitter and Facebook have opened up
communication channels (though mostly one-way) for agencies to communicate with their
constituents. Some departments now conduct web-based surveys, but these tend to replicate
many of the problems with traditional surveys as discussed above (Robbins et al. 2008). For this
reason there has been some experimentation with more interactive forms of online engagement
where discussion is facilitated (Boner et al. 2005).
A growing number of government agencies have also been championing the application of
collaborative web technologies (web 2.0) such as wikis and social networking platforms as a
means to promote more open, accountable and responsive government (e.g. Government 2.0
Hendriks
442
Taskforce 2009). While these crowd sourcing approaches oer new interfaces for citizens to
learn more about, and possibly engage in, government activities, there is the danger that they oer
only a limited form of e-engagement among groups of like-minded people (Lubensky 2009).
The Internet oers a number of opportunities for expanding who engages in participatory
processes, and how. Web technology has also been used eectively to complement face-to-face
deliberative processes (Hartz-Karp 2005). Notwithstanding the potential of the Internet for
enhancing public participation, its use to date in public agencies has been mostly about enhan-
cing customer service as opposed to consultation and engagement (Dutil et al. 2007). Indeed the
long-term danger, particularly for policy evaluation is that opportunities for public engagement
are lled with shallow forms of e-governance that seek limited customer and client feedback
rather than considered input from citizens.
Pursuing participatory policy evaluation
The expansion of participatory governance over the past decade has gone largely unnoticed by the
literature on policy evaluation. Instead the role of participation in evaluation has been construed
in narrow terms through the lens of performance management where public engagement is
limited to one-way modes of involvement, such as citizen satisfaction surveys.
Yet as this chapter has shown ex post policy evaluation can be greatly enriched by the appli-
cation of more innovative forms of public participation. Processes that emphasize inclusion and
deliberation can help to elicit important perspectives on policy programs and agencies, and expose
relevant arguments, perspectives, and values to public scrutiny. Participation can also help public
managers to negotiate the increasing complexity of policy issues by bringing those aected by
policies into the evaluation process. Most importantly the inclusion of aected publics helps to
secure the democratic legitimacy of an evaluative process and its outcomes.
Participation, however, poses a number of challenges for policy evaluation. First, drawing more
voices into the evaluation process can intensify the politics of an evaluation program. While all
forms of policy evaluation involve competing actors framing, blaming and credit claiming
(Bovens et al. 2006: 323), opening the process up to more inclusive and deliberative forms of
participation risks intensifying contestation. This is especially the case when participation is
extended to everyday citizens, whose perspectives may not be considered valid or legitimate.
Greater deliberation in policy evaluation is likely to be resisted by powerful actors who benet
from the status quo or those who are keen to keep issues out of the public spotlight (Hendriks
2002, 2011). It also needs to be recognized that not all services and issues are amenable to direct
citizen engagement and participation. Fair and open dialogue will be dicult in those contexts
where there is a sense of policy failure, crisis or declining trust (Bovens et al. 2006).
The second challenge concerns the common criticism that public participation is too often
tokenistic and unsustainable. Many participatory eorts represent one-o projects that are
poorly integrated into existing governance arrangements and institutions (Williamson and Fung
2004). Evaluation processes are especially vulnerable in this respect because they are often out-
sourced to independent bodies. Moreover, it is not uncommon for the one agency or policy to
be evaluated multiple times resulting in piecemeal and disconnected recommendations (Bovens
et al. 2006). The challenge with any participatory evaluation is to ensure that it is connected to
other forms of evaluation and the broader institutions of governance. It is also important that
any participatory evaluation is situated in an overall strategy for public engagement that targets a
range of policy actors using dierent processes.
Third, participation can generate tensions and complexities for public managers. One core
challenge is trying to reconcile the publics desire for greater involvement while at the same
Policy evaluation and public participation
443
time attempting to be an authoritative voice or decision-maker (Yang and Callahan 2007). Public
managers also face constraints within their organizations, for example they are often unable to
choose the way they engage with the community, since the mandate and powers of their agency
shape purpose and practice (Stewart 2009b: 49). As a result, many participatory activities are
outsourced to private consultants, which has implications for public sector accountability (see
Speers 2007) and the sustainability of public engagement more generally (see Hendriks and Carson
2008; Williamson and Fung 2004). The broader challenge here is that participatory policy evalua-
tion requires a shift in the way bureaucracies authorize, manage and demonstrate accountability
(Goetz and Gaventa 2001).
Participation also requires public managers to accommodate alternative forms of knowledge
that typically do not sit well alongside more traditional evaluation approaches which produce
quantitative data with seemingly denitive results. Ultimately, the outputs from any evalua-
tion process involving participation must compete with the ndings emerging from other more
traditional forms of policy evaluation. In the process of judging di erent arguments, the validity
of citizens preferences can often be called into question, and labeled as too impressionistic,
irrational, or idiosyncratic (Hendriks 2011; Yang and Callahan 2007). The challenge for public
managers is to ensure that citizens input into an evaluation process receives equal consideration
alongside the perspectives of elites and lobby groups.
In order to tackle these and other challenges, the eld of public administration needs to better
equip its practitioners with skills for undertaking participatory forms of governance (Bingham et
al. 2005; OECD 2001). New skills and incentive structures are required to help practitioners
expand their participatory eorts in evaluation beyond citizen surveys towards more inclusive
and deliberative approaches. Skills are also needed to not only manage and conduct participation,
but also to eectively communicate its limits and constraints. As Stewart suggests (2009b: 49):
Engagement is about understanding where people are coming from and making sure they know
which of their concerns might (or might not) be aected as a result of their participation.
Deepening the role of participation in policy evaluation oers an important opportunity to
democratize the policy process. After all evaluation is the stage where the eectiveness of policy
programs are assessed, and the site where new ideas and agendas are formed. Thus widening and
deepening public involvement in the policy evaluation process will enrich the conclusions
reached, and ultimately their legitimacy.
Notes
1Bydeliberative here I mean an interactive form of communication in which participants provide
reasons for their positions, listen to the arguments of others, and are open to changing their position in
view of the better argument (Dryzek 2000).
2 For more, see Institute for Citizen Centre Service (ICCS), available at: http://www.iccs-isac.org/en/cf/
Bibliography
Adams, B. 2004. Public meetings and the democratic process, Public Administration Review 64(1): 4354.
Alford, J. and J. OFlynn. 2009. Making sense of public value: Concepts, critques and emergent meanings,
International Journal of Public Administration 32(3): 17191.
Althaus, C., P. Bridgman and G. Davis. 2007. The Australian Policy Handbook. Crows Nest: Allen and
Unwin.
Baiocchi, G. 2005. Militants and Citizens: The Politics of Participatory Democracy in Porto Alegre. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Baker, W.H., H.L. Addams and B. Davis. 2005. Critical factors for enhancing municipal public hearings,
Public Administration Review 65(4): 4909.
Hendriks
444
Barnes, M., J. Newman, A. Knops and H. Sullivan. 2003. Constituting the public in public participation,
Public Administration 81(2): 37999.
Benington, J. 2009. Creating the public in order to create public value?, International Journal of Public
Administration 32(2): 23249.
Bingham, L.B., T. Nabatchi and R.O. Leary. 2005. The new governance: Practices and processes for
stakeholder and citizen participation in the work of government, Public Administration Review 65(5): 547.
Blalock, A.B. 1999. Evaluation reseach and the performance management movement: From estrangement
to useful integration?, Evaluation 5(2): 11749.
Boner, P.A., R. Carlitz, R. Gunn, L.E. Maak and C.A. Ratli. 2005. Bringing the public and government
together through online dialogues, in J. Gastil and P. Levine (eds) The Deliberative Democracy Handbook:
Strategies for Eective Civic Engagement in the 21st Century. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 14153.
Bovens, M., P. t Hart and S. Kuipers. 2006. The politics of policy evaluation, in M. Moran, M. Rein
and R.E. Goodin (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Public Policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 319 35.
Callahan, K. 2000. Performance measurement and citizen participation, in M. Holzer and S. Lee (eds)
Public Productivity Handbook, 2nd edn. New York: Marcel Dekker.
Carson, L. 2008. Creating democratic surplus through citizens assemblies, Journal of Public Deliberation
4(1): Article 5. Available at: http://services.bepress.com/jpd/vol4/iss1/art5/
——, S. White, C. Hendriks and J. Palmer. 2002. Community consultation in environmental policy
making, The Drawing Board: An Australian Review of Public Aairs 3(1): 113.
Crosby, N. and D. Nethercut. 2005. Citizens juries: Creating a trustworthy voice of the people,in
J.
Gastil and P.
Levine (eds) The Deliberative Democracy Handbook: Strategies for Eective Civic Engagement in
the Twenty-First Century. San Francisco: Jossey Bass, 11119.
Curtain, R. 2006. Engaging citizens to solve major public challenges, in H.K. Colebatch (ed.) Beyond the
Policy Cycle: The Policy Process in Australia. Crows Nest: Allen and Unwin, 12142.
Dryzek, J.S. 2000. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
—— 2010. Foundations and Frontiers of Deliberative Governance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dutil, P.A., C. Howard, J. Langford and J. Roy. 2007. Rethinking government-public relationships in a
digital world, Journal of Information Technology and Politics 4(1): 7790.
Einsiedel, E.F., E. Jelsøe and T. Breck, T. 2001. Publics at the technology table: The Australian, Canadian and
Danish Consensus Conferences on Food Biotechnology, Public Understanding of Science 10(1): 8398.
Fischer, F. 1995. Evaluating Public Policy. Chicago: Nelson Hall.
—— 2000. Citizens, Experts, and the Environment. Durham, NC: Duke University.
—— and J. Forester (eds). 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Fishkin, J. 2009. When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy and Public Consultation. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Forester, J. 1999. The Deliberative Practitioner: Encouraging Participatory Planning Processes. Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press.
Fung, A. 2003. Deliberative democracy, Chicago style: Grass-roots governance in policing and public
education, in A. Fung and E.O. Wright (eds) Deepening Democracy: Institutional Innovation in Empowered
Participatory Governance. London: Verso, 111 43.
—— 2006a. Varieties of participation in complex governance, Public Administration Review 66(1)
(supplementary): 6675.
—— 2006b. Democratising the policy process, in M. Moran, M. Rein and R.E. Goodin (eds) The
Oxford Handbook of Public Policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 66985.
Gastil, J. and P. Levine. (eds). 2005. The Deliberative Democracy Handbook: Strategies for Eective
Civic
Engagement in the
Twenty-First Century. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Goetz, A.M. and J. Gaventa. 2001. Bringing Citizen Voice and Client Focus into Service Delivery, IDS Working
Paper 138. Brighton: Institute of Development Studies.
Goodin, R.E. and J. Dryzek. 2006. Deliberative impacts: The macro-political uptake of mini-publics,
Politics and Society 34(2): 21944.
Government 2.0 Taskforce. 2009. Engage: Getting on with Government 2.0. Canberra: Commonwealth of
Australia.
Guba, E.G. and V.S. Lincoln. 1989. Fourth Generation Policy Evaluation. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Hajer, M. 2005. Rebuilding Ground Zero. The politics of performance, Planning Theory and Practice 6(4):
44564.
Policy evaluation and public participation
445
—— and H. Wagenaar. 2003a. Introduction, in M. Hajer and H. Wagenaar (eds) Deliberative Policy
Analysis: Understanding Governance in the Network Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 130.
—— and H. Wagenaar. (eds). 2003b. Deliberative Policy Analysis: Understanding Governance in the Network
Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Halachimi, A. and M. Holzer. 2010. Citizen participation and performance measurement: Operationalising
democracy through better accountability, Public Administration Quarterly 34(3): 37899.
Hartz-Karp, J. 2005. A case study in deliberative democracy: Dialogue with the city, Journal of Public
Deliberation 1(1): Article 6. Available at: http://services.bepress.com/jpd/vol1/iss1/art6.
Head, B. 2007. Community engagement: Participation on whose terms?, Australian Journal of Political
Science 42(3): 44154.
Heberlein, T.A. 1976. Some observations on alternative mechanisms for public involvement: The hearing,
the public opinion poll, the workshop and the quasi-experiment, Natural Resources Journal 16: 197212.
Heikkila, T. and K.R. Isett. 2007. Citizen involvement and performance management in special-purpose
governments, Public Administration Review 67(2): 238.
Hendriks, C.M. 2002. Institutions of deliberative democratic processes and interest groups: Roles, tensions
and incentives, Australian Journal of Public Administration 61(1): 6475.
—— 2005. Participatory storylines and their impact on deliberative forums, Policy Sciences 38(4): 120.
—— 2008. On inclusion and network governance: the democratic disconnect of Dutch energy transitions,
Public Administration 86(4): 100931.
—— 2011. The Politics of Public Deliberation: Citizen Engagement and Interest Advocacy. London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
—— and L. Carson. 2008. Can the market help the forum? Negotiating the commercialization of deliberative
democracy, Policy
Sciences 41(4): 293313.
Ho, A.T.
2005. Citizen participation in performance management, in R.C. Box (ed.) Democracy and Public
Administration. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe.
Holzer, M. and K. Kloby. 2005a. Sustaining citizen-driven performance improvement: models for adoption
and issues of sustainability, The Innovation Journal: The Public Sector Innovation Journal 10: 120.
—— and K. Kloby. 2005b. Public performance measurement: An assessment of the state-of-the-art and
models for citizen participation, International Journal of Productivity and Performnce Management 54(7): 51732.
Horner, L., R. Lekhi and R. Blaug. 2006. Deliberative Democracy and the Role of Public Managers. London:
The Work Foundation.
Howard, C. 2010. Are we being served? A critical perspective on Canadas Citizens First satisfaction surveys,
International Review of Administrative Sciences 76: 6583.
Hunold, C. and I.M. Young. 1998. Justice, democracy and hazardous siting, Political Studies, 46(1): 8295.
IAP2. 2007. IAP2 Spectrum of public participaton (International Association for Public Participation
(IAP2). Available at: http://iap2.org/associations/4748/les/IAP2 Spectrum_vertical.pdf (accessed 6
January 2009).
Johnson, G.F. 2009. Deliberative democratic practices in Canada: An analysis of institutional empowerment
in three cases, Canadian Journal of Political Science 42(3): 679703.
Jørgensen, T.B. and B. Bozeman. 2007. Public values: An inventory, Administration and Society 39(3):
35481.
Kathelene, L. and J. Martin. 1991. Enhancing citizen participation: Panel designs, perspectives and policy
formulation, Policy Analysis and Management 10(1): 4663.
Kelly, J.M. 2005. The dilemma of the unsatised
customer in a
market model of public administration,
Public Administration Review 65(1): 76.
—— and D. Swindell. 2002. A multiple-indicator approach to municipal service evaluation: Correlating
performance measurement and citizen satisfaction across jurisdictions, Public Administration Review
62(5): 610.
Kickert, W.J.M., E.-H. Klijn and J.F.M. Koppenjan. (eds). 1997. Managing Complex Networks: Strategies for
the Public Sector. London: Sage.
King, C.S., K.M. Feltey and B.O.N. Susel. 1998. The question of participation: Toward authentic public
participation in public administration, Public Administration Review 58(4): 31726.
Kooiman, J. (ed.). 1993. Modern Governance: New Government: Society Interactions. London: Sage.
Koppenjan, J. and E.-H. Klijn. 2004. Managing Uncertainties in Networks: A Network Approach to Problem
Solving and Decision Making. London: Routledge.
Lowi, T.J. 1969. The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States, 2nd edn. New York:
Norton.
Hendriks
446
Lubensky, R. 2009. Submission to Government 2.0 Taskforce (Canberra). Available at: http://gov2.net.
au/submissions/ron-lubensky/.
Lukensmeyer, C.J., J. Goldman and S. Brigham. 2005. A town meeting for the twenty-rst century,in
J. Gastil and P. Levine (eds) The Deliberative Democracy Handbook: Strategies for Eective Civic Engagement in
the 21st Century. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 15463.
McComas, K.A. 2001. Theory and practice of public meetings, Communication Theory 11(1): 3655.
——, J.C. Besley and L.W. Black. 2010. The rituals of public meetings, Public Administration Review
70(1): 12230.
Majone, G. 1989. Evidence, Argument and Persuassion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Marsh, D., C. Lewis and P. Fawcett. 2010. Citizen-centred policy making under Rudd: Network gov-
ernance in the shadow of heirarchy?, in C. Aulich and M. Evans (eds) The Rudd Government: Australian
Commonwealth Government 20072010. Canberra: ANU E-press, 14360.
Moore, M. 1995. Creating Public Value: Strategic Management in Government. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Niemeyer, S. 2004. Deliberation in the wilderness: Displacing symbolic politics, Environmental Politics
13(2): 34772.
OFaircheallaigh, C. 2002. A New Approach to Policy Evaluation: Mining and Indigenous People. Aldershot:
Ashgate.
OECD. 2001. Citizens as Partners: Information, Consultation and Public Participation. Paris: OECD.
—— 2009. Focus on Citizens: Public Engagement for Better Policy and Services. Paris: OECD.
Olson, M. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Osborne, D. and T. Gaebler. 1992. Reinventing Government. New York: Plume.
Parkinson, J. 2004. Why deliberate? The encounter between deliberation and new public managers,
Public Administration 82(2): 37795.
—— 2006. Deliberating in the Real World: Problems of Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy. Oxford Oxford
University Press.
Putnam, R.D. 1993. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University
Press.
Reddel, T. and G. Woolcock. 2003. From consultation to participatory governance? A critical review of
citizen engagement strategies in Queensland, Australian Journal of Public Administration 63(3): 7587.
Renn, O., T. Webler and P. Wiedemann (eds). 1995. Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Robbins, M.D., B. Simonsen and B. Feldman. 2008. Citizens and resource allocation: Improving decision
making with interactive web-based citizen participation, Public Administration Review 68(3): 564.
Roberts, N. 2004. Public deliberation in an age of direct citizen participation, American Review of Public
Administration 34(4): 31553.
Salter, L. 2007. The public of public inquiries, in L. Dobuzinskis, M. Howlett and D. Laycock (eds) Policy
Analysis in Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto, 291314.
Schneider, A.L. and H. Ingram. 1997. Policy Design for Democracy. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas.
Smith, G. 2009. Democratic Innovations: Designing Institutions for Citizen Participation. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Snider, J.H. 2003. Should the public meeting enter the information age?, National Civic Review, 92(3):
209.
Speers, K. 2007. The invisible private sector: Consultants and public policy in Canada, in L. Dobu-
zinskis, M. Howlett and D. Laycock (eds) Policy Analysis in Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto,
399422.
Stewart, J. 2009a. Public Policy Values. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
—— 2009b. The Dilemmas of Engagement: The Role of Consultation in Governance. Canberra: Australian New
Zealand School of Government and ANU E-Press. Available at: http://epress.anu.edu.au/dilemmas_cit
ation.html.
Topal, C. 2009. The construction of general public interest: Risk, legitimacy and power in a public
hearing, Organization Studies 30(23): 277300.
Wanna, J. 2009. Collaborative government: Meanings, dimension, drivers and outcomes,inJ.OFlynn
and J. Wanna (eds) Collaborative
Governance: A New
Era of Public Policy in Australia? Canberra: ANU
EPress, 312. Available at http://epress.anu.edu.au/anzsog/collab_gov/pdf/whole_book.pdf
Policy evaluation and public participation
447
Warren, M. and H. Pearse. (eds). 2008. Designing Deliberative Democracy: The British Columbia Citizens
Assembly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williamson, A. and A. Fung. 2004. Public deliberation: Where we are and where can we go?, National
Civic Review, winter.
Yang, K. and K. Callahan. 2007. Citizen involvement eorts and bureaucratic responsiveness: Participa-
tory values, stakeholder pressures, and administrative practicality, Public Administrative Review March/
April: 24964.
Zhong, L.J. and A.P.J. Mol. 2008. Participatory environmental governance in China: Public hearings on
urban water tari setting, Journal of Environmental Management 88(4): 899913.
Hendriks
448
Part IX
Policy dynamics
Patterns of stability and change
33
Policy dynamics and change
The never-ending puzzle
Giliberto Capano
Understanding policy change in order to grasp policy dynamics
Public policy is a dynamic phenomenon. This means not only that policies are intrinsically
processual, but also that as a whole they are not the simple sum of their individual parts (stages,
actors, institutions, time, instruments, etc); at the same time their parts are variously interlinked
via a dense web of interconnections, the nature, dynamics and eects of which should not be
taken for granted. The world of policy dynamics is an incredibly fascinating puzzle of which
scholars are constantly striving to discover the basic elements and reliable, regular patterns. It is
precisely because of their dynamic nature that policies may appear at one and the same time
both stable and changing. However, stability and change are a product of observers viewpoints.
They depend on which analytical categories are used, and on what observers are actually looking
for. The same element of dynamics, or the same time span, in the historical development of a
policy may appear either stable or characterized by signicant changes. The dierent theoretical
perspectives cannot, however, hide the dynamic nature of public policy, and the diculties
encountered in trying to explain its underlying features. Moreover, those scholars who assume
that policies are characterized by long periods of stability have to admit that in the end these
same policies change, possibly in a dramatic, radical manner, and they often struggle to explain
such structural movements. On the other hand, those who assume that the dynamic character of
policy means that it continuously changes, albeit from another point of view, have to deal with
a complex, multifaceted, evasive set of questions.
The truth is that in order to understand policy dynamics, the analytical focus has to be directed
towards change. As Heraclitus stated, everything ows: change is a feature of human devel-
opment, and also of social and political phenomena. The same is true of public policies: they are
moving events, routines, strategies, and adaptations (Heclo 1972: 83). In the policy eld, as in
politics, change is the norm (Lewis and Steinmo 2010), so to say that all policy is policy
change (Hogwood and Peters 1983) is not a provocation or a symbolic metaphor, but an
inexorable fact.
Change is the normal status of policy-making, whereas stability is simply contingent upon
human agency (through rules, institutions, social norms, ideas, etc.) striving to control envir-
onmental uncertainty (Blyth 2011). However, this collective eort is not always coherent, and
451
is very often conictual (because dierent actors have dierent ideas about what constitutes stabi-
lity), and thus the stability of public policy is simple a partial, static point of equilibrium in policy
dynamics. From this point of view, studying policy dynamics means developing, from both
theoretical and empirical points of view, patterns of policy change over time.
All theoretical attempts made to explain the puzzle of policy change have to deal with certain
fundamental issues which may be summarized as follows.
First of all, there is a set of basic questions. What has really changed? How do policies change?
When do they change? Why do they change? (Capano 2009). These questions focus on the
fundamental elements that every scholar interested in solving the puzzle of policy dynamics has
to face up to, namely: (1) the denition of what change is at stake (the dependent variable
problem); (2) an understanding of how policy change develops (the logic of change direction);
(3) the explanation of why policy change occurs (the causality problem); and (4) the reasons for
the timing of change.
Second, all eorts to explain policy have to identify its fundamental causal mechanisms (also
perceived as the drivers, generators, motors of change).
Third, all theoretical frameworks have to deal with the problem of the role of agency in
policy change (are actors really agents of change, or are they simply tools in the hands of structural
factors?).
The most important frameworks present in studies of policy dynamicsincluding the Advo-
cacy Coalition Framework (ACF) (Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith 1993; Sabatier and Weible 2007),
the Punctuated Equilibrium Framework (PEF) (Baumgartner and Jones 2002, 2009; Baum-
gartner et al. 2009), the Multiple Stream Approach (MSA) (Kingdon 1984; Zahariadis 2003),
the Path Dependence Framework (PDF) (Mahoney 2000; Pierson 2000, 2004), the Policy
Generations Framework (PGF) (de Vries 2005, 2010), as well as neoinstitutionalist theories (both
from the historical perspective (Streeck and Thelen 2005; Mahoney and Thelen 2010) and from
the rational perspective (Ostrom 1990, 2005), have all proered dierent sets of answers to the
above-mentioned issues.
The basic questions
The dependent variable problem
The study of the content of policy change is a puzzle within a puzzle, since very often the object of
analysis is presented in an ambiguous, unclear manner. Policies are not only dynamic, but are
also composed of dierent elements (actors, goals, instruments, strategies, laws, plans, paradigms,
preferences); furthermore, from a structural point of view, policies are multilevel processes (health
policy ranges from the state level to the individual level, via an intermediate political-institutional
level). So when policy change is the dependent variable, we need to clarify exactly what
dimension of policy is under scrutiny, and where this is situated in the institutional arrange-
ment. The what question represents the real cornerstone of all attempts to analyze policy change
(although the where question may still be important). The what question is not a problem
for mainstream political science, whereas policy change is simply the output of the political process.
However, this perspective (which can help us to understand, for example, the content of policy
decisions at the legislative level) is somewhat limited, and is not useful to those who believe in
the dynamic, processual, and multilevel nature of policy-making. For policy scholars studying
policy as political scientists, policy is not simply an output of the political process but is the
political process itself. So, in order to resolve the question, the complex composition of policies
should be disaggregated for analytical purposes (Howlett and Cashore 2009).
Capano
452
It is clear that this analytical disaggregation is a researchers decision. It depends on the de-
nition attributed to policy, and on the scientic goals of the investigation. Policy literature since
the end of the 1980s has witnessed various denitions of the dierent components of policy,
and thus of policy change, starting with the idea of tripartition, submitted by Sabatier (1988), based
on the distinction between technical aspects, policy strategies, and deep policies values. Peter
Hall (1993) echoed this tripartition idea, albeit from a dierent theoretical perspective. Cashore
and Howlett (2007) proposed a sixfold taxonomy of policy elements, based on the separation
between ends and goals, and the tri-cotomization of the level of abstraction through which ends
and means can be dealt with (high level abstraction, program level operationalization and spe-
cic on-the-ground measures). However, none of these examples is exhaustive, since the dis-
aggregation of the components of policies, and thus of the possible dependent variable in the
case of the analysis of policy change, is based on the specicdenition of what policy is, as there
could be several potential lists of the constitutive components of policies. What is important
here, nevertheless, is that research attempts to clearly dene which dimension, aspect or element
of policy is the real object of its analysis.
The game being played out here is not a simple one: due to the constitutive multidimensional
nature of policies, their dynamic nature, and the unclear character of their horizontal and ver-
tical borders, the problem of identifying the dependent variable in policy change is highly
demanding, and one that needs to be dealt with while avoiding any form of reductionism. You
can choose to study policy change in a specic sector by focusing on changes in instruments, or
in the legislative content of policies, or in the role of policy actors; however, it is theoretically
and methodologically wrong to assume that the chosen aspect perfectly represents the overall trend
in that policy sector. Thus a strictly epistemological consciousness is required in order to accept
that the choice of dependent variablethe way in which policy change is operationalized
does not perfectly t with the observed general developments of policy dynamics, whereas it
can help to explain a part thereof. The possible implications of the ways in which these partially
explained changes can inuence the rest of the dynamics in question, are a matter for further
research.
The logic of direction problem
The how problem focuses on the directionality of policy change (Nisbet 1972; Baumgartner
and Jones 2002; Cashore and Howlett 2007). Policy change can be incremental or radical; linear
(a coherent development of the past) or nonlinear (when a change represents a break with the
past, creating a completely new situation); reversible or irreversible (Capano 2009). Obviously,
these dimensions of the how problem are not objective, but are the researchers intellectual
construct. How policies change is another puzzle within a puzzle, the solution of which lies
with the researcher, that is, it depends on his/her epistemological and theoretical choices.
However, what needs to be underlined here is that there are no strict relations between these
three dimensions of the question of how policy changes. For example, even though one would
think of linearity as being linked with incremental dynamics, studies show that incremental pro-
cesses can lead to radical, apparently irreversible, changes in the medium-/long-term nonlinear
output (as all historical-institutionalist studies have shown; see Mahoney and Thelen 2010 for all).
However, at the same time, linearity and incrementalism are not logically connected with
irreversible outputs (as the renewed role of governments in addressing the economy following
the nancial crisis of 2008 clearly shows). The same reasoning can be adopted with regard to the
possible links between radical change and its irreversibility. As the PEF and PGF have shown,
the punctuated developments of policy dynamics (radical changes following long periods of
Policy dynamics and change
453
stability) are not necessarily irreversible, and are very often characterized by oscillation between
policy choices (but against this conclusion are those historical neoinstitutionalists who adopt a
path-dependent perspective). It is clear here that the temporal dimension is essential if we are to
establish whether a change is linear, radical, or irreversible. However, as we shall see tempo is
a key factor in policy dynamics and change. It is clear that a change may seem incremental if the
period of time in question is very brief, whereas it can appear radical if the time span is increased.
The temporal dimension makes the dierence in the perception of how policies change. How-
ever, once again what matters is the researchers choice: the temporal aspect of the considered
change is clearly at his/her discretion. From this point of view, all debate between the incre-
mentalist and radical perspectives, vis-à-vis policy change (as well as political change), yields
very little. Given that everything ows in policy dynamics, in the long run everything changes
radically, albeit through an incremental process. At the same time, a radical change in time t1
can open the door to the reestablishment of old policy features in time t2. From this point of
view, the how of policy change should be contextualized from both the structural and the
diachronic perspective. It is intrinsically contingent and related to the specic context in which
change occurs.
The causality problem
Why do policies change, and why do they change in a given manner? In order to answer the
third fundamental question when dealing with the puzzle of policy dynamics, account must be
taken of the structural complexity of policy. In fact, policy is a process, and thus the dependant
variable chosen to operationalize policy change, is embedded in a ux of interrelated factors
(actors, institutions, interests, routines) which inuence each other; since it is a process, policy
develops over time, so the same dependent variable may be aected by dierent factors at dierent
times; since policy does not exist in a vacuum, but is rmly situated within a specic environ-
ment (with speci c political, social, economic characteristics) there are many potential inde-
pendent and intervenient variables which could inuence policy change (Capano and Howlett
2009b). This structural complexity of policy dynamics cannot be understood by pursuing over-
simplications or general theories. In fact there is not only one possible way by which policies
change, and there are several dierent possible explanations of such change. Nevertheless, recent
research may help to clarify our explanations of policy change.
First of all, the complexity of policy dynamics (and the highly intricate interdependence of its
components) is a structural factor inviting scholars to abandon their exogenous-driven expla-
nations. External factors matter, obviously, but they do not directly determine policy change.
Environmental changes can be facilitators or triggers of change, but the what change and how
policy changes conundrums depend on the internal characteristics of the policy eld aected by
the external stimuli. So all the external shock hypotheses should be put aside when studying
policy change. This is a real problem for the more commonly adopted explanatory frameworks:
it is particularly true for the ACF and for the PEF, which assume the fundamental role of external
perturbations, events, and changes in determining policy change. However, the relevance of internal
dynamics as a reaction (not only in an adaptive way) to environmental pressures, has been pointed
out on several occasions in the past (Mahwinney 1993; Capano 1996), and empirically proven in
recent years by research in various dierent policy elds (Capano and Howlett 2009a; Williams
2009), while also being admitted by those scholars who have done relevant research following the
ACF (Weible et al. 2009). So the explanation of policy change should be integrative, by ordering
relations between external and internal dynamics. Thus the why of policy change can be
externally inuenced, although the nal word rests with internal characteristics and developments.
Capano
454
Second, due to the complexity of policy dynamics, the relationship between cause and eect
is extremely problematic, and strictly linked to context, timing, and contingency. So policy change
is unforeseeable: small movements can lead to large-scale change, while important events may
have extremely limited eects.
Third, and most importantly, due to its complexity, the why question cannot be answered
from a linear, causal perspective. Explaining policy change cannot be done by searching for net
causal eects, that is, by assuming simple and linear causal relations between independent and
dependent variables. Policy change is a matter of combinatorial causes (Ragin 2006), and due to
its complexity, the same policy change can be caused by dierent combinations of causes or of
causal mechanisms present at any given moment (Jervis 1997). It would seem that Aaron Wild-
avsky (1979) was right when he invited scholars to consider policy as its own cause, because its
complexity means that its specic conguration (its contextual pattern of behavior and interac-
tions) matters in the policy change process. Furthermore, policy conguration is stable but not
static, due to its continual adjustments caused by both its internal and external interactions.
So in order to explain why policies change, the researcher has to resolve a moving puzzle:
the dependent variable is constantly moving within a context (the conguration of the policy)
that is stable, but not static.
The temporal problem
For too long, policies have been considered as historical phenomena. However, policy dynamics
represent a process, meaning a sequence of events, actions, interactions, outputs and outcomes
over the course of time. The temporal dimension of policy change has been rediscovered thanks to
the historical-neoinstitutionalism and path-dependent perspectives, although both approaches are
based on a traditional perception of the temporal dimension of policies as another way of
representing historical time.
However, there are other dimensions of time involving policy dynamics and change. Fol-
lowing the theoretical proposals of Barbara Adam (2004), these dierent dimensions of temporality
constitute the timescape of policy change. Time frame, timing, temporality, tempo, duration, and
sequence are the most relevant dimensions of the intrinsic temporality of policy dynamics and
change. The time frame is the period of time of policy dynamics that is analyzed when studying
changes in said policy dynamics. The ACF, for example, suggests that the study of policy change
should focus on a period of at least ten years of the policy dynamics, because changes need time
to develop and emerge. The time frame chosen by the researcher has a deep impact on the expla-
natory eort. In fact, the longer the period analyzed, the greater the likelihood that the status of
the dependant variable changes, becoming an independent or intervenient variable Further-
more, it is clear that the time frame also aects the evaluation of how policy has changed:
what seems to be incremental in the short run could become radical in the long run, and vice
versa. The timing of policy dynamics and change focuses on the synchronization between policy
dynamics and the external environment. For example, there could be a temporal misalignment
between the debate over possible changes inside and outside the policy domain (i.e. in the
publics opinion or in the political system). From this point of view, timing is also the temporal
dimension of the policy windows (Kingdon 1984), which can be conceived as the perfect over-
lapping of the timing of dierent dynamics (the political and policy ones). Temporality represents
the directionality of time: it can be linear or cyclical. It is linear when that time returns no
more, indicating the irreversibility of the change in question. It is cyclical when that time
nally returns, thus representing the reversibility of change. The tempo dimension accounts for
the intensity and the density, and thus the speed, of the dynamics, and therefore of the achieved
Policy dynamics and change
455
change. A high tempo means that the change in a specic policy time frame has been very fast,
and that time has been utilized intensely. Duration is the dimension through which policy
dynamics develop, and the time required to achieve policy change.
The sequence is the order of succession through which policy dynamics develops, and policy
scholars have specically focused on this temporal dimension of public policy in their analytical
eorts to take account of the path dependency inuence on policy trajectories (see Adrian Kay
in this volume) and to explain the policy sequence through the process tracing (see Carsten
Daugbjerg in this volume). There are two ways of conceiving the temporal sequence of the policy
dynamics and change (Howlett 2009). The rst one, following the path dependence approach,
is characterized by turning points, that is, critical junctures at which policy change occursvery
often due to contingent eventsand long periods of inertia. This type of sequence represents
the historical trajectory of policy dynamics, characterized by periods of momentum in which
changes occur. It is a kind of linear succession between changes which are intended as irrever-
sible, and produced substantially by external shocks or by the incapacity of current policy (and
its inertial character) to adapt to external transformations. In this version, the sequence seems to be
external to policy dynamics and change. The second type of sequence, suggested by Haydu
(1998), is conceived as a kind of dialectical confrontation over time between contrasting solu-
tions to recurring problems. From this point of view, the temporal sequence of policy dynamics
and change is an ongoing battle between solutions to the same problems, in which the temporary
winner is the result of contingent factors which are not random, as in the path-dependent
sequence, but the product of agency (actors pursuing their own interests or ideas). So the logic
of this sequence is based on reversible changes. This way of dening the sequence considers the
succession of events as an internal, intrinsic process of policy dynamics and change. Conceived
in this way, the temporal sequence is another way of emphasizing the potential that endogenous
factors have to forcibly inuence policy change.
This deconstruction of time in policy dynamics and change considerably helps our under-
standing of how important the choice of time dimension is when analyzing and accounting for
policy change. For example, were one to decide to focus on a time frame of one year, during
which a new legislative reform has been adopted, the result would be a change characterized by
high tempo (high density and speed), right timing and linear temporality. However, were this
time frame extended to 20 years, the researcher may discover, for example, that ten years later
the new law has been reversed (cyclical temporality) or its implementation has been slow and
ineective (low tempo) and characterized by a contingent, and so nondecisive, overlapping between
the policy timing and the external one (Loomis 1994; Pollit 2008). The concept of time, then,
should be taken seriously by policy scholars, especially by those involved both in better devel-
oping the sequential nature of policy dynamics and in designing ne-grained frameworks of
policy trajectories, while it should be pointed out here that the most highly reputed theoretical
frameworks give only limited importance to it. The PDF simply adopts the rst type of tem-
poral sequence, while the ACF takes the time frame dimension into consideration, since long-
itudinal analysis is at the basis of the analytical logic of those advancing the latter. The PGF assumes
the second type of sequence. In the case of the MSA, only timing is a relevant dimension of tem-
porality. Finally the IAD seems to be uninterested in the temporal dimension of policy-making
altogether.
Causal mechanisms of policy change
Explaining policy change is a frustrating activity for those who do not adopt a covering-law legal
perspective of explanation. If the search for linear causality is abandoned, as I have proposed
Capano
456
above, the explanatory enterprise becomes very complex, and basically never-ending. It is no
coincidence that many theoretical frameworks have been proposed in the policy literature to
explain policy change, and that they are all complex designs of multiple interconnected factors.
Combinatory causality, that is, the search for the interconnected mechanisms whereby change
occurs, characterize all of them. There is not sucient space here to portray their fundamental
characteristics, and as such they are well-known to the policy scholars. Multiple Stream Approach,
Punctuated Equilibrium Framework, Advocacy Coalition Framework, Policy Generation Fra-
mework, Path Dependence approaches and Institutional Analysis and Development Framework
have for a long time been part of policy scholars toolkit. They are all dierent from each other,
although they have certain characteristics in common: they all assume the processual nature of
policy dynamics, that is, that policy change occurs through a specic process; they analyze epi-
sodes that are continuous streams of social and political life (Tilly 2001), and they try to grasp
the most relevant factors which inuence change. To be more precise, all these frameworks try
to dene the most relevant causal mechanisms of policy change.
Causal mechanisms are portable concepts that describe how causation occur (Falleti and Lynch
2009: 1148). As Tilly points out, mechanisms form a delimited class of events that change relations
among specied sets of elements in identical or closely similar ways over a variety of situations
(2001: 256). Mechanisms constitute the links between input and outputs, between external shocks
and policy change, between internal policy development and subsequent changes. As Falleti and
Lynch point out: Mechanisms tell us how things happen: how actors relate, how individuals
come to believe what they do or what the draw from past experience, how policies and institutions
endure or change. (2009: 1147). So, focusing on mechanisms means searching for the the pathway
or process by which an eect is produced or a purpose is accomplished (Gerring 2008: 178).
The concept of causal mechanisms is more precise than that of drivers or factors. It assumes
that a potential driver or factor of change is exactly the means by which causes produce eects.
A causal mechanism means that a factor or a driver, thanks to its action, produces certain out-
comes. Another property of mechanisms is that they do not produce eects in a determinist
way; their outcomes are inuenced by the context. This is because the same causal mechanism
can produce dierent eects in dierent contexts, and the same eects can be produced by dierent
causal mechanisms.
Assuming a mechanismic perspective leads scholars to choose the most relevant causal mechanisms
from among all potential factors, thus simplifying the possible theoretical framework.
Seen from this point of view, all of the most commonly used theoretical frameworks for
explaining policy change have clearly some specic factors handled as causal mechanisms. The
ACF, for example, has particularly emphasized actors beliefs and learning; the path dependence
approaches and certain versions of historical-institutionalism have focused on critical junctures
and increasing returns; other streams of neoinstitutionalist thought have placed the emphasis on
policy drift, conversion, layering, and replacement; the PEF and the PGF have given impor-
tance to the shifting of attention and on the ux of new information. The PEF (in an initial
version) also emphasized the role of multiple institutional venues, which were later perceived as
institutional frictions. The IAD approach has focused on institutional arrangements. The MSA
has emphasized the relevance of policy windows and policy entrepreneurs. Furthermore, all of
the aforementioned frameworks and theories pay attention, albeit to dierent degrees, to the
role of ideas and institutions as signicant causal mechanisms.
So from this point of view, the variety of theoretical frameworks designed to explain policy
change re ects dierent
choices with regard to what are considered the most signicant causal
mechanisms in
play within policy-making. They vary also regarding another causal mechanism,
time, as I have shown above.
Policy dynamics and change
457
There are some positives to reasoning in terms of a mechanismic perspective when trying to
explain policy change. The rst one is that this approach takes due account of a chosen set of
potential causal mechanisms, handling them in a more comfortable way, thus avoiding the risk of
overestimation (for example, globalization is clearly a causal mechanism inuencing many national
policy elds, but should be considered together with other specic causal mechanisms which
vary from one country to the next, according to the specic national context).
The second one is that the mechanismic approach to explanation perfectly ts with the processual
nature of change: nding causal mechanisms means, in fact, reconstructing the diachronic
dynamics leading to change.
The third one is that, through a comparative analysis, this approach provides us with a better
understanding of which contextual factors favor the eectiveness of specic causal mechanisms
(policy learning does not work in the same way in dierent countries and in dierent policy elds;
new information do not have the same eects in dierent countries or in dierent policy elds).
Fourth, the search for causal mechanisms could be the best way of dealing with the structural,
multilevel nature of policy dynamics and change. In fact the multi-institutional arrangements of
public policy means that dierent causal mechanisms can work in the same policy eld, but because
every institutional layer represents a dierent context, changes are not only of dierent types,
according to the diversity of the layer, but are also based on dierent sets of causal mechanisms.
The same mechanism may work in dierent ways, depending on the specic level at which the
change is occurring (learning at the legislative stage is somewhat dierent from, and works in a
dierent way from, learning at the micro level, where the change has not only to be approved
but also to be implemented).
Fifth, causal mechanisms can also help us to understand how agency and structure actually interact
and matter in determining policy change (for example, whether the eect of new information
alters the behavior of actors because of structural conditions, or because of the rational will of
policy actors).
Sixth, focusing on causal mechanisms could be very fruitful when performing comparative
processual analyses, by reconstructing policy trajectories and sequences. In fact, the majority of
current theoretical frameworks are not very helpful when it comes to comparing policies or
countries, since they contain too many factors and elements (especially the ACF and IAD, whereas
PEF is more interested in analyzing policy change as a sequence of discrete decisions). This is
not a call for theoretical parsimony, which would be an impossible mission when analyzing policy
change, but simply for more aordable theoretically oriented research, in which the comparative
perspective constitutes an ineludible methodological tool.
So, by focusing on sets of causal mechanisms, the study of policy change could be more man-
ageable and better suited to the accumulation of knowledge. At the same time, the adoption of
a mechanismic perspective seems to be very much in keeping both with the trajectory and the
sequence of policy dynamics and with the intrinsic processual nature of policy change. By
working on sets of causal mechanisms, the interaction and eects of which develop over time, it
is possible to investigate and order the possible patterns (that is, trajectories and sequences) of
policy dynamics and change.
One nal point which deserves to be mentioned here is that the present plethora of studies of
policy change by policy scholars contains certain potential causal mechanisms which have not
been taken into due consideration, or which have been aorded marginal importance. In fact,
the theoretical frameworks proposed in an attempt to explain policy change, have paid con-
siderable attention to causal mechanisms such as learning, policy legacy, lock-in eects,
feed-
back, information, rules,
ideas, and institutional arrangements, and so on, but have given little
importance to other possible factors which could play a relevant role as causal mechanisms in
Capano
458
policy change, such as leadership, the features of political systems, and interest groups. These factors
are basically absent from policy change research, perhaps because they belong to the mainstream
of political science, and are thus considered to be the conceptual tools of policy scholars
rivals. I think that this gap should be lled, because policy change is replete with leaders
trying to lead processes (that is, to resist or to address change) at all institutional levels; parties,
politicians, bureaucrats and governments which are all constantly involved in policy dynamics;
interests groups which, day by day, attempt to maintain or change their status and rewards
within the dynamics of policy change (for example, how much of the comparative dierence in
welfare reforms is due to the national structure of interests groups?).
Thus, broadening the perspective of the potential causal mechanisms, by taking in the theore-
tical toolbox of policy scholars and the abovementioned three causal mechanisms, is a necessary
step toward improving the quality of research into policy change.
The puzzle and the agents
The dynamics and characteristics of change may vary, depending on the country in question,
the chosen policy eld, the content at stake, the institutional level, and the historical period.
What denitely does not vary is the central role of agency in inuencing such change. Policies
are made by actors, not by structural conditions, ideas, institutions, political parties, or interest
groups. (Lundquist 1980). Policy actors are those who act in the policy arena, during all phases of
the policy-making process. They are the ones who learn, who receive new information on
policy problems, and who interpret such problems. They are the ones whose attention shifts dia-
chronically. They are the ones who pursue their own interests and ideas. They are the ones who
determine the internal temporal dimensions of policy change and dynamics. They are the ones
who, through their daily behavior (consisting of decisions and nondecisions, interactions, learning,
search for solutions) determine the persistence of, or change in, policy dynamics. Obviously
they are strongly inuenced and guided by the context, that is, by institutions, social norms, and
patterns of institutionalized roles. However, in the end, actual decisions are the results of their
own willtheir constrained willbut nevertheless their will. Policy actors are the ones who,
take causal mechanisms and make them work within the reality of policy-making. Policy actors
are those who determine how policy changes. They do so both for incremental and radical
changes (Wilsford 2010).
In fact, even in an apparently static situation, the actors decision to choose Y instead of X
(for example, to eliminate a specic policy instrument, or to adopt another in its place) can make a
dierence because this incremental choice could alter the policy congurations, inducing other
actors to change their behavior by creating a slow, but clear, cascade of eects. Although Y or
X are limited alternatives permitted by the present equilibrium, and by the strong institutiona-
lized constraints on actors, their choice is not determined by the context but depends on the
will and the actions of policy-makers. Why do policy actors opt for Y rather than X in a similar
context, given their similar preferences and boundaries? The question may be a small one, but
small decisions in similar contexts may lead to changes in policy trajectory and sequence in the
medium and long term.
Policy actors are also those responsible for deciding what can be done at critical junctures in
time and at turning points, precisely when existing boundaries and contextualized constraints
become minimized. In such contingent situations, when a new trajectory can be chosen or the
policy sequence can be redirected, it is precisely the policy actors and their coalitions who decide
what the new path to be taken is going to be, and what the contents of radical change shall consist
of. Policy actors are the ones who constantly interpret contingencies, and take responsibility for
Policy dynamics and change
459
deciding whether there are any opportunities for change, and they sometimes act so as to create
the conditions for change.
Policy dynamics is an abstract concept constantly fed by the real actions of policy actors. Such
policy actors may behave as leaders, entrepreneurs, interest-driven politicians, old-fashioned
bureaucrats, and so on, but they nevertheless constitute the core of policy dynamics and its
sequence, and thanks to their actions and interactions, policy dynamics survive and policy
change occurs.
It is precisely due to this agency role that the theoretical eorts made to order policy dynamics
and to understand policy change constitute a never-ending puzzle. We constantly try to conne
agency within patterns of regular behavior (institutional arrangements, arenas, networks, etc.),
but very often it evades our theoretical restraints, and thus the search for the solution to the
puzzle continues.
Bibliography
Adam, Barbara. 2004. Time. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones (eds). 2002. Policy Dynamics. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
——and Bryan D. Jones. 2009. Agendas and Instability in American Politics, 2nd edn. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
——, Christian Breunig, Christoer Green-Pedersen, Bryan D. Jones, Peter B. Mortensen, Michiel
Nuytemans and Stefaan Walgrave. 2009. Punctuated equilibrium in comparative perspective, American
Journal of Political Science 53(3): 60320.
Blyth, Mark. 2011. Ideas, uncertainty, and evolution, in Daniel Beland and Robert Henry Cox (eds) Ideas
and Politics in Social Science Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 83101.
Capano, Giliberto. 1996. Political science and the comparative study of policy change in higher education:
Theorico-methodological notes from a policy perspective, Higher Education 31(3): 26382.
—— 2009. Understanding policy change as an epistemological and theoretical problem, Journal of Comparative
Policy Analysis 1(1): 731.
——and Michael Howlett (eds). 2009a. European and North American Policy Change. Drivers and Dynamics.
London: Routledge.
——and Michael Howlett. 2009b. Conclusion: A research agenda for policy dynamics, in Giliberto
Capano and Michael Howlett (eds) European and North American Policy Change. Drivers and Dynamics.
London: Routledge, 21531.
Cashore, Benjamin and Michael Howlett. 2007. Punctuating which equilibrium? Understanding thermostatic
policy dynamics in Pacic Northwest forestry, American Journal of Political Science 51(3): 53251.
de Vries, Michiel S. 2005. Generations of interactive policy-making in the Netherlands, International
Review of Administrative Sciences 71(4): 57791.
—— 2010. The Importance of Neglect in Policy-Making. London: Macmillan.
Falleti, Tulia and Julia Lynch. 2009. Context
and causal mechanisms in political analysis, Comparative Political
Studies 42(9): 114366.
Gerring,
John. 2008. The mechanismic worldview: Thinking inside the box, British Journal of Political
Science 38(1): 16179.
Hall, Peter. 1993. Policy paradigms, social learning, and the state: The case of economic policymaking in
Britain, Comparative Politics 25(3): 27596.
Haydu, Jerey. 1988. Making use of the past: Time periods as cases to compare and as sequences of
problem solving, The American Journal of Sociology 104(2): 33971.
Heclo, Hugh. 1972. Review article: Policy analysis, British Journal of Political Science 2(1): 83108.
Hogwood, Peter W. and Guy B. Peters. 1983. Policy Dynamics. New York: St. Martins Press.
Howlett, Michael. 2009. Process sequencing policy dynamics: Beyond homeostasis and path dependency,
Journal of Public Policy 29(3): 24162.
——and Ben Cashore. 2009. The dependent variable problem in the study of policy change: Understanding
policy change as a methodological problem, Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 1(1): 3346.
Kingdon, John W. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little, Brown.
Capano
460
Jervis, Robert. 1997. System Eects: Complexity in Political and Social Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Lewis, Orion and Sven Steinmo. 2010. Taking evolution seriously in political science, Theory in Biosciences
129 (23): 23545.
Loomis, Burdett A. 1994. Time, Politics, and Policies: A Legislative Year. Lawrence, KS: University Press of
Kansas.
Lundquist, Lennart. 1980. The Hare and the Tortoise: Clean Air Policies in the United States and Sweden. Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Mahoney, James. 2000. Path dependence in historical sociology, Theory and Society 29(4): 50748.
——and Kathleen Thelen (eds). 2010. Explaining Institutional Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Mawhinney, Hanne B. 1993. An advocacy coalition approach to change in Canadian education, in Paul
Sabatier and Henk Jenkins-Smith (eds) Policy Change and Learning. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 5981.
Nisbet, Robert. 1972. Introduction: The problem of social change, in Robert Nisbet (ed.) Social Change.
New York: Harper and Row, 145.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1990. Governing the Commons. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 2005. Understanding Institutional Diversity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Pierson, Paul. 2000. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, American Political Science
Review 94(2): 25167.
—— 2004. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Pollitt, Christopher. 2008. Time, Policy, Management. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Ragin, Charles. 2006. How to lure analytic social science out of the doldrums: Some lessons from comparative
research, International Sociology 21(5): 63346.
Sabatier, Paul. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy oriented
learning therein, Policy Science 21(23):
12968.
——and Henk Jenkins-Smith
(eds) 1993. Policy Change and Learning. An Advocacy Coalition Approach.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
——and Christopher Weible. 2007. The advocacy coalition framework: Innovations and clarications,in
Paul A. Sabatier (ed.), Theories of the Policy Process, 2nd edn. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 189220.
Streeck, Wolfgang, and Kathleen Thelen (eds). 2005. Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced
Political Economies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tilly, Charles. 2001. Mechanisms in political processes, Annual Review of Political Science 4: 2141.
Weible, Christopher, Paul Sabatier and Kelly McQueen. 2009. Themes and variations: Taking stock of
the advocacy coalition framework, Policy Studies Journal 37(1): 12140.
Wildavsky, Aaron. 1979. Speaking Truth to Power: The Art and Craft of Policy Analysis. Boston: Little, Brown.
Williams, Russell A. 2009. Exogenous shocks in subsystem adjustment and policy change: The credit
crunch and Canadian banking regulation, Journal of Public Policy 29(1): 29 53.
Wilsford, David. 2010. The logic of policy change: Structure and agency in political life, Journal of Health
Politics, Policy and Law 35(4): 66380.
Zahariadis, Nikolaos. 2003. Ambiguity and Choice in Public Policy. Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Press.
Policy dynamics and change
461
34
Policy trajectories and legacies
Path dependency revisited
Adrian Kay
The emergence of a new institutionalism across the social sciences has coincided with the
increased interest in temporality, change and history in social and political analysis. Institutions are
structures that endure, have a history and can be used to link temporally events and processes.
The concept of path dependency has been used within policy studies and political science almost
exclusively within a broad institutionalist framework. It is institutions that are path dependent;
as Raadschelders (1998: 569) states: whatever the discipline contemporary neo-institutional
analysis has one feature in common: the notion of path dependency. The widespread and
cross-disciplinary use of path dependency for the analysis of institutional stickiness makes the
concept an obvious starting point for the examination of policy trajectories and legacies. Indeed,
the concept appeals as a label for the simplest of policy dynamics: that past policy decisions act as
an institution-like constraint on the options available to current policy-makers; or to use the
language of dynamics, past policy decisions act to circumscribe or foreclose parts of policy space.
This chapter revisits path dependency in light of its appeal as a means of understanding the
process and logic of policy trajectories and legacies, with a particular focus on the renement of
the concept in response to complaints of determinism and an inability to accommodate change.
A process is path dependent if initial moves in one direction elicit further moves in that same
direction; in other words the order in which things happen aects how they happen; the tra-
jectory of change up to a certain point constrains the trajectory after that point. As Douglass North
puts it, path dependency is a process that constrains future choice sets:
At every step along the way there are choices political and economic that provide
real alternatives. Path dependence is a way to narrow conceptually the choice set and link
decision-making through time. It is not a story of inevitability in which the past neatly
predicts the future.
(1990: 989)
The reference to choice sets and decision-making reveals the origins of the concept in economics.
Indeed, path dependency is problematic for that discipline because it implies that decentralised
interactions between economically rational actors do not necessarily lead to ecient outcomes;
indeed, inecient equilibria may be recognised as such but still persist.
462
The concept of path dependency is not a framework or theory or model in the terms of
Ostrom (1999: 3941): it does not provide a general list of variables that can be used to organise
diagnostic and prescriptive inquiry nor does it provide hypotheses about specic links between
variables or particular parameters of those links. Instead, path dependency is an empirical category,
an organising concept or metaphor which can be used to label a certain type of temporal process.
As Hall and Taylor put it:
they [historical institutionalists] have been strong proponents of an image of social causation
that is path dependent in the sense that it rejects the traditional postulate that the same
operative forces will generate the same results everywhere in favour of the view that the
eect of such forces will be mediated by the contextual features of a given situation often
inherited from the past.
(1996: 941)
The application of this organising concept or metaphor to a phenomenon is only the beginning
of a form of explanation. Although it asserts a relationship between the sequence of early events
and the probability of later events, the concept of path dependency does not per se provide
necessary or sucient conditions to understand or explain that which it labels: path dependent
processes, even when identied, require theorising; it is the mechanisms that connect decisions
or actions across time that explain a path-dependent process.
Although both refer to mid-range phenomena, policy and institution are not synonyms.
Within the policy system, there are various structures at dierent scales which act as institutions
in shaping agents decision-making in the formulation, enactment and implementation of policy.
These are not reducible to individual level agents or single elements in the policy process.
Examples of policy institutions are budget rules, policy networks, shared mental maps as well as
the standard operating procedures for policy-making in government departments and agencies.
Most importantly in terms of understanding policy development as path dependent, past policy
decisions are institutions in terms of current policy decisions: they can act as structures that can
limit or shape current policy options.
The question of what about a policy is path dependent does not admit a single, conclusive
answer; rather it remains an open question for scholars applying the concept with theoretical
and empirical corollaries. If the policy whole or system is path dependent, there may be several
potential underlying mechanisms operating, independently or in combinations. This property of
multiple realisability has theoretical implications in terms of the micro foundations of path depen-
dency and the spatial and temporal scales of policy analysis. It is necessary when using the concept,
either theoretically or empirically, to be clear about the perspective being adopted. The devel-
opment of a policy may be labelled path dependent over some period, but the various mechanisms
that underlie that process remain unclear unless a more ne-grained perspective is adopted.
Without micro foundations, the value of the concept in making sense of policy trajectories is
doubtful. Indeed, path-dependent processes may coexist with other types of processes within
policy systems. This is important in order to avoid the imputation that path dependency is
simply a fashionable neologism for the notion that history matters. An adequately ne-grained
perspective is essential in using path dependency analytically; when policies or elements of
policies are seen as strongly interrelated or where our analytical lens shows policy institutions as
deeply interwoven then a much clearer sense of the mechanisms that underlie path-dependent
processes is gained.
The rst section of the chapter considers the application of path dependency to the analysis
of policy development and its potential advantages in understanding the dynamics of that
Policy trajectories and legacies
463
development. The next section considers several criticisms of the concept: that it lacks a convin-
cing account of decision-making over time, both of the accumulation of constraints and context
bound rationality; it is incapable of dealing with policy change; and it lacks a clear normative
focus. In the nal section, I argue that despite its theoretical underdevelopment and relatively
limited number of successful empirical applications, the concept of path dependency does have
potential utility in the eld of policy studies in terms of understanding why policies might be
dicult to reform and also why they may tend to become more complex over time.
Benets of path dependency for understanding policy trajectories
and legacies
Path dependency is an appealing concept for understanding public policy development; it pro-
vides a label for the observations and intuitions that policies, once established, can be dicult to
change or reform. Early and inuential examples of the use of path dependency for understanding
policy development include health care policy in the US (Hacker 1998, 2002; Wilsford 1994)
and the UK (Greener 2002); the reform of housing benet in the UK (Kemp 2001); to UK
pension policy (Pemberton 2003); and the Common Agricultural Policy (CAP) of the European
Union (Kay 2003).
Path dependency encapsulates the insight that policy decisions accumulate over time; a pro-
cess of accretion can occur in a policy area that restricts options for future policy-makers. In this
sense, path dependency arguments can provide an important caution against a too easy con-
clusion of the inevitability, naturalness, or functionality of observed outcomes (Pierson 2000a:
252). For example, Pemberton (2003) argues that the pensions crisis in the UK is not primarily
demographic but rather due to a low savings rate; further, this low rate is a function of the path
dependency and increasing complexity of pension policy. The system of pension provision in the
UK has shifted over the last 25 years from one dominated by state provision to one in which
the state pension plays a residual welfare role. Despite this large change at the policy system level,
there is evidence of path dependency in particular policy subsystems. In the case of UK pen-
sions, policy subsystems exist around specic pension schemes. An individual contract established
under a particular pension scheme at a particular time is costly to change: there are large sunk
costs; increasing returns associated with rising numbers of contributors and pensioners in a par-
ticular scheme; further, there may be signicant learning eects. All of these factors contribute
to signicant switching costs for the abolition of one scheme and the transferring of that set of
individual contracts into a superseding scheme. Particular schemes are locked in for particular
individuals. Nonetheless, pension reform has been possible but change has come in the form of
the addition of new schemes or elements to the system. This amounts not to a single, path dependent
policy trajectory but rather to a widening array of locked in subsystems over time. This accretion
of new subsystems or schemes has led to the increasing complexity of the overall system of pen-
sions and raised questions of eectiveness at a policy whole level. Kemp (2001) reports similar
dynamics with regard to housing benet policy in the UK.
Path dependency can help separate not just dierent orders of policy change as in Hall (1993),
but dierent rates of policy change. One of the foundations of dynamic policy analysis is the
assumption that there are a multitude of temporal scales immanent in any system. Therefore, within
a policy system, there may be some elements that are path dependent, and others that are not.
Further, there may be a relationship between the dierent processes at dierent speeds. Later in
the chapter, I develop the point that it is the combinations of institutions and policies that
provide the important mechanisms underlying path dependency but also create the potential for
strategic action and policy innovation by agents.
Kay
464
The concept of path dependency has the additional advantage of exibility for policy scholars.
In particular, because the concept does not contain within it a xed temporal or spatial scale of
analysis, the insights of path dependency can often complement rather than rival other accounts
of policy change. Social housing in the UK is an example of where path dependency can hold
at the subsystem level with interesting consequences, but where the policy system as a whole
has changed profoundly. Since the mid-1970s there has been a series of failed initiatives by
central government to directly control the rents charged in the social housing sector and ensure
equity between local authorities and housing associations. This particular element of social
housing policy is path dependent; each local authority has an established policy for rent calcu-
lation, often determined by initial decisions made in the immediate post-war era. That these
have proved resistant to central control or inuence signicantly constrains the ability of central
government to pursue some of its objectives for social housing. However, during the same
period as this path-dependent process there has been a clear shift in the social housing policy
paradigm as home ownership increased substantially, notably through the central governments
right to buy scheme introduced in the early 1980s that allowed local authority tenants to buy
their own home.
Problems of path dependency for understanding policy trajectories
and legacies
Accounts of decision-making over time
The criticism that the concept of path dependency lacks explanatory power is well expressed by
Raadschelders:
it is only by virtue of retrospect that we are aware of stages or paths of development. Path
dependency refers to a string of related events: causality in retrospect. The concept does
not come even close to pinpointing a mechanism or the mechanisms that propel social
change.
(1998: 576)
The quotation contains two criticisms. The rst is that the concept cannot be used for current or
future phenomena. This is, of course, not a singular feature of path dependency but common to
all concepts that are useful for structuring retrospective, thick historical descriptions to support
narrative explanations in the social sciences. Indeed, as discussed in the previous two chapters, a
dynamic perspective reveals that this is not an appropriate standard for considering the utility of
dierent concepts, theories or metaphors.
The more important criticism is that even if one accepts path dependency as intuitively appeal-
ing, it is unlikely to be convincing analytically because the notion does not provide any ne-
grained mechanisms that might provide necessary and sucient conditions for the process observed.
The challenge for the use of path dependency in the study of policy trajectories is the unco-
vering of mechanisms that can help make sense of a path dependent process. One inuential strand
of the literature on path dependency has worked on the micro foundations of the concept using
insights from new institutional economics. Much of this literature proceeds by analogy from
technological development to institutional development. In simple terms, imagine two tech-
nologies, A and B, both of which are subject to increasing returns but there is uncertainty over
the rate of increasing returns. Initial adoptions of one technology, say B, which may occur for a
number of small or chance reasons, beget further adoptions of B in the market because of
Policy trajectories and legacies
465
increasing returns namely it becomes cheaper for future rms to adopt technology B rather than
A. The interesting results from the models built on these assumptions (for economists at least)
are that you might get inecient technologies adopted by markets. The normative implications
of this borrowing from economics are considered in more detail later.
Arthur (1994) states the circumstances in which path dependence as an increasing returns
process is likely: the presence of large xed (and sunk) costs; network eects; learning eects;
and adaptive expectations. As noted, these factors have been used at a macro, constitutional level
to make arguments about path dependency in institutional development (North 1990; Pierson
2000a, 2000b, 2000c). Within this list of sources of increasing returns, it is useful to distinguish
between those factors that relate to the internal eciency of rms large xed costs leading to
declining average costs as production increases and learning eects from those that are external
to the rm, in particular, network eects. The distinction is important because later in the chapter,
path dependency is discussed in terms of the increasing returns involved in combinations of
institutions and policies rather than increasing returns as a property of the internal operations of
rms. This complements the insistence on a ne-grained perspective of policy systems developed
in this chapter.
A focus on increasing returns is only a partial interpretation of the economics of path depen-
dency. Increasing returns are sucient but not necessary for path dependency. As Arrow (2000)
points out, the existence of signicant sunk costs along with sequencing arguments can support
many of the path dependency narratives of technological change. Although he does not use the
concept of path dependency, Arthur Stinchcombes (1968: Chapter 5) celebrated work on
constructing theories of historical causation emphasises the central importance of sunk costs. I
submit that any decision that is dicult to reverse and which has enduring and ongoing eects
can be said to have initiated a path-dependent process; and work on path-dependent processes
should not focus exclusively on increasing returns processes and it is moot whether they should
privilege this mechanism-type over other sources of path dependency.
Contrarily, Schwarz (2004) argues that the combination of initial, small and contingent steps
with increasing returns denes a path dependent process; if there was an large initial cause that
had signicant and enduring eect on the subsequent process then this historical cause would be
salient in any explanation of the process. The process would no longer be path dependent but
rather, as a policy dynamic, be better characterised as the temporal unravelling of the consequences
of some initial event. In a similar vein, Page (2006) introduces the idea of phat dependence to
refer to cases where it is the distribution rather than the precise sequence of early events that is
important in shaping later events. Both these insights are noteworthy in highlighting the need
for future scholarly work in cataloguing and explaining dierent types of path dependency and
its relationship to other policy dynamics such as process sequencing (see Daugbjerg in this volume).
However, for the sake of expositional clarity this chapter remains with the denition of path
dependency as a general metaphor for sticky policy or institutional processes.
A number of non-increasing returns mechanisms have been suggested as underlying path
dependency in policy development: the eect of policy on interest groups as when policies
constrain some groups and enable others (Pierson 2000a); self-reinforcing mechanisms where
policies involve investment or disinvestments in administrative infrastructure which transforms gov-
ernmental capacity and the set of possible future policies that may be enacted (Skocpol 1992);
policies that involve the establishment of formal or informal contracts with individuals (Pem-
berton 2003; Kay 2003; Kemp 2001) which are costly to change. Further, there are network
eects to types of contracts rather than the number of signatories. Once a contract is established,
the transaction costs of agreeing another contract of that type in that area of public policy will
be considerably lower than any alternative contract.
Kay
466
All these policy-specic mechanisms are based on denite, conscious choices, which have the
foreseeable consequence of high future switching costs; none relies on an increasing returns pro-
cess. Nevertheless, there are examples that suggest that increasing returns processes can occur in
policy development. In the structural reforms of the primary care sector in the UK after 1997, a
series of primary care models were piloted. By a series of chance factors, a particular primary care
trust model quickly became popular. This model subsequently became the governments tem-
plate for all future combinations of primary care organisations. There was no particular feature
to this model to recommend it over any of the others that were piloted between 1997 and 2000;
instead it was the case that this model was adopted early in the governments reform process,
which made it considerably easier (or cheaper) for subsequent primary care groups to use it, and
with such a momentum became the template adopted by the government for all primary care
agglomerations. At a general level, all metaphors of policy ideas or proposals emerging from the
policy soup or garbage can share a notion of a market place of ideas; analogous to a market
system, ideas compete for attention and inuence. Where the market structure produces increasing
returns, policy ideas can succeed into proposals and eventual enactment by an initial series of
small, contingent steps as early adopters of an idea increase the return to future adopters.
Any borrowing from microeconomics, including the idea of increasing returns, inevitably situ-
ates the agent in terms of responding to the costs and benets of dierent options in a manner
consistent with straightforward parametric rationality. The assumption of this type of rationality
serves certain purposes in formal economic modelling, but to use it in more informal, intuitive
and post-positivist accounts of path dependency in public policy is problematic (Hay 2004). One
response is to use the notion of context-bound rationality in an account of decision-making in a
path dependent process. Nooteboom (1997) describes the manner in which markets lock in to
certain technologies in similar terms to how philosophers of science characterise the entrench-
ment of scientic theories. Both can be path dependent. He cites Kuhns famous account of
how scientic theories develop according to paradigms, a set of tacit and unarticulated guiding
assumptions, rather than the standard conceptions of pure rationality at the heart of a scientic
approach. Further, just as the Kuhnian model challenges the conception of scientic activity approx-
imating to certain canons rationality, so will any parallel model applied to the economic case.
Halls (1993) widely cited notion of a policy paradigm exemplies this insight in policy studies:
a policy paradigm is an interpretative framework that operates in the policy-making process;
specically, it refers to the ideas and standards that specify the goals, instruments and the very
nature of a policy issue.
In these terms, the mechanism that underlies path dependency in the policy process is a form
of context-bound rationality among policy actors. The current path dependency literature is
mostly developed around the following two claims: (1) that the analogy from economics to
institutions can be extended to policy, and (2) that microeconomics can be borrowed as the
micro foundations of path dependency in policy development. Importantly, these claims require
a rational choice actor making the decisions. The assumption of this type of rationality is a strict
corollary of claims (1) and (2). This is potentially problematic for policy studies; in particular,
those parts of contemporary public policy theory that have begun to move away from a reliance
on the simple postulates of instrumental rationality to a more nuanced and contextualised views
of rationality.
Policy change and stability
At the heart of any account of path dependency is stability: observations of change challenge the
notion. This is a common criticism of the historical institutionalist school, in its emphasis upon
Policy trajectories and legacies
467
path dependence and historical legacies it is rather better at explaining stability than change (Hay
2002:15). Thelen (1999) argues that path dependency is simultaneously overly sensitive to initial
conditions and too deterministic and mechanical with respect to subsequent policy development.
In terms of policy studies, one possible counterargument is based on the interpretation of
stability in path dependency. Specically, the notion does allow policy change; policy legacies
constrain rather than determine current policy. Policy does change but within a particular set of
possibilities, and thus the policy may be said to exhibit stability. There are two main implica-
tions of the constrained change argument. The rst is that these bounded possibility sets may be
large or paths wide; and, the wider they are, the less the notion of path dependency can
account for current policy development. In alternative terms, the weaker is the echo of past
policy developments in the present and the more other concepts, framework and theories are
required.
The notion of policy direction may assist constrained change accounts of policy development. A
stable policy path when projected into policy space may well imply signicant cumulative policy
change over time or in other terms, a signicant distance from the initial position in policy
space and time. Rose and Davies (1994) show the importance of compounding eects as small,
incremental and constrained changes in annual budget allocations can accumulate to signicant
policy shifts over a period of a decade or more. Further, a change in direction may appear at
one distance a small perturbation but by shifting the direction of the policy may turn out in
retrospect to have been a critical juncture and a problem for the validity of path dependency as
a description.
Nonetheless, the limitations of path dependency as a conception of policy change have been
highlighted in empirical applications in public policy: for example, Kemp (2001) with respect to
housing benet reform in the UK; Pemberton (2003) with regard to pensions; Greener (2002)
on the NHS. Each of these studies nds path dependency in policy development alongside
some policy change. They consider change as a reaction to the unintended consequences or side
eects of policy, or from pressure for reform due to exogenous shifts in the wider policy envir-
onment, for example where the distribution of power between interested groups has changed.
Once a dualism between policy stability and policy change is established, the notion of path
dependency is only useful for accounting for the former; indeed the purpose of the concept is
to aid understanding of policy stickiness and why actors do not change policy across time.
However, the dualism between stability and change can be avoided by considering the
sedimentation of policy decisions or the growing complexity of policy space that is implied by
the notion of path dependency. The dynamics of policy subsystem accumulation are theoreti-
cally underdeveloped but are important for the use of path dependency in policy narratives.
The development of UK pharmaceutical policy since the 1980s is an example of new policies
being added on as a patch or x to satisfy pressure to mitigate the consequences of the ori-
ginal policy. Relatively high prices for medicines were agreed by the government to reward
innovation by the industry under the Pharmaceutical Price Regulation Scheme (PPRS), and
this contributed to the rapid increases in public expenditure on medicines observed since the late
1980s. The PPRS remains unchanged and potentially path dependent but its budgetary con-
sequences have precipitated a series of new policies aimed at controlling the demand for medicines
in the NHS e.g. cash-limited prescribing budgets. The path dependency of particular policy
subsystems is a contributory factor in the explanation of the accumulation of these policy patches
and the growing complexity of the policy system, with potential consequences for the overall
coherence and eectiveness of policy.
To reprise, a key issue when using the concept of path dependency is the granularity of the
perspective. Much of the work within the historical institutionalist literature uses the concept at
Kay
468
a macro perspective in which there is a single whole, that allows for discussion of an institutional
setting or a policy. The path then refers to the trajectory for that composite variable, the direc-
tion of which is reinforced after early moves in the sequence. While this is valid for some nar-
ratives, from a more ne-grained perspective the issue is which elements of that composite
system are xed or locked-in, and which are capable of being reformed. Further, within the policy
space occupied by the composite whole there may be potential for the introduction of new
institutions or policy subsystems.
In more ne-grained analysis, increasing returns processes operate at the level of sequences of
institutional or policy choices: once an initial policy framework is established, there are strong
increasing returns involved in the choice of new, supplementary policies within that framework.
That is, an increasing returns process explains policy change qua the introduction of new, sup-
plementary policies. As North (1990: 95) states, it is the interdependent web of an institutional
matrix that produces massive increasing returns. This view of increasing returns helps to avoid
too sharp a distinction between stability and change, as seen in on-path versus o-path change
or where stability is followed by a path-breaking juncture, and the introduction of a new institu-
tional or policy setting. At a more ne-grained perspective, institutions exist in combinations:
they are interdependent, with necessary and contingent relationships. Thelen describes examples
where institutional lock-in is combined with elements of institutional innovation that can push
the overall trajectory of policy and politics in a dierent direction; indeed to understand how
institutions evolve, it may be more fruitful to aim for a more ne-grained analysis that seeks to
identify what aspects of a specic institutional conguration are (or are not) negotiable and
under what conditions (2003: 233).
In an important recent work pushing the concept path dependency beyond simply the under-
standing of continuity, Crouch and Farrell (2004) consider how actors cope with exogenous
changes in their environment. At some point, the once reliably successful path no longer works,
and even though policy actors know this, they nd it extremely dicult to change. Simple path
dependency has the actor trappedin a strict sense the concept does not admit any other possibility;
however, a more nuanced account would look at how the perceived failure of a habitual path
may lead to the search for alternatives, but where that search process is itself path dependent.
The relatively informal models oered by Crouch and Farrell (2004) are designed to address
the apparent determinism of path dependency once a path is selected. Change is explicitly mod-
elled as the intentional adaptation of agents to exogenous, environmental shifts. The emphasis is
on the ability of agents to reactivate redundant institutions, or convert existing institutions to
dierent purposes, or borrow wholly new institutions from elsewhere to tackle exigencies.
This opens up an alternative theoretical line on the problem of policy change in historical
institutionalist theory: instead of insisting on a strict dualism between stability and change, policy
systems may be adapted to new circumstances through a gradual process of layering and con-
version rather than through periods of drastic and rapid change (Streeck and Thelen 2005; Ackrill
and Kay 2006). Layering and conversion are important causal mechanisms in a nascent non-
determinist institutional analysis of policy change (Campbell 2004; Crouch 2005, 2007). Recog-
nising that institutions shape the desires, motives and preferences of individual and group actors,
layering refers to the adding of new preferences onto an existing set of institutionally shaped
policy preferences. Such appending of new elements can lead to dysfunctionality and incoherence
in the policy system and set o path-changing dynamics. In the conversion mechanism, agents
develop new policy preferences from outside the institutionalised policy system, and convert
inherited institutions toward these novel goals and functions. There is a signicant empirical gap
in the comparative public policy literature that explores the explanatory power of the policy
layering and conversion mechanisms.
Policy trajectories and legacies
469
One implication of conversion and layering is that at the level of the composite whole, policy
systems cease to embody a simple unique logic, but rather a complex bundle of dierent policy logics,
ideas and interests. Some of these may be dormant, unused or forgotten for periods but are capable
of being reactivated by strategic action by agent in response to exogenous environmental shifts.
The reassertion of the capacity of agents situated within path dependent processes with increasing
returns to act to change the direction of the path in response to shifts in their environment is
important. Inheritance and policy legacies are not as hard or xed or as determined as some of
the simple path dependency analysis may suggest; or more accurately, increasing returns pro-
cesses in economics typically assume a static environment whereas changes in that environment
can attenuate (or amplify) feedback processes. In providing a set of mechanisms that may help to
structure a narrative in terms of transitions between paths, Crouch and Farrell (2004) provide a service
to the analysis of policy dynamics. This can complement the emphasis on inter-policy and inter-
institutional relationships, in particular combinational eects, which imply that policy development
proceeds in a more subtle way than the two-speed view of policy development.
Normative aspects of the term
One of the consequences of constructing the explanatory foundations of path dependency in
public policy by analogy from the economics of technological development is to import the
normative result that ineciencies can persist in path dependent processes. This is a powerful
result for neoclassical economics: certain historical factors can ensure that ineciencies occur
and markets do not eliminate these over time. Eciency is understood here as social eciency
namely a situation where both technical and allocative eciency hold. The strength of this nor-
mative result depends on the judgement as to whether the ineciency could have been foreseen at
some point in the initial stages in the path dependency process and corrected; and second,
whether the ineciency remains remediable, namely that a Pareto improvement can be identied
and is achievable from the current situation.
For some writers the question of whether path dependency implies the persistence of inecient
institutions is an open and empirical question (e.g. Hay and Wincott 1998); for others path
dependency is more clearly something which inhibits the introduction of better or perhaps
more rational policy or organisational form (e.g. Greener 2002). Overall, the normative impli-
cations of path dependency are less pressing for scholars outside the boundaries of neo-classical
economics; it is generally accepted that ine cient policies or institutions may persist. However,
it is a much stronger claim that policies in a path dependent process are necessarily inecient, or
alternatively, contained within the concept is the imputation of ineciency. The claim is strong
at a theoretical level as the concept would require signicant elaboration in terms of both policy
design and the pressures that sustain path dependent and inecient policy. There is also the pro-
blem of indeterminism: path dependency emphasises that policy paths are unique and arrived at by
a series of small and contingent moves. As such, it is dicult to say that there exists another path
that could have been arrived at which is more ecient and without such a relevant counterfactual
it is dicult to accept the imputation of ineciency.
At an empirical level, the claim that policies are necessarily inecient is also strong. Devel-
opments in performance measurement in the public sector that might allow arguments that, for
example, health care or education policy are better in one system than another. Despite this, it
is dicult to assert, within a particular political system, that there exist policy options which repre-
sent a welfare improvement over the current policy (net of switching costs and increased
transaction costs) and there is widespread recognition of this by policy actors. Without these
two conditions holding, the normative implications of path dependency in terms of public
Kay
470
policy are attenuated. Nonetheless empirical works on path dependency in policy development
seem willing to impute ineciency to some degree (Pemberton 2003; Kay 2003; Greener
2002; Kemp 2001; Wilsford 1994). This often not so stark as labelling policies in terms of e-
ciency and certainly involves no quantitative analysis; however, it is not an over-interpretation
of these works to tease out the implicit assumption that a policy would be better without
path-dependent processes acting as a barrier to eective reform.
Conclusion
The rise of the broad school of historical institutionalism has been a salient trend in the social
sciences over the last 20 years and its critical insights have recently been adapted for the more
ne-grained concept of policy by recognising that clusters of governmental decisions, actions,
and norms can over time form policy systems, reinforced by feedback mechanisms, which
function as institutions. Historical institutional theory is becoming increasingly rened in its atten-
tion to historical causality and aims to explain dierent types of path dependency beyond the
simple version where the inheritance of accumulated prior commitments limits substantially
current options for policy-makers (Page 2006).
Historical institutionalism has often been judged as over-emphasising positive feedback pro-
cesses and the sensitivity of institutional development to small eects at origin but under-
emphasising the subsequent opportunity for endogenous change in the process of institutional
reproduction over time (e.g. Hay 2002). It is perturbations occurring outside the institutiona-
lised policy system, often characterised as societal or political upheaval or learning, that explain
policy changes; without such exogenous shocks institutions tend to be stable.
In revisiting the concept of path dependency, this chapter has cast some light on a recent
seam of work that provides a particular focus on the capacity of policy-makers, in the
context of strong path dependent policy legacies, to innovate in response to novel demands
from the external environment. However, there are two problems for the analysis of change
within path dependent trajectories: (1) a theoretical one: it is unclear how much or which
elements of a policy system must change to be regarded as a structural break in policy devel-
opment, not just an insignicant, within path, uctuation in policy history; and (2) an empirical
one: comparative policy scholars have produced signicant and important works on policy
reform in response to various pressures, but there are few cases where dierent periods of reform
have been matched neatly to salient structural breaks or punctuated equilibria in path-dependent
trajectories.
Bibliography
Ackrill, R.W. and A. Kay 2006. Historical institutionalism and the EU budget, Journal of European Public
Policy 13(1): 11333.
Arthur, W.B. 1994. Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of
Michigan Press.
Arrow, K.J. 2000. Increasing returns: Historiographic issues and path dependence, The European Journal of
the History of Economic Thought 7(1): 17180.
Campbell, J.L. 2004. Institutional Change and Globalization. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
Crouch, C. 2005. Capitalist Diversity and Change. New York: Oxford University Press.
—— 2007. How to do post-determinist institutional analysis, Socio-economic Review 5(3): 527537.
—— and H. Farrell. 2004. Breaking the path of institutional development? Alternatives to the new
determinism, Rationality and Society 16(1): 543.
Greener, I. 2002. Understanding NHS reform: The policy-transfer, social learning and path dependency
perspectives, Governance 15(2): 16183.
Policy trajectories and legacies
471
Hacker, J.S. 1998. The historical logic of National Health Insurance: Structure and sequence in the development
of British, Canadian, and US medical policy, Studies in American Political Development 12: 57130.
—— 2002. The Divided Welfare State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hall, P.A. 1993. Policy paradigms, social learning, and the state, Comparative Politics 25(3): 27596.
——and R.C.R. Taylor. 1996. Political science and the three new institutionalisms, Political Studies 44(4):
93657.
Hay, C. 2002. Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
—— 2004. Theory, stylized heuristic or self-fullling prophecy? The status of rational choice theory in
public administration, Public Administration 82(1): 3962.
——and D. Wincott. 1998. Structure, agency and historical institutionalism, Political Studies 46(5): 9517.
Kay, A. 2003. Path dependency and the CAP, Journal of European Public Policy 10(3): 40521.
Kemp, P. 2001. Housing benet and welfare state retrenchment in Britain, Journal of Social Policy 29(2):
26379.
North, D.C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Nooteboom, B. 1997. Path dependence of knowledge: Implications for the theory of the rm, in Lars
Magnusson and Jan Ottosson (eds) Evolutionary Economics and Path Dependence. Cheltenham and Lyme,
NH: Edward Elgar.
Ostrom, E. 1999. Institutional rational choice: An assessment of the institutional analysis and development
framework,
in Paul Sabatier (ed.) Theories of the
Policy Process. Boulder, CO: Westview, 3572.
Page, S. 2006. Path dependence, Quarterly Journal of Political Science 1(1): 87115.
Pemberton, H. 2003. Lock-in or lock-out? Path dependency and British pensions, Annual Conference of
the Political Studies Association, 17 April.
Pierson, P. 2000a. Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics, American Political Science
Review 94(2): 25167.
—— 2000b. Not just what but when: Timing and sequencing in political processes, Studies in American
Political Development 14(1): 7292.
—— 2000c. The limits of design: Explaining institutional origins and change, Governance 13(4): 47499.
Raadschelders, J.C.N. 1998. Evolution, institutional analysis and path dependency: An administrative-history
perspective on fashionable approaches and concepts, International Review of Administrative Sciences 64(4):
56582.
Rose, R. and P.L. Davies 1994. Inheritance in Public Policy: Change Without Choice in Britain. London: Yale
University Press.
Schwarz, Herman 2004. Down the wrong path: Path dependence, increasing returns, and historical
institutionalism.Available at: http://www.people.virginia.edu/~hms2f/Path.pdf (accessed August 2011).
Skocpol, T. 1992. Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Political Origins of Social Policy in the United States.
Cambridge: Belknap Press of Havard University Press.
Stinchcome, A.L. 1968. Constructing Social Theories. London: University of Chicago Press.
Streek, W. and K. Thelen 2005. Introduction: Institutional change in advanced political economies,in
Wolfgang Streek and Kathleen Thelen (eds) Beyond Continuity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thelen, K. 1999. Historical institutionalism in comparative politics, Annual Review of Political Science 2:
369404.
—— 2003. How institutions evolve,
in James Mahoney
and Dietrich Rueschmeyer (eds) Comparative
Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 20841.
Wilsford, D. 1994. Path dependency, or why history makes it dicult but not impossible to reform health
care services in a big way, Journal of Public Policy 14: 25183.
Kay
472
35
Process sequencing
Carsten Daugbjerg
Introduction
1
Much policy research is undertaken within a restricted time perspective. In explaining policy deci-
sions, many studies focus on the immediate, assuming that causes and outcomes are both tem-
porally contiguous and rapidly unfolding (Pierson 2003: 178, see also Bulmer 2009). As Pierson
(2003: 180) argues: There is no reason to think that most political processes, or the most inter-
esting ones, are necessarily best understood by invoking accounts with this kind of temporal struc-
ture. A research strategy in public policy analysis focusing on the immediate may at best provide
partial understanding of policy evolution since important dynamics which are rooted in past
events may be missed. Hence, in the recent two decades or so, there has been a growing interest
among policy analysts in policy development over time, in particular among historical institution-
alists who have attempted to establish the reproduction mechanisms maintaining path dependent
policy development (see Kay, this volume). An alternative, but related, approach to explaining policy
evolution over time is process sequencing. It focuses on the temporal connections between
policy events and attempts to establish how previous policy change enables and shapes subsequent
policy changes. While analysis on path dependency focuses on the mechanisms retaining policy
development within a particular path, allowing for bounded policy change, the sequencing approach
concentrates on the way in which policy evolves without assuming that the policy direction
resulting from a series of policy reforms would be predetermined by path dependency. Rather,
it is an analytical approach to policy evolution in which ne-grained temporal analysis of the causal
relations between policy events is the key to explaining policy evolution. The basic assumption in
process sequencing is that an event in a policy sequence is both a reaction to an antecedent event
and a cause of a subsequent one. Thus, policy outcomes feed back and become inputs in the policy
process. In process sequencing, the analytical focus is on the structural constraints and opportunities
embedded in previous policy events and the ability of reform advocates to overcome the constraints
and utilise the opportunities in order to respond to challenges emerging from the broader policy con-
text or from within the policy. Though each policy adjustment is unlikely to be radical, the sequence
of adjustments may over time cumulatively amount to substantial policy change (Rose 1990: 264).
Process sequencing has only recently been suggested as an approach to analyse public policy
evolution (Howlett and Rayner 2006). It is under-theorised and therefore the purpose of this
473
chapter is to outline the approach and its basic concepts and an attempt is made to further develop
the approach by identifying some of the causal mechanisms which link events in a policy sequence.
It is suggested how learning and precedent are potentially important causal mechanisms con-
necting events in a policy sequence. Examples from the sequence of agricultural policy reforms
in the European Union (EU) over two decades are used to highlight the analytical advantages
of applying process sequencing in the study of policy evolution and reform.
Path dependency and process sequencing: two distinct approaches to
temporal analysis
Most recent dynamic analyses on policy change are based on the notion of punctuated equili-
brium which describes policy development as characterised by relatively short moments of
innovative change followed by extended periods of stability (Krasner 1984: 2404). The notion
of punctuated equilibrium has been widely accepted as a plausible model of policy evolution.
For instance, though not explicitly positioning themselves in the historical institutionalist litera-
ture, but within the agenda-setting literature, Baumgartner and Jones (1993) apply the notion of
punctuated equilibrium in explaining agenda stability over long periods of time and how
punctuations interrupt and subsequently change the policy agenda. Similarly, the advocacy coali-
tion framework developed by Sabatier (1988) and the policy network analysis school (Rhodes
and Marsh 1992) also focus on explaining policy change from a not dissimilar perspective
though the notion of punctuated equilibrium is not explicitly applied.
From a historical institutionalist perspective, radical institutional change is caused by exogenous
shocks, creating a critical juncture which is generally understood as a contingent event that
was not expected to take place, given certain theoretical understandings of how causal processes
work (Mahoney 2000: 513). The concept of path dependency was used to explain the periods
of stasis though it was not until a decade ago that more analytical emphasis was put on identi-
fying the self-reinforcing reproduction mechanisms maintaining a particular path. Clearly, this
improved our understanding of the phenomenon of path dependency (see Thelen 1999; Pier-
son 2000a; Mahoney 2000). This theoretical preoccupation with path dependency within the
historical institutionalist literature left unanswered the question of what explains institutional/
policy change. The notion of path dependency does not enable policy changes which
amounts to more than incrementalism to be explained. The statement by Thelen and Steinmo
(1992: 15) that institutions explain everything until they explain nothing still seems to apply.
Therefore, the notion of path dependency has limitations in explaining policy evolution because
policies are adjusted occasionally and such incremental adjustments may amount to substantial
change over time. Further, some adjustments appearing insignicant at the time of their adop-
tion may turn out to be an important catalyst for more comprehensive changes at a later stage.
Thus, an important theoretical question in relation to policy change is whether a sequence of
cumulative incremental policy changes can gradually lead to paradigm shift within a policy. There
is a growing literature arguing that this may be possible (Coleman et al. 1997; Cashore and
Howlett 2007; Daugbjerg and Swinbank 2009), in eect questioning the assumption of the
punctuated equilibrium model that radical change occurs in critical junctures over relatively
short time periods.
Indeed, some of the critique of path dependency originates from within the historical institu-
tionalist literature. It has been questioned whether the notion of punctuated equilibrium is a
valid metaphor for institutional and policy development, suggesting that there often seems to be
too much continuity through putative breakpoints in history, but also often too much change
beneath the surface of apparently stable formal institutional arrangements (Thelen 2003: 211).
Daugbjerg
474
Among historical institutionalists, this scepticism towards the notion of punctuated equilibrium
as the only model of institutional development has triggered a theoretical discussion on gradual
institutional change which amounts to more than just minor adjustments. Thelen (2003) and
her associates (Streeck and Thelen 2005; Mahoney and Thelen 2009) have engaged in eorts to
develop analytical devices which can help identify various types of gradual institutional transfor-
mation and understand their causes and how the transformation process unfolds. Recent theo-
retical developments suggest that much gradual institutional transformation is driven from within
the institution rather than by forces exogenous to the institution; however, institutional theory
has had little to say on this thus far (Streeck and Thelen 2005: 19; Mahoney and Thelen 2010:
67). Though this discussion focuses on institutional development, it is also highly relevant for
public policy evolution. Public policies can be considered institutions since they consist of a set
of rules which facilitate or dictate certain actions and constrain or preclude others and inuence
the allocation of economic and political resources, modifying the costs and benets associated
with alternative political strategies, and consequently altering ensuing political development
(Pierson 1993: 596).
Reactive sequencing and path dependency
A promising starting point for the development of analytical models enabling us to explain and
understand gradual institutional and policy change is the notion of reactive sequencing. Reactive
sequences are chains of temporally ordered and causally connected events (Mahoney 2000:
509) and
in a reactive sequence, each event in the sequence is both a reaction to antecedent
events and a cause of subsequent events In a reactive sequence, early events trigger
subsequent development by setting in motion a chain of tightly linked reactions and
counterreactions.
(Mahoney 2000: 526, see also Pierson 2000b: 84)
Earlier events cause the subsequent events, because they trigger a powerful response (Pierson
2000: 85), thus producing an inherent logic in the chain of events. In other words, events in
one period [are used] to explain outcomes in another (Haydu 1998: 353). This type of sequencing
has also been dubbed reiterated problem solving (Haydu 1998, 2010) or process sequencing
(Howlett and Rayner 2006). While Haydus discussion of reiterated problem solving tends to
be more general and focusing on macro-political developments and the big steps in a historical
trajectory, Howlett and Rayners discussion is focused on its relevance for the policy sciences.
Process sequencing focuses on the way in which policy events are causally connected in a policy
sequence. Some of the events may seem insignicant at the time they happen, but may turn out
to be signicant events changing direction of policy or even reversing it. Therefore process sequen-
cing requires ne-grained empirical analysis and a detailed understanding of the case under
scrutiny. Since this chapter is focused on public policy issues, I shall refer to process sequencing
in the balance of the chapter.
Mahoney (2000: 509) considers reactive sequencing as a type of path dependency because
each step in the chain [of events] is dependent on prior steps. This labelling of reactive
sequencing as a type of path dependency is based on his extraction of three basic dening fea-
tures of path dependent analysis. According to Mahoney (2000: 51011), the analysis of path
dependency is characterised, rst, by the study of causal processes that are highly sensitive to
events that take place in the early stages of an overall historical sequence. Second, he argues
Process sequencing
475
that in a path dependent sequence, early historical events are contingent occurrences that cannot
be explained on the basis of prior events or initial conditions”’. Third, after the initial step, path
dependent sequences are marked by relatively deterministic causal patterns.
From a dierent perspective, Haydu (1998, 2010) and Howlett and Rayner (2006) make a
clear distinction between path-dependent sequencing and process (or problem solving) sequen-
cing. While the rst dening feature of path dependency, as outlined by Mahoney, is unpro-
blematic for these writings, the second and the third are not dening features for process (or
problem solving) sequencing. As to the claim that the initial event in a sequence is contingent,
scholars distinguishing sharply between the two approaches to temporal analysis have argued
that outcomes at a given switch point are themselves products of the past rather than historical
accidents (Haydu 1998: 354). In their review of the public policy literature applying the punc-
tuated equilibrium model, Howlett and Rayner (2006: 7) also reach the conclusion that the
outcomes of policy switch points are outgrowths of earlier trajectories.
The third feature of path dependency, deterministic causal patterns, is also a feature dicult
to recognise in process sequencing and perhaps even in Mahoneys own portrayal of reactive
sequencing. While there is agreement that events in a temporal sequence are causally connected
and can be traced back to a historical juncture, process sequencing analysts do not recognise this
historical legacy as deterministic for future developments (Howlett and Rayner 2006: 7). In path
dependency, choices made at a critical juncture to a considerable extent lock in the trajectory of
future choices (Pierson 2000a). In process sequencing, the overall direction of the trajectory is
not conceived o as uni-directional (Howlett and Rayner 2006: 78, see also Sewell 1996: 263).
Events are causally linked through reiterated problem solving and this may involve a change of
direction. A particular trajectory is strengthened where the feedbacks from previous choices are
positive. Where feedbacks are negative, the trajectory may change direction but not necessarily
in the dramatic manner envisaged for critical junctures. Thus, as Jervis (1997: 129) argues in rela-
tion to policy evolution: although some feedbacks are amplifying or dampening, in many
other cases they force the policy in a dierent direction. The possibility of counter-reactions
caused by negative feedbacks weakens the argument, put forward by Mahoney, that the trajectory
laid down by the initial events in a sequence determines future choices and thus maintain the
path. A trajectory can only be retained in a particular direction when there are self-reinforcing
reproduction mechanisms at work in a sequence. Such mechanisms are essential to the path
dependency argument, but not to process sequencing. Though reactive sequencing, as outlined
by Mahoney, involves reaction and counterreaction mechanisms that give an event chain an
inherent logic in which one event naturally leads to another event (Mahoney 2000: 511),
the resultant sequence is not path dependent because there are no reproduction mechanisms to
sustain the sequence on a particular path.
Process sequencing in public policy
Process sequencing is particularly useful in public policy analysis (Howlett and Rayner 2006:
1314). To understand policy development, the approach emphasises ne-grained temporal
analysis of reactions and counter-reactions in a process of reiterated problem solving. The downside
of process sequencing is its limited potential to generate theoretical statements on the way in
which events in sequences are connected (Pierson 2000b: 84). In this section, the under-theorised
nature of this approach to temporal analysis of policy is addressed and it is suggested how
learning and precedent can become causal mechanisms connecting events in a policy sequence.
Connecting events causally in a sequence is an important challenge facing process sequencing
analysis. In sequential analysis
Daugbjerg
476
explanations should respect historical time by casting causal analysis in the form of sequenced
events, with earlier happenings leading to and accounting for later ones. Explanations of
this kind should, moreover, carefully specify the mechanisms through which causal inuence
is conveyed through time.
(Haydu 1998: 354)
The theoretical challenge is to consider what connects policy events without violating the ability
of the analytical approach to identify case-specic empirical details which are important for
understanding the sequence of events under scrutiny.
Policy problems and policy actors
In process sequencing, events are connected through a reiterated process of problem solving
unfolding over longer periods of time (Haydu 1998: 349). Since most public policy formulation
and implementation take place in sub-systems in which a limited number of actors are continuously
and actively involved in decision-making and often in many day-to-day administrative decisions
(e.g. Richardson and Jordan 1979; Rhodes and Marsh 1992; Baumgartner and Jones 1993;
Sabatier 1988) it is analytically useful to distinguish between endogenously or exogenously problem
dynamics. Problems are endogenously generated when they originate from within the subsystem.
These may be unintended policy eects which threaten the core functions and thus viability of
the policy. They need not necessarily aect political actors outside the subsystem but may often
do so. An example of endogenously generated policy eects is recurring budgetary diculties caused
by the cost of implementing certain policy instruments. Exogenously generated problems emerge
as a result of evolving broader policy contexts beyond the control of the policy subsystem. Devel-
opments in the broader policy context may challenge the policy and thus put pressure on the
members or the subsystem to respond with policy changes. Exogenous problems can, for instance,
be caused by the growing level of economic, cultural and political globalisation. An instance of the
latter is the inclusion of agricultural trade on the negotiating agenda of Uruguay Round of the
General Agreement on Taris and Trade (GATT) in the mid-1980s. As it became evident in 1990
that agricultural support and protection could not be sidelined in the Round, as had happened in
earlier rounds, the trade impacts of the Common Agricultural Policy (CAP) became a new key
policy problem which EU agricultural policy-makers had to address (Daugbjerg and Swinbank 2009).
An important theoretical challenge is to establish the conditions under which individual events in a
policy sequence become both an outcome of previous policy decisions and developments and a
cause of subsequent policy changes. Mahoney (2000: 511) refers to an inherent logic and a natural
connection between events and thus puts forward a somewhat deterministic view on the driving
forces behind a sequence. He tends to emphasise structure and devotes limited attention to the role
of actors in connecting events. To establish the causal link between events in a policy sequence
more attention must be paid to the way in which policy actors act within a policy structure and how
they change it. Policy sequences are continually shaped and reshaped by the creativity and stub-
bornness of their human creators (Sewell 1996: 272; see also Haydu 1998: 357, 2010: 323, 3940).
Therefore, on the one hand, theory on sequencing must leave room for agency when theorising
about the causal connection between individual events in a sequence. On the other hand, since
public policies are institutions, they constrain and facilitate certain actions over others. To have some
independent impact on a policy sequence, actors must have capacity to reect over the opportunities
and constraints embodied in previous policy events when responding to policy problems.
Hays (1995, 2002) concept of strategic learning spells out the potentials and limitations in
actors ability to reect over the policy processes in which they are involved. While lacking
Process sequencing
477
complete information, political actors have some capacity to learn. As Hay (2002: 210) points
out: given that actors are reective, routinely monitoring the consequences of their action, we
might expect their knowledge of the context to evolve over time. However, since the broader
and policy-specic context is complex and evolving, they are unlikely to reach a state of com-
plete knowledge. Through their actions and the consequences of these, policy-makers learn,
enhancing awareness of structures and the constraints/opportunities they impose, providing the
basis from which subsequent strategy might be formulated and perhaps prove more successful
(1995: 201, see also 1998: 43). Learning is based on selective knowledge on the context within
which strategic action is conducted. Since agents have incomplete information on the constraints
and opportunities embodied in the settings within which they operate, they use more or less
informed projections regarding the strategic motivations, intentions and likely actions of other
signicant players (ibid.: 44). However, since the context is constantly evolving through the
consequences (both intended and unintended) of strategic action (ibid.: 43), cumulative learn-
ing may not necessarily result. There is no guarantee that actors draw the right lessons from
past experience; indeed, they may not even have the insight to judge which lessons are right
and which ones are wrong (2002: 211). Thus, it is not the context as such which is the source
of learning but actors perceptions of the intended and unintended consequences of previous
policy decisions which connect events in a sequence.
Policy feedback: learning and precedent
The feedback from previous policy decisions is the key to establish how the actions of reective
policy actors create a link between antecedent and subsequent events in a policy sequence.
Public policies produce various types of outcomes which feed back into the policy process and
thus they become inputs into the policy process (Pierson 1993). Feedbacks aect the perceptions
and actions of government ocials and various types of stakeholders continuously and actively
involved in policy formulation and implementation. These reect over the feedback from policy
implementation when attempting to understand whether the policy works as intended or
whether it produces undesired unintended consequences (Lindblom 1959: 86).
As Heclo (1974: 305) pointed almost four decades ago, Governments not only power”…
they also puzzle. What he meant was that policy development was not only driven by powering,
but also by attempts to learn from experience and adopt the best available solutions to policy
problems. However, the two processes of powering and puzzling cannot easily be separated. Policy
actors act within a structure which constrains certain actions and facilitates others. This structure
may also facilitate and constrain which lessons are learned from policy experience and which are
ignored. Since policy, as an institution, also reects the outcome of past power struggles, learning
may be constrained by powering (Roederer-Rynning and Daugbjerg 2010: 31617).
2
Policy-makers have to respond to policy problems emerging from an evolving broader policy
context and to policy problems generated from within the policy itself. Though some policy
problems can be ignored, at least for some time, others require action to maintain output legiti-
macy; that is, demonstrating to a broader universe of policy participants that policy can eec-
tively address the problems with which it is confronted. The extent to which policy-makers are
able to respond to the policy problems depends on their ability to reect continuously over the
opportunities and constraints embodied in the policy structure and develop strategies to address
the challenges.
Each event in a policy sequence embodies a number of constraints and opportunities which
policy actors can utilise to prevent or to facilitate further evolution of the policy; while previous
events constrain certain policy responses, they provide opportunities for others. Prior events
Daugbjerg
478
foster and shape the crises that prepare the ground for new solutions, and they inuence the choices
made by actors in response to those crises (Haydu 2010: 36). Feedback process may reveal these
constraints and opportunities to reective and skilful reform advocates who want to change
policy in particular directions and to those who desire the status quo and at the most willing to
accept limited adjustments to address the most immediate policy problems. These perceived oppor-
tunities and constraints inuence the power balance within the policy process by empowering
some actors with particular interests and weaken others who hold diering views on the desired
direction of policy evolution regardless of whether or not these views are motivated by power
concerns or are outcomes of genuine learning processes.
As argued above, feedback involves an element of learning albeit constrained by the policy
structure. In a larger policy complex, small-scale experiments with new policy solutions may be
undertaken for more limited parts of the policy. Positive experiences with these can produce
positive learning eects modifying entrenched perceptions of certain types of policy instruments
among some policy-makers and thus create opportunities for extended and more intensive use
of these. For instance, the 1992 reform of the CAP shows how positive experiences with new
policy instruments can change preferences. The reform lowered the guaranteed minimum prices
by a third and introduced annual direct compensatory payments. This switched a substantial share
of farm support from indirect price support, in which subsidies to farmers were paid through
articially high consumer prices, to direct payments. The farm unions were strongly opposed to this
change because it would make farm support look like social benets (Daugbjerg 2009). However,
the compensatory payments proved much more popular than anticipated in the farm commu-
nity (Moyer and Josling 2002: 194). Farmers learned that direct payments increased their income
security and safeguarded them against drastic income losses from, for example, poor harvests
(ibid.). Since the early 1990s, direct payments to farmers have been unquestioned and an integral
and growing component of EU farm policy.
On the contrary, negative policy experiences may produce counter-reactions precluding the
increased use of such instruments and perhaps even policy reversal. However, such learning eects
may not materialise in policy change until the power balance shifts in favour of those interests
desiring an eective response to the policy problems. For instance, surplus production emerged
as a major problem in the EUs agricultural policy in the late 1970s and early 1980s. In the dairy
sector, surplus production was eectively dealt with by introducing dairy quotas in 1984. In the
arable sectors, the problem was not eectively addressed until 1992 when compulsory set-aside
of arable farm land was introduced (Daugbjerg 2012). The 1992 reform of the main arable policy
sectors demonstrates that negative feedback can change the power balance within a policy sub-
system. Subsidised exports of EU surplus production had triggered the anger of the United
States and other cereals exporting countries and therefore the EU was unable to avoid farm trade
became an integral part of the GATT negotiating agenda (Daugbjerg and Swinbank 2009). This
led to a shift in the power balance between the EU Commission and the Council of Agri-
culture Minsters in favour of former and eventually enabled substantial reform of the CAP
(Coleman and Tangermann 1999).
Feedbacks may reveal policy inconsistencies which are counterproductive in relation to the
objectives to be achieved within the policy eld. Specic measures may pull policy in dierent
directions and in some instances even neutralise the eects of each other. Such eects may be
ignored, particularly in situations in which contradictory measures have been deliberately
introduced to create or maintain a delicate balance between dierent groups of stakeholder with
opposing interests. However, when these inconsistent measures start generating eects that
threaten the core functions of the policy, and particularly when this amounts to a crisis, policy
change becomes inevitable.
Process sequencing
479
The most likely policy responses to learning feedbacks are those which are seen as repre-
senting the logical continuation of the direction set by the previous event in the policy sequence.
In situations in which the distance between the existing policy design and the policy changes
which from a rational perspective would be required to solve the problems is too large to be
undertaken in one step for political reasons, policy change will tend to be gradual. In some, but
more rare, situations the change of policy direction may be more abrupt and substantial. This
tends to happen when contextual changes provoke a policy crisis and immediate response is needed.
But even in these situations the policy response may grow out from the previous events in the
policy sequence (Howlett and Rayner 2006: 7). Learning feedbacks from previous events in the policy
sequence are most likely to impact on policy responses in situations in which the level of poli-
ticisation is low. As the level of politicisation increases, the less likely it is that learning will
inuence policy responses. Rather, policy-makers will exercise power to attempt moving policy
in a particular direction when responding to policy problems and as a result learning processes
might be sidelined (Pierson 1993: 61718).
The causal connection to previous policy events in such politicised situations may be a new
measure introduced in a previous reform to address a particular problem. This can be utilised to
legitimise a full-scale use of the new measures within the policy even when it was originally aimed
at a more marginal problem or was limited to solve a temporary problem. Policy-makers use
precedent to legitimise policy change by claiming that the new measures have indeed already
been applied within the policy and that its extended use is a logical continuation of the direction of
policy evolution previously set out. Reform advocates can, thus, construct precedent to support
their interests in moving policy in a particular direction. Precedent can be a quite powerful political
tool. Even though a new measure may be insignicant when introduced, or appear so, it may
sow the seeds for a sequence of policy adjustment amounting to substantial change over time.
For instance, the introduction of the so-called Small Farmers Scheme in 2001 to simplify
administrative procedures in EU agricultural policy demonstrates that a policy change aimed at
addressing a relatively limited problem can form a powerful precedent for more comprehensive
reform later on. The scheme oered farmers receiving less than 1,250 in direct aid payments
annually to transform these payments into a single at rate payment based on a historical
reference period. The introduction of this scheme seemed insignicant at the time. However, it
introduced a new form of direct aid payments to farmers. The direct payments introduced in
1992 required farmers to produce certain crops of keep particular types of livestock. The pay-
ments of the Small Farmers Scheme were not linked to production requirement and thus they
were what is known in agricultural policy terminology as decoupled payments. They eventually
spread to most of the commodity support schemes under the CAP in the 2003 policy reform.
Simplication served as the precedent legitimising the proposal to apply the decoupled farm
payment model, introduced in the Small Farmers Scheme, as the general support model in the
CAP. As stated by the Commission: The Small Farmers Scheme represents an important pre-
cedent for reducing the administrative burden (authors italics, Commission of the European
Communities 2002: 10).
Conclusion
In this chapter, process sequencing has been outlined and it has been argued that it is a distinct
analytical approach to studying policy evolution. Though it shares a temporal approach to the
study of policy-making with the path dependency approach, it is not based on the assumption
that public policy evolution is predetermined by a particular path sustained by a set of self-
reinforcing reproduction mechanisms. Rather, events in a policy sequence are connected by the
Daugbjerg
480
attempts of policy actors to solve policy problems. As Haydu (2010: 36) points out: Thinking
in terms of reiterated problem solving thus corrects the tendency of path dependency to make
historical trajectories overdetermined, with outcomes increasingly locked in over time. Policy
events in a temporal sequence are casually linked by the feedbacks from previous events. These
feedbacks disclose the constraints and opportunities for further reform to policy-makers. Though
constrained by the policy structure, these actors utilise learning eects and precedent to generate
support for policy changes. Thus, learning eects and precedent can provide causal link between
antecedent and subsequent policy events in a sequence.
Process sequencing is theoretically underdeveloped in terms of specifying the factors linking
antecedent and subsequent events in a policy sequence. In this chapter, some initial theoretical
considerations have been presented, focusing on the role of learning and precedent as casual links
between individual events in a policy sequence. It has also been emphasised that policy sequences
are the outcomes of human action and therefore analysis of sequencing must focus on the
interaction between structure and agency as policy-makers respond to policy problems.
Future research should concentrate on identifying other factors which potentially provide the
causal connection between antecedent and subsequent policy event, specify how they privilege
certain policy decisions and constrain others and explain how policy actors identify and conceive
of the opportunities and constraints embodied in previous policy events. However, it is important
not to over-theorise process sequencing. There is a risk that too much reliance on theory in iden-
tifying the causal mechanisms linking events in a sequence tempts analysts to downgrade ne-
grained empirical analysis of the way in which events are actually connected. As Bearman et al.
(1999, 508) caution: Theory involves denying data. Thin narrative accounts are the product of
specic theories that direct the [analyst] to identify some events as salient and to deny others as
not salient. Thus, the further development of process sequencing as an analytical framework to
studying policy evolution must balance between theory as an analytical tool to guide the search for
the causal mechanisms on the one hand and an open-minded empirical approach to how events
are casually connected in the specic case study on the other hand. Another but related chal-
lenge, not addressed in this chapter, is methodological. The challenge is to apply research methods
which enable the scholar to establish the causal connection between policy events and avoid
substituting causal analysis for accounts of a series of events which are temporally ordered but not
explained. Process tracing is the most obvious research method to apply in process sequencing.
The key focus of this research method is to develop tools which can help the scholar to establish
whether events in a sequence are causally connected (Beach and Pedersen 2012).
Notes
1 I would like to thank Darren Halpin, Adrian Kay and Rasmus Brun Pedersen for helpful comments on
earlier versions.
2 See Pierson (1993: 61419) and Bennett and Howlett (1992) for a discussion of the diculties of
applying the learning concept in empirical research.
Bibliography
Baumgartner, Frank R. and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and Instability in American Politics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1102.
Beach, Derek and Rasmus Brun Pedersen. 2012. Process Tracing Methods: Guidelines and Foundations, Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Bearman, Peter, Robert Faris and James Moody. 1999. Blocking the future: New solutions for old problems
in historical science, Social Science History 23(4): 50133.
Process sequencing
481
Bennett, Colin J. and Michael Howlett. 1992. The lessons of learning: Reconciling theories of policy
learning and policy change, Policy Science 25(3): 27592.
Bulmer, Simon. 2009. Politics in Time meets the politics of time: Historical institutionalism and EU timescape,
Journal of European Public Policy 16(2): 30724.
Cashore, B. and M. Howlett. 2007. Punctuating which equilibrium? Understanding thermostatic policy
dynamics in Pacic Northwest forestry, American Journal of Political Science 51(3): 53251.
Coleman, W.D. and S. Tangermann. 1999. The 1992 CAP reform, the Uruguay round and the commission,
Journal of Common Market Studies: 37(3): 385405.
——, G.D. Skogstad and M.M. Atkinson. 1997. Paradigm shifts and policy networks: Cumulative change
in agriculture, Journal of Public Policy 16(3): 273 301.
Commission of the European Communities. 2002. Communication from the Commission to the Council and the
European Parliament. Mid-Term Review of the Common Agricultural Policy, COM(2002)394, Brussels: CEC.
Daugbjerg, Carsten. 2009. Sequencing in public policy: The evolution of the CAP over a decade, Journal
of European Public Policy 16(3): 395411.
—— 2012. Globalization and internal policy dynamics in the reform of the Common Agricultural
Policy, in Jeremy Richardson (ed.) Constructing a Policy-making State? Policy Dynamics in the EU, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
——and Alan Swinbank. 2009. Ideas, Institutions and Trade: The WTO and the Curious Role of EU Farm
Policy in Trade Liberalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hay, Colin. 1995. Structure and agency, in D. Marsh and G. Stoker (eds) and Methods of Political Science.
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
—— 1998. The tangled webs we weave: The discourse, strategy and practice of networking, in David
Marsh (ed.) Comparing Policy Networks. Buckingham: Open University Press, 3351.
—— 2002. Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction.
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Haydu,
Jerey. 1998. Making use of the past: Time periods as cases to compare and as sequences of
problem solving, American Journal of Sociology 1(2): 33971.
—— 2010. Reversal of fortune: path dependency, problem solving, and temporal analysis, Theory and
Society 39(1): 3948.
Heclo, Hugh. 1974. Modern Social Policy in Britain and Sweden. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Howlett, Michael and Jeremy Rayner. 2006. Understanding the historical turn in the policy sciences. A
critique of stochastic, narrative, path dependency and process-sequencing models of policy-making over
time, Policy Sciences 39(1): 118.
Jervis, R. 1997. System Eects: Complexity in Political and Social Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Krasner, S.D. 1984. Approaches to the state: Alternative conceptions and historical dynamics, Comparative
Politics 16(2): 22346.
Lindblom, Charles E. 1959. The science of muddling through”’, Public Administration Review 19(2): 7988.
Mahoney, J. 2000. Path dependence in historical sociology , Theory and Society 29(4): 50748.
——and Kathleen Thelen. 2010. A theory of gradual institutional changed, in James Mahoney and
Kathleen Thelen (eds) Explaining Institutional Change: Ambiguity, Agency, and Power. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Moyer, H.W. and T.E. Josling. 2002. Agricultural Policy Reform: Politics and Policy Process in the EC and the
US in the 1990s. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Pierson, P. 1993. When eect becomes cause: Policy feedback and political change, World Politics 45(4):
595628.
—— 2000a. Increasing returns, path dependence and the study of politics, American
Political Science Review
94(2): 25167.
—— 2000b. Not just
what, but when: Timing and sequence in political processes, Studies in American
Political Development 14 (spring): 7292.
—— 2003. Big, slow moving, and invisible: Macrosocial processes in the study of comparative poli-
tics, in J. Mahoney and D. Rueschemeyer (eds) Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 177207.
Rhodes, R.A.W and David Marsh. 1992. New directions in the study of policy networks, European
Journal of Political Research 21(12): 181202.
Richardson, J.J and A.G. Jordan. 1979. Governing under Pressure: The Policy Process in a Post-Parliamentary
Democracy. Oxford: Robertson.
Roederer-Rynning, Christilla and Carsten Daugbjerg. 2010. Power, learning or path dependency?
Investigating the roots of the European Food Safety Authority, Public Administration 88(2): 31530.
Daugbjerg
482
Rose, R. 1990. Inheritance before choice in public policy, Journal of Theoretical Politics 2(3): 26391.
Sabatier, Paul. 1988. An advocacy coalition framework of policy change and the role of policy-oriented
learning therein, Policy Sciences 21(2): 12968.
Sewell, William H. 1996. Three temporalities: Toward an eventful sociology, in Terence J. McDonald
(ed.) The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 24580.
Streeck, Wolfgang and Kathleen Thelen. 2005. Introduction: Institutional change in advanced political
economies, in Wolfgang Streeck and Kathleen Thelen (eds) Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in
Advanced Political Economies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 139.
Thelen, Kathleen. 1999. Historical institutionalism in comparative politics, Annual Review of Political Science
2: 369404.
—— 2003. How institutionalism evolves: Insights from comparative historical analysis, in J. Mahoney and
D. Rueschemeyer (eds) Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 20840.
—— and S. Steinmo. 1992. Historical institutionalism in comparative politics, in S. Steinmo, K. Thelen
and F. Longstreth (eds) Structuring Politics: Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Analysis. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 132.
Process sequencing
483
36
Learning from success and failure?
Allan McConnell
Introduction
A common sense view of the political world might expect policy-makers to seek success and avoid
failure. Such assumptions are echoed in the public language of policy and political elites, from pre-
sidents and prime ministers to government ministers and senior ocials. Stated success goals include
building on what already works, as well as learning from mistakes when policies fail or disaster strikes.
To what extent do such assumptions and ocial rhetoric accord with the realities of public
policy? Perhaps surprisingly, the phenomenon of policy success has been given scant attention in
the public policy literature (for exceptions, see Kerr 1976; Marsh and McConnell 2010; McConnell
2010a, 2010b). More has been written on aspects of failure, including policy ascoes, crises and
disasters, although the literature tends to concentrate on the management of acute episodes, rather
than on long-term repercussions (see Hogwood and Peters 1985; Dunleavy 1995; Bovens and
t Hart 1996; Bovens et al. 2001; Birkland 2007; Boin et al. 2005). The purpose of this chapter is to
build on the insights and implications of this relatively small group of literature (particularly that
of McConnell 2010a, 2010b) in order to oer a more nuanced analysis of the simple assumption
that policy-makers seek to cultivate success and avoid failure.
The chapter is structured as follows. First, it examines the innumerable methodological dif-
culties in conceiving of success and failure. Second, it deals with the issue of success as fact vs.
success as interpretation, and produces a working denition which allows us to conceive of success
(and failure) as occurring in three realms: processes, programmes and politics. Third, it argues
that by understanding the malleable, contested and multidimensional aspects of success, we are
better placed to understand why the common sense logic of learning from success and failure has
some validity, but not nearly as much as we might assume. Policymakers can certainly build on
existing successes and learn from failures, but they may also tolerate, mask, risk, exploit and
even cultivate failure.
The methodological difculties of ascertaining success and failure
Broadly speaking, public policy is whatever governments choose to do or choose not to do. We
know from the literature on policy instruments (see e.g. Hood and Margetts 2007; Howlett
484
2010) that governments have many tools at their disposal, from laissez-faire to active provision
of public services. They can refuse to intervene in industrial disputes, initiate anti-drink-driving
campaigns, set regulatory standards for food hygiene, impose new taxes, build public hospitals,
establish customs and immigration controls and send troops to foreign lands. What constitutes
success in making such policy choices? The issue is predictably contested and methodologically
dicult, as it is with many phenomena within the political and social sciences.
Diering perceptions: put simply, is success a matter of fact or a matter of interpretation? Broadly
speaking, there are two dierent tendencies often implicit in the literature and reecting
broader trends within the policy sciences.
One tendency is interpretive or discursive, leaning heavily towards the assumption that success
is in the eye of beholder (see e.g. Bovens and t Hart 1996; Fischer 1995, 2003). It is easy to see
why such a position has some analytical validity. For example, in relation to the coalition inter-
ventions in Iraq or Afghanistan, it is likely that no amount of argument or evidence would per-
suade anti-war campaigners that the incursions were successful in bringing peace and stability to
authoritarian regimes. It is also highly unlikely that animal rights activists would be persuaded that
legislation permitting drug testing on animals was successful because of the benets it provided in
developing vaccines, drugs and treatments. The corollary of this tradition is that success and failure
are little more than labels used by governments, commentators, the media and others, depending
on their values, acceptance of government goals and the means of achieving them.
A counter-tendency is in the rational-scientic tradition, which leans heavily towards the
assumption that policy outcomes are objective facts. Therefore, armed with the knowledge of
government goals, we simply gather evidence which can be matched against these goals in order
to ascertain an outcome of success or failure (see e.g. Gupta 2001; Davidson 2005). Again, it
is easy to see some analytical worth in this tradition, because government can achieve broadly
what it sets out to achieve, regardless of whether the goals and the outcomes are supported. No
amount of diering perceptions, for example, can refute the fact that a public school was built,
or that income taxes were levied and collected, or that NASA launched space shuttles into
space, or that Saddam Hussein was deposed as president of Iraq. One implication of the rational-
scientic tradition, therefore, is that, success and failure are matters of objectivity, with little or
no room for perceptions of the merits or otherwise of a policy.
Overall, we are confronted with the real diculty of how to conceive of success, when two
such apparently diametrically opposed positions are evident. We will return to this issue shortly.
Multiple benchmarks: no denitive standards exist, by which we can judge success or failure.
An examination of discourse surrounding policy success reveals a number of potential success
measures. They are not mutually exclusive and they may complement or conict, but they indicate
substantial diversity.
Implemented as intended e.g. public servants were ecient and eective in carrying out
instructions.
Original objectives were met e.g. target of 80 per cent of local property taxpayers, paying
their bills online.
Benet was achieved for the target group(s) e.g. welfare payments to farmers.
An improvement on a prior state of aairs e.g. unemployment has fallen by 2 per cent.
Criteria have been met which have wide value in that policy domain e.g. eciency in budgeting,
adherence to risk management standards in continuity planning, secrecy in intelligence.
The policy is supported by key interests e.g. citizens, key stakeholders, media.
The
policy is achieving more when compared to another jurisdiction e.g. one country doing
better than another
in dealing with the global nancial crisis.
Learning from success and failure
485
Benets outweigh the costs e.g. benets of waging war on another regime, outweigh the human
and nancial costs.
The policy is innovative e.g. using new technology to tackle online fraud.
The policy complies with moral, ethical or legal standards e.g. adherence to principles of
fairness; operates within the parameters of existing laws.
It seems, therefore, that success standards are malleable, to the point for example that a government
and its supporters, can claim policy success, while its opponents can claim failure. A June 2010
Gallup poll on President Obamas management of the BP Gulf of Mexico oil spill, revealed a
56 per cent approval rating from Democrats and Democratleaners, but only 11 per cent
approval from Republicans and Republican-leaners.
Dealing with shortfalls, ambiguities and con icts: success isnt all or nothing based on the achieve-
ment (or not) of a singular goal. Policy outcomes typically fall short of aspirations to varying
degrees, If a government seeks to eliminate a 30 billion dollar budget de cit, many outcomes
are possible, such as reductions to 28 billion, 20 billion, 10 billion and 5 billion. Yet there is no
scientic line that can be drawn to demarcate success from failure. In all likelihood, government
and its supporters will emphasise the importance of what has been achieved, while opponents
and critics will highlight the shortfalls.
Furthermore, it is by no means certain that outcomes will be clear and unambiguous. Evi-
dence may be lacking, stated goals may mask hidden agendas and success may produce unin-
tended consequences. Indeed, one of the most common diculties relates to the existence of
multiple and conicting goals where some are achieved and some not (indeed the achievement
of one may be at the expense of another). For example, police resources focused heavily on
crime investigation, may be at the expense of crime prevention. Similarly, a drive by schools to
increase educational achievement, may conict with a goal of increasing the number of pupils/
students from deprived backgrounds. In reality, therefore, policy outcomes are often messy,
requiring judgement on the signicance given to what has been achieved, weighed up against
the failures and the grey areas in between.
Success for whom? Public policy, by its very nature of intervening (or not) to persuade, nancially
reward/penalise, regulate and provide, typically benets some groups or interests by comparison
with others, albeit that the broader rationale is articulated as being in the public interest. So, for
example, the rights of smokers to smoke cigarettes, can be restricted in public places on the basis that
doing so limits passive smoking and improves public health. Similarly, income tax payers who have
no children, would be required to pay an increase in income tax that was levied specically for the
purpose of generating additional resources for schools. It is hard to escape the fact that a policy may
be successful for those to whom it brings rights and rewards, but may not be conceived as such by
those whose freedoms or resources are curtailed/reduced in order to achieve the broader goal.
Variance over time: it may be tempting to view policies as succeeding or failing, as though a
snapshot is able to capture policy outcomes at an appropriate point in time. Yet, to continue the
analogy, snapshots at dierent points in time might lead to dierent assessments. Apparent short-
term failure may produce long-term success, such as the great planning disaster of the Sydney
Opera house (see Hall 1982) and its transformation into an iconic, revenue-raising tourist attraction.
The opposite may be the case, where short-term success fades away to be replaced by condi-
tions more likely to be considered as failure. The 20089 global nancial crisis is a case in point,
where light touch regulation and faith in the eciency and self-corrective capacities of markets,
has been viewed widely in hindsight as producing unsustainable levels of protability. Analysing
policy success needs to contend with the existence of multiple and perhaps contradictory outcomes
over time.
McConnell
486
Isolating the policy eect: political science is home to multiple methods and approaches (Hay 2002)
and policy analysis is no dierent, including widely diering assumptions about how to evaluate
outcomes (for contrasting positions see e.g. Fischer 1995; Davidson 2005). The very fact that
multiple and conicting assumptions exist, is a clue to the diculties of explaining and assessing
policies and their outcomes. If, for example, we wanted to assess the success of a governments
anti-drugs advertisements, we would confront the fact that changes in drugs habits can be the
product of many factors such as availability of supply, family pressures, peer inuences, mass media
stories and individual psychologies. We would either need to operationalise all the main variables
and engage in rigorous statistical examination, or perhaps make a series of informed judgements,
based on imperfect and perhaps conicting evidence. In the policy sciences, it would be very
dicult to reach a universal consensus on our ability to isolate the outcome of a policy.
There are no magical answers to these questions, or solutions to any of the other methodo-
logical diculties. However, I would argue that rather than being deterred by such matters,
there is an opportunity to gain insight from them.
Moving forwards: the nature of policy success and policy failure
For heuristic purposes, we need to confront the issue of whether success is a fact or an inter-
pretation. I would argue that to side purely with one or the other is to be analytically blind to
important aspects of policy phenomena. A rational-scientic approach can never escape the exis-
tence of multiple interpretations and diering levels of support in plural societies. Equally, an inter-
pretive approach can never escape the reality that governments can do broadly what they set out to
do, regardless of whether the outcomes are perceived as successful. We need a conception of
success that recognises and embraces both. Accordingly, I propose the following denition:
A policy is successful if it achieves the goals that proponents set out to achieve and attracts
no criticism of any signicance and/or support is virtually universal.
(McConnell 2010b: 351)
The key advantage of this denition is that it manages to combine more objective-oriented
achievements, with perceptions of whether such achievements deserve the label of success,
depending on popular and stakeholder support (explicit or implicit) for the means and ends. An
example of success is the system of dams and dykes in the Netherlands, aimed at preventing about a
quarter of the countrys land mass being submerged by water, and universally supported among the
populace. Many matters of low politics on non-controversial issues may also fall into this category,
where government goals are achieved and there is no objection or criticism of any signicance.
It is also possible to conceive of a spectrum of outcomes (see McConnell 2010a, 2010b)
moving from durable or resilient success (where shortfalls in goal achievement are second best
but tolerable and sustainable), to conicted success (where achievements and support are nely
balanced with failures and criticism), through to precarious successes (where failures and criticism
outweigh some achievements and support) and nally to outright policy failure.
A policy fails if it does not achieve the goals that proponents set out to achieve, and
opposition is great and/or support is virtually non-existent.
(McConnell 2010: 357)
Failures may generate high levels of media interest (such as the poll tax in the UK) or they may
be contained within the realms of small policy subsystems, away from the glare of the media.
Learning from success and failure
487
Three realms of policy success
If we want to understand the dynamics of success and failure, a crucial step now needs to be taken in
developing our understanding. What governments do can usefully be split into three realms.
Table 36.1 provides ne detail and hence the discussion here is conned to making the general
point that governments can succeed and/or fail in each of these realms.
Process: among other things, governments dene problems, appraise options, design instruments,
engage with stakeholders and take decisions. Processes of policy formation involve strategies which,
if they succeed, allow governments to preserve their goals and policy instruments, produce
policy in a legitimate fashion, build sustainable coalitions, appear innovative and attract little or
no criticism for the process of policy formation. For example, a range of processes from adherence
to constitutional rules or norms, to utilising good practice in stakeholder engagement can form the
basis of successful and legitimate, coalition-building processes. If policy is about what governments
do, they do process and they may succeed and/or fail in this regard
Programmes: As we know, governments produce programmes, involving varying mixes of policy
instruments. Regardless of the process of policy formation, we may judge programmes separately,
to the extent of matching them against a number of possible indicators. They may be imple-
mented in line with objectives, achieve desired outcomes (such as the switchover from analogue
to digital television in Luxembourg, Finland and Sweden) create benet for the target group(s),
satisfy criteria valued highly in that policy domain (such as secrecy in the intelligence sector) and
attract widespread support or at least no criticism/opposition of any signicance. Governments
do programmes and they may succeed/and or fail in this realm.
Politics: the processes and programmes of governments also have political repercussions. They
can boost political reputations and electoral prospects, ease the business of governing through agenda
containment, contribute to desired policy trajectories, maintain broader governance agendas and
help to galvanise political support behind these moves. An example is Australian Prime Minister
Kevin Rudds 2007 historic sorry speech to aboriginal people for the forced removal of a
Table 36.1 The three realms of policy success
Process success Programme success Political success
Preserving government policy
goals and instruments
Implementation in line with
objectives
Enhancing electoral prospects or
reputation of governments and
leaders
Conferring legitimacy on the
policy
Achievement of desired
outcomes
Controlling policy agenda and
easing the business of governing
Building a sustainable coalition Creating benet for a target
group
Sustaining the broad values and
direction of government
Symbolizing innovation and
inuence
Meets policy domain criteria Opposition to political benets for
government is virtually
non-existent and/or support is
virtually universal
Opposition to process is virtually
non-existent and/or support is
virtually universal
Opposition to programme
aims, values, and means of
achieving them is virtually
non-existent, and/or support
is virtually universal
Source: Adapted from McConnell (2010b: Tables 1, 2 and 3)
McConnell
488
stolen generation of children from their families. Governments do politics and they may be
more, or less, successful in doing so.
Policy-making as the juggling of success and failure
There is no doubt that governments can learn from both successes and failures. Learning from
success involves a form of positive feedback, where policies deemed successful are reproduced
and expanded, such as the waves of privatisation of the late 1980s and 1990s. Learning from
failure can be described as negative feedback, where a form of self-correction ensures that fail-
ures are addressed. Corrections may involve the ne-tuning of existing policies (through, for
example, amended guidelines for front-line public housing ocials), the replacement of existing
policies with new ones (Australian gun law reforms after the 1996 Port Arthur massacre) or
even a paradigm realignment which sets the agenda for reform (arguably, pre- and post-global
nancial crisis shifts in political elite attitudes to debt, regulation and the free market).
Yet an implication of the foregoing discussion of success and failure, is that governments may
aspire to dierent successes. Indeed, doing so may involve prioritising some over others, and
using the malleable label of success to help legitimise their choices and direction. Failure in
some realms is often a precondition for success in others. Failures in some areas can be tolerated,
masked, risked, exploited and even cultivated in the pursuit of success elsewhere.
Tolerating failure
Public policy failures are everywhere. Judging how signicant they are, may involve Wildavskian
art rather than science. Nevertheless, some simple examples help to make broader points. Low
level failures involve small shortfalls, for example 97 per cent of welfare claims processed within
two weeks as opposed to a target of 98 per cent. There is no incentive to address such minor
failures if broader programme successes are evident and not compromised by the failures.
Moderate or medium-level failures may also be tolerated on the grounds that, on balance, the
programme successes are a price worth paying. The European Unions (EU) Common Agricultural
Policy is a good example. It does achieve key goals such as EU self-suciency and raising the
standards of farmers incomes, but has generated considerable criticism and controversy because
of its drain on the EU budget and production of huge surpluses. Supporters perceive it to be an
EU agship policy while opponents portray it more as the Titanic.
Dealing with such failures may also compromise political success. For example, few are likely
to disagree with a diagnosis of failure in relation to squalid high rise/tower blocks which are
home for some of the poorest and most vulnerable people in society. Yet is not dicult to see
why such failures may be tolerated, especially under conditions of economic stress and scal strin-
gency. Costs of reform would need to come from other programmes, potentially jeopardising
their success. Dealing with programmatic problems may also compromise political success. Exem-
plars are austerity measures, debt reduction programmes and eciency drives. Japanese Prime
Minister Hashimotoseciency drive in the banking sector in order to revive a struggling
economy underestimated the adverse political eects and was a major factor in his defeat at the
1998 general election. In 2011 similar political pressures were brought to bear on governments
in Greece, Spain and Ireland. The success of debt reduction programmes generates high risk of
political failure, at least in terms of popular support for governments.
Even high-level failures may be tolerated, or at least there may be attempts to suppress them,
if policy-makers consider that addressing the issues is likely to jeopardise programmatic and/or
political success. One such example is arguably the Guantanamo Bay detention camp under the
Learning from success and failure
489
Obama Administration, where innumerable ethical, human rights, legal and logistical problems
continue, but closure of the camp may well jeopardise the success of the incarceration programme
itself (what to do with approximately 170 potential terrorists when there is a lack of a strong
evidence base to convict?) as well as jeopardising the political goals of the Obama Administra-
tion to ght terrorism in a climate where approximately six out of every ten voters in America,
do not want the camp to be closed.
A more general point needs to be made. Policy problems vary in complexity, from simple
well-structured problems and no clear solutions, to wicked issues with multiple and complex
causes, and absence of widely accepted and authoritative solutions (Head 2008; Hoppe 2010).
Also, signals of failure are often vague and ambiguous, subject to multiple (mis)interpretations,
leading to policy-makers processing information disproportionately sometimes over- or
under-reacting to signs of failure (Jones and Baumgartner 2005).
In sum, failures are often tolerated because to do otherwise would be to consume valuable
agenda time, as well as engage in costly reforms with no guarantee that they will work. Political
success in terms of easing the business of governing and keeping broader policy and paradigm
values on track, is often at the expense of tolerating failures.
Masking failure
It is not only that failures may be tolerated, but they may also be masked, intentionally or
unintentionally, by the activities of policy-makers.
The use of political language can push failures, to the lower realms of political agendas.
Edelmans (1977) famous dictum, words that succeed and policies that fail, was used to refer to
political promises and reassurances which hid chronic inequalities, injustices and policy failure,
especially in the area of social welfare. Deborah Stone (2002) provides a more detailed analysis of
the ways in which metaphors, synecdoche and other linguistic devices, can be used to suppress
policy problems. Phrases such as storm in a teacup or freak events can be used to dampen the
salience of failures, while those that seek to elevate the issues can be labelled as trouble-makers
or even enemies of democracy. Indeed, the argumentative turn in policy analysis (see e.g. Majone
1989; Fischer and Forester 1993: Hodgson and Irving 2007), illustrates the importance of argu-
mentation and framing, with dierent interests battling to elevate and even dominate political
discourse with their views.
Policymakers may also produce placebo policies (where there is a high symbolic content in
terms of appearing to tackle the problem, with a low likelihood that they will do so, see
McConnell 2010a). For example, Clarke (1999) in his work on contingency planning for crises
and disasters, argues that plans are primarily of symbolic value (we are prepared and in control)
rather than operational value. Sharman (2011) in his detailed study of the regulation of money
laundering, explores the rapid diusion and copying of regulations as being politically successful
policy failures. They demonstrate political success because they create the appearance of good
governance, strong regulation and zero tolerance of money laundering, but outcomes are patchy
at best and ineective at worst, particularly in developing countries. For example, the small
Pacic island of Nauru (population 11,000) has developed state-of-the-art anti-money laun-
dering legislation but it has no nancial sector of any kind not even a bank or an ATM! Even
institutional reforms and restructuring can have strong symbolic and feel good elements, without
necessarily minimising long-term, chronic problems. The creation of the Department of Home-
land Security (DHS) in the United States symbolised an integrated response to the threat of
terrorist attacks, but in reality has arguably done little to minimise the behaviour of actors in
policy subsystems (May et al. 2009).
McConnell
490
Often, when policies fail and/or when crisis and disaster strikes, inquiries are used in order to
nd out what went wrong and learn lessons for the future. We might expect them to reveal, rather
than mask, failures and their causes. Yet as argued by recent literature on the politics of inquiries
(Stanley and Manthorpe 2004; Kitts 2006; Prasser 2006; Birkland 2007; Boin et al. 2008), investi-
gations may be steered away from examining potential causal factors, as a consequence of terms
of reference, membership and funding. In essence, when failures occur, potential underlying
causal factors may be insulated from investigation, in order protect the values and policies which
sustain broader success trajectories. In 20056 when the privatised Australian Wheat Board Ltd
was investigated by the Cole inquiry for paying kickbacks’’to Saddam Husseins regime in
contravention of UN sanctions, the terms of reference did not encompass inter alia the minimalist
regulatory regime emanating from the original privatisation, that may have helped explain why
the company had freedom to engage in illicit nancial activities (McConnell et al. 2008).
A related issue is blame games, involving the deection of attention towards particular indi-
viduals, interests, institutions, technical and climatic/geophysical factors (see Weaver 1986; Hood
2011). The purpose in deecting attention towards a particular actor or set of conditions, is also
to deect attention away from other factors. In other words, blame games may be an attempt to
shore up the returns of policy success.
As Schattschneider (1960) and Bacharach and Bartatz (1970) argued convincingly many years ago,
political systems develop a mobilization of bias which is capable of ltering out grievances and
failures. The masking of failure is the ip aside of dominant biases, geared towards particular
aspirations of programmatic and political success.
Generating the risk of failure
Policymakers cannot predict the future with absolute certainty. They can certainly engage in
small policy trials, use ex ante evaluations and attempt to model outcomes, but there are always
elements of uncertainty and contingency (Shapiro and Bedi 2007). All policy-making involves
an element of judgement, sometimes instinctive and sometimes the product of careful scenario
planning, in relation to the risks (May 2005; Althaus 2008). All policy processes carry some
possibility of failure. To put this in the language of this chapter, attempts to achieve process
success carry risks of programme and political failure (see McConnell 2010a). For example:
log-rolling and horse trading carry the risk of diering interpretations at the implementation
stage, actors not behaving as agreed, and changing socio-economic and political contexts
rendering the agreements unworkable;
evidence-based policy-making brings the risk of policy-making being informed by skewed
or incorrect evidence, or being merely the legitimating basis for policy and political trajectories
that bring strong contradictions;
deliberation and stakeholder engagement can be little more than the legitimating framework for
policy and political pathways, bringing the risk of inated expectations which cannot be met;
use of strong executive power to push through policies and legislation carries the risk of
political backlash, as well as programmes lacking sucient scrutiny to ensure eective
implementation;
policy transfers from other jurisdictions carry the risk of being uninformed, incomplete or
inappropriate for the new policy context.
The list could be longer but the basic point is clear. Every strategic process strategy brings
opportunities but also risks. What constitutes process success for policy-makers in producing
Learning from success and failure
491
their desired policies through constitutionally and quasi-constitutionally legitimate means, can carry
the longer-term risk of producing programmes which fail to full intended goals, while backring
politically on government agendas and compromising its broader political goals and pathways.
Failure is not inevitable but failure is often a prospect, to varying degrees and depending on the
context such as the degree of politicisation surrounding the issue and likely levels of support/
opposition. Public policy-making and accepting the risk of failure go hand in hand.
Cultivating/creating/exploiting failure
The logic of the policy cycle approach is that policy-making is driven by problems in search of
solutions. However, as garbage can theory indicates, the opposite may be the case. Policy can
be driven by solutions in search of problems in order to justify an intended course of action.
The literature on crisis and disaster makes similar points, that crisis conditions can be capitalised
upon and even exploited in order to achieve longer-term programmes and political goals (Klein
2007; Boin et al. 2009). For example, often cited allegations include the existence of weapons
of mass destruction in Iraq as a means of legitimating the coalition invasion of Iraq in 2002, and
asylum seekers throwing their children overboard a stricken vessel bound for Australian waters,
in order to legitimate immigration reform. Crises can be an opportunity to boost political careers
and demonstrate tness for oce. For example, the 2002 oods in Germany helped to provide
the foundation for the invigoration of Chancellor Schröder, some six weeks before the federal
election - helping his party to victory (Bytzek 2008). In the wake of the 9/11 attacks, George
W. Bushs approval ratings soared to the highest in US polling history. As Rahm Emanuel,
Barack Obamas Chief of Sta, stated: you never want a good crisis to go to waste (Washington
Post: 6 March 2009). Overall, therefore, failure may be sought out and even cultivated, in order
to pave the way for programme and political success.
Conclusion
Conventional wisdom and governmental rhetoric lean heavily towards the promise that political
and policy elites will build on successes and learn from failures. Leaving aside the issue that what
constitutes learning is a value assumption, change and learning can certainly happen. However,
it is far from an automatic or reexive process. The nature of policy success is contested and
riddled with methodological diculties, requiring a value judgement in terms of attaching the label
of success to outcomes, depending on the salience given to achievements and the signicance
given to shortfalls and ambiguities. There is a degree of malleability in the way that policies can
be framed, as successful or otherwise.
When we also factor in the existence of dierent forms of successes in the process, programme
and political realms of policy, it is evident that failures and lack of learning from them are
not only commonplace, but often necessary because they have been disregarded in the pursuit
of longer-term success goals. Successful processes (such as a government rushing a bill through a
legislature) in order to achieve its goal, may run the risk (conceived of as acceptable risk by
policy-makers) of programme failure through ill-thought-out legislation, and even of political
failure if the issue is high prole and politically partisan. Or, successful programmes, especially if
they are ruthlessly e cient in achieving highly contested goals, may carry the risk of political
failure. Alternatively, ineective programmes tackling dicult and perhaps wicked issues, may
be tolerated and even promoted, if it suits political success aspirations in maintaining control of
agendas through the appearance of tackling problems. Colloquially, we might refer to this as
good politics but bad policy.
McConnell
492
As indicated by the argument and analysis in this chapter, failures are not always abhorrent to
policy-makers. Failures can be tolerated, masked, risked, cultivated and even exploited in order
to pave the way for process, programme and political goals. Policymaking involves trade-os
and risk taking, juggling the hope of some successes, with the acceptance and even desirability
of failure.
Bibliography
Althaus, C. 2008. Calculating Political Risk. Sydney: University of New South Wales Press.
Bacharach, P. and M. Baratz. 1970. Power and Poverty: Theory and Practice. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Birkland, T.A. 2007. Lessons of Disaster: Policy Change after Catastrophic Events. Washington, DC: Georgetown
University Press.
Boin, A., A. McConnell and P. t Hart eds. 2008. Governing after Crisis: The Politics of Investigation,
Accountability and Learning. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
——,P.t Hart and A. McConnell. 2009. Towards a theory of crisis exploitation: Political and policy
impacts of framing contests and blame games, Journal of European Public Policy 16(1): 81106.
——,P.t Hart, E. Stern and B. Sundelius. 2005. The Politics of Crisis Management: Public Leadership under
Pressure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bovens, M.P. and P. t Hart. 1996. Understanding Policy Fiascoes. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.
——,P.t Hart, and B.G. Peters (eds). 2001. Success and Failure in Public Governance: A Comparative Analysis.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Bytzek, E. 2008. Flood response and political survival: Gerhard Schröder and the 2002 Elbe oods in
Germany, in A. Boin, A. McConnell and P. t Hart (eds) Governing after Crisis: The Politics of Investigation,
Accountability and Learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 85 113.
Clarke, L.B. 1999. Mission Improbable: Using Fantasy Documents to Tame Disasters. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Davidson, E.J. 2005. Evaluation Methodology Basics: The Nuts and Bolts of Sound Evaluation. Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage.
Dunleavy, P. 1995. Policy disasters: Explaining the UKs record, Public Policy and Administration 10(2): 5270.
Edelman. 1977. Political Language: Words that Succeed and Policies that Fail. New York: Academic Press.
Fischer, F. 1995. Evaluating Public Policy. Chicago: Nelson-Hall Publishers.
—— 2003. Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative Practices. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
——and J. Forester. 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Gupta, Dipak K. 2001. Analyzing Public Policy: Concepts, Tools, and Techniques. Washington, DC: Congressional
Quarterly
Inc.
Hall, P.G. 1982. Great
Planning Disasters. Berkeley, CA, University of California Press.
Hay, C. 2002. Political Analysis. Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan.
Head, B.W. 2008. Wicked problems in public policy, Public Policy 3(2): 10118.
Hodgson, S.M. and Z. Irving (eds). 2007. Policy Reconsidered: Meanings, Politics and Practices. Bristol: Policy
Press.
Hood, C. 2011. The Blame Game: Spin, Bureaucracy and Self-preservation in Government. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
——and H.Z. Margetts. 2007. The Tools of Government in the Digital Age. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Hogwood, B.W. and B.G. Peters. 1985. The Pathology of Public Policy . Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hoppe, R. 2010. The Governance of Problems: Puzzling, Powering and Participation. Bristol: Policy Press.
Howlett, M. 2010. Designing Public Policies: Principles and Instruments. New York: Routledge.
Jones, B.D. and F.R. Baumgartner. 2005. The Politics of Attention: How Government Prioritizes Problems.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kerr, D.H. 1976. The logic of policy and successful policies, Policy Sciences 7(3): 35163.
Kitts, K. 2006. Presidential Commissions and National Security: The Politics of Damage Control. Boulder, CO:
Lynne Rienner.
Klein, N. 2007. The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism. New York: Metropolitan Books and
Henry Holt.
Learning from success and failure
493
McConnell, A. 2010a. Understanding Policy Success: Rethinking Public Policy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
—— 2010b. Policy success, policy failure and grey areas in-between, Journal of Public Policy, 30(30): 34562.
—— A.Gauja and L. Botterill. 2008. Policy ascos, blame management and AWB limited: The Howard
governments escape from the Iraq wheat scandal, Australian Journal of Political Science 43(4): 599-616.
Majone, G. 1989. Evidence, Argument, and Persuasion in the Policy Process. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Marsh, D. and A. McConnell, A. 2010. Towards a framework for establishing policy success, Public
Administration 88(2): 5867.
May, P.J. 2005. Policy maps and political feasibility, in I. Geva-May (ed.) Thinking Like a Policy Analyst:
Policy Analysis as a Clinical Profession. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 12751.
——, J. Sapotichne and S. Workman. 2009. Widespread policy disruption: Terrorism, public risks, and
homeland security, Policy Studies Journal 37(2): 17194.
Pawson, R. 2006. Evidence-based Policy: A Realist Perspective. London: Sage.
Prasser, S. 2006. Royal Commissions and Public Inquiries in Australia. Chatswood, NSW: LexisNexis Butterworths.
Schattschneider, Elmer Eric. 1960. The Semisovereign People: A Realists View of Democracy in America. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Schneider, A.L. and H. Ingram. 1997. Policy Design for Democracy. Lawrence, KS: University Press of
Kansas.
Shapiro, I. and S. Bedi. (eds). 2007. Political Contingency: Studying the Unexpected, the Accidental and the
Unforeseen. New York: New York University Press.
Sharman, J.C. 2011. The Money Laundry: Regulating Global Finance in the Criminal Economy. Ithaca, NY and
London: Cornell University Press.
Stanley, N. and J. Manthorpe. 2004. The Age of the Inquiry: Learning and Blaming in Health and Social Care.
London: Routledge.
Stone, D. 2002. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Making, 2nd edn. New York: W.W. Norton.
Weaver, R.K. 1986. The politics of blame avoidance, Journal of Public Policy 6(4): 371 98.
McConnell
494
Author index
Aaron, P. and Musto, D. 145
Abbott, A. 233, 407
Abbott, D., Brown, S. and Wilson, G. 378
Abelson, Donald 6
Aberbach, J.D., Putnam, R.D. and Rockman.,
B.A. 337
Ackleson, Jason 184
Ackrill, R.W. and Kay, A. 469
Adam, Barbara 455
Adams, B. 440, 441
Adams, Gordon 338
Adelle, C. et al. 24647, 249
Adelle, Camilla xi, 24454
Adler, E. and Haas, P.M. 237, 240
Adshead, M. 15657
Agranoff, R. and McGuire, M. 361, 363
Agranoff, R. and Yildiz, M. 369
Agranoff, Robert xi, 36173
Ahn, C.S. 337
Ahn, T.K. 121
Ahuja, A., Kremer, M. and Zwane, A.P. 415
Ajzen, I. and Fishbein, M. 125
Albæk, E., Green-Pedersen, C. and Nielsen, L.B.
172
Albert, M. and Laberge, S. 233
Albrechts, L. 233
Albright, Elizabeth A. 129, 133, 186
Albrow, Martin 332, 334
Alchian, A.A. and Demsetz, H. 239
Alesina, Alberto 85
Alford, J. and OFlynn, J. 436
Aligica, P. and Boettke, P. 91
Aligica, Paul Dragos xi, 8797
Allan, J.P. and Scruggs, L. 32, 37
Allcott, H. and Mullainanthan, S. 423, 424
Allen, Linda 121
Allio, L. 244, 246
Allison, G. and Zelikow, P. 338
Allison, Graham 21, 338
Almond, G.A. and Genco, S.J. 59
Almond, Gabriel A. 62
Alter, C. and Hage, J. 364
Althaus, C. 491
Althaus, C., Bridgman, P. and Davis, G. 434
Altman, J.A. and Petkus, E. 302
Ameringer, Carl F. 133
Anderson, J. 300
Andersson, Krister P. 120, 121
Andersson, Magnus 129
Andrews, M., McConnell, J. and Wescott, A. 376,
381
Anglund, S.M. 304
Angrist, J. and Pischke, J.S. 416, 419
Angrist, J., Imbens, G.W. and Rubin, D.B. 430n9
Ansell, C. and Gash, A. 341
Appleby, Paul 333
Araral Jr., Eduardo xi, 11524
Argyris, C. and Schön, D. 106
Aristotle 102, 201
Armstrong, E.M., Carpenter, D. and Hojnacki.,
M.E. 280
Aronson, P.H. and Ordeshook, P.C. 80
Arrow, Kenneth J. 76, 78, 8384, 466
Arthur, W.B. 402, 466
Ashford, Douglas E. 362
Atkinson, M. and Coleman, W. 19
Baccaro, L. 36
Baccaro, L. and Simoni, M. 36
Bachrach, P. and Baratz, M.S. 167, 491
Baiocchi, G. 442
Baker, R. 340, 341
Baker, W.H., Addams, H.L. and Davis, B. 440,
441
Bal, Mieke 103
Balfour, D.L. and Mesaros, W. 103
Balla, S.J. and Wright, J.R. 280
Balla, Steven J. 280
Banerjee, A.V. 41516, 419, 427
Banerjee, A.V. and Duo, E. 416, 419, 420, 426
Banerjee, A.V. et al. 415
Barabási, Albert-László 282
495
Bardach, Eugene 7, 10, 34, 244, 369, 370
Bardhan, P. 416
Barnes, M. et al. 438
Barnett, M.N. and Finnemore, M. 339
Barnett, P. et al. 22
Barrow, C.J. 9, 246, 248
Bartels, L.M. 206
Barthes, Roland 106
Barzelay, Michael 335, 340, 405
Basu, K. 416
Basurto, Xavier 120
Bateson, Gregory 192
Baumgartner, F.R. and Jones, B.D. 18, 139, 140,
141, 142, 143, 144, 145, 146, 147, 150n2, 167,
172, 175, 177, 178, 179, 193, 201, 205, 281,
452, 453, 474, 477
Baumgartner, F.R. and Leech, B.L. 282
Baumgartner, F.R., De Boef, S.L. and Boydstun,
A.E. 193, 201
Baumgartner, F.R. et al. 143, 144, 145, 146, 147,
14849, 281, 452
Baumgartner, F.R., Green-Pedersen, C. and
Jones, B.D. 167, 190
Baumgartner, F.R., Jones, B.D. and Leech, B.L.
205
Baumgartner, Frank R. 146
Beach, D. and Pedersen, R.B. 481
Beard, Adrian 191
Bearman, P., Faris, R. and Moody, J. 481
Beck, James M. 335
Beck, Ulrich 63
Becker, Gary S. 85, 282
Beetham, David 23, 334
Behn, R.D. 34
Béland, D. 184, 403
Bendor, J. and Hammond, T.H. 21
Bendor, J., Moe, T.M. and Shotts, K.W. 321, 325
Bendor, J., Taylor, S. and van Gaalen, R. 84
Bendor, Jonathan 277, 283
Benington, J. 436
Benjamin, M. 353
Bennett, C.J. 34, 404
Bennett, C.J. and Howlett, M. 24, 35, 404, 407
Bennett, W. Lance 170, 178
Bennett, W.L. and Feldman, M.S. 103
Bennett, W.L., Lawrence, R.C. and Livingston, S.
170
Benson, J.K. 158
Berger, P. and Luckmann, T. 100, 103
Berry, F.S. and Berry, W.D. 144, 404, 406
Bertrand, M. et al. 431n23
Best, R. 177, 184
Bevir, M. and Richards, D. 161, 338
Bikhchandani, S., Hirshleifer, D. and Welch, I.
282
Biller, R.P. 34
Bina, O. 245
Bingham, G. 357
Bingham, L.B., Nabatchi, T. and Leary, R.O.
438, 444
Birkland, T.A. and Lawrence, R.G. 175, 176, 181
Birkland, Thomas A. xi, 143, 17588, 206, 484,
491; garbage can model (GCM), work with
32627
Black, Duncan 76, 78, 79, 80
Black, Julia 67
Blackburn, J. and Holland, J. 381
Blair, Tony 65
Blais, A. and Dion, S. 84, 336
Blalock, A.B. 436
blame games 491
Blankart, C.B. and Koester, G.B. 85
Blankart, Charles B. 65
Blankenau, Joe 184
Blau, P.M. and Scott, W.R. 332
Bloom, H. et al. 415
Blyth, Mark 451
Boardman, A.E. et al. 5
Bobrow, D. and Dryzek, J. 105, 217, 255, 256,
258
Bochel, H.M. and Duncan, S. 108
Bogason, P. and Toonen, T.A.J. 363
Boin, A., McConnell, A. and t Hart, P. 484, 491,
492
Boje, David M. 103
Bond, A. and Morrison-Saunders, A. 249
Boner, P.A. et al. 442
Bonoli, G. 32, 34, 36, 37
Boom, H. 317n3
Borgatti, S.P., Everett, M.G. and Freeman, L.C.
241n2
Boston, J., Church, S. and Bale, T. 6
Boston, Jonathan 8, 340
Boswell, C. 405
Bots, Pieter W.G. xi, 25569
Bourdieu, Pierre 107, 239
Boushey, Graeme xii, 13852, 282
Bovens, M.P. and t Hart, P. 484, 485
Bovens, M.P., t Hart, P. and Peters, B.G. 484
Bovens, M., t
Hart, P. and
Kuipers, S. 43435,
443
Bowornwathana, B. and Poocharoen, O. 338
Bowornwathana, Bidhya 338
Boxer, Sarah. B. 200
Boyce, Mary E. 103
Boydstun, Amber E. 282
Boykoff, M. and Boykoff, J.M. 208
Boykoff, Maxwell 207, 208, 209
Boyne, George A. 84
Bradford, N. 405, 408
Braithwaite, J. and Draos, P. 63
Braun, D. and Gilardi, F. 34, 404, 406
Braybrooke, D. and Lindblom, C.E. 21, 287,
28889, 291, 292
Author index
496
Braybrooke, David 289
Breeman, G. et al. 168
Brehm, J. and Gates, S. 280
Bressers, H.T.A. and OToole, L.J. 22
Breton, A. and Wintrobe, R. 84
Breton, Albert 79
Breunig, C. and Jones, B. 147, 149, 150n10
Breunig, C. and Koski, C. 144, 147, 148
Brewer, G. and DeLeon, P. 255, 256
Brewer, G.D. 3334
Brinkerhoff, Derick W. xii, 37483
Brinkerhoff, D.W. and Crosby, B.L. 37980
Brinkerhoff, D.W. and Ingle, M. 377
Brinkerhoff, Jennifer M. xii, 37483
British Pension Commission 409
Brooks, David 220
Brooks, S.M. 34, 404, 410
Brown, Gordon (and government of) 65
Brown, Lawrence D. 292
Brown, Steven R. 278
Brown, T.L. and Potoski, M. 363
Browne, William P. 54, 156
Bruner, Jerome 102
Bruns, Bryan Rudolph 120
Bryson, J.M. and Crosby, B.C. 299, 300, 302, 303
Buchanan, James 7677, 78, 82
Buchanan, J.M. and Tullock, G. 78, 79, 80, 83,
98
Buckman, G. and Diesendorf, M. 22
Bulmer, M. 407, 408, 409
Bulmer, Simon 473
Burnham, James 335
Burnier, DeLysa 178
Burns, John F. 196
Burstein, P. 155, 156
Busch, P.-O. and Jörgens, H. 34, 37
Busch, P.-O., Jörgens, H. and Tews, K. 34
Busenberg, George J. 184
Bush, George W. 223, 492
Bushouse, Brenda K. 121
Butcher, Mike 197
Butler, R. 299, 302
Bytzek, E. 492
Cahill, A,G. and Overman, E.S. 20
Callahan, K. 437
Callon, Michel 1067
Camerer, C.F. and Thaler, R.F. 276
Camerer, Colin F. 276
Cameron, David 196, 197
Campbell, A.L. 403
Campbell, C. and Szablowski, G. 337
Campbell, J.L. 469
Cao, X. 405
Capano, G. and Howlett, M. 454
Capano, Giliberto xii, 45161
Carley, Michael 20, 246
Carlson, C. 354
Carlson, Deven 5
Carpenter, D. and Sin, G. 179, 185
Carpenter, D., Esterling, K. and Lazer, D. 159
Carpenter, Daniel 280
Carson, L. 442
Carson, L. et al. 438
Carstensen, Martin B. 19
Cartwright, N. 430n10
Cashmore, M., Bond, A. and Cobb, D. 249
Cashore, B. and Howlett, M. 144, 453, 474
Castells, Manuel 363
Castles, F.G. 32, 37
Castles, F.G. and Mitchell, D. 32
Cecot, C., Hahn, R.W. and Renda., A. 249
Cerny, Philip 45
Chaker, A. et al. 245
Chapman, R.A. 408
Chattopadhyay, Paresh 335
Checkel, J. 23839
Chen, Huey-Tsyh 11
Chenoweth, E. and Clarke, S.E. 184
Cheung, A.B.L. and Scott, I. 340
Choe, Jaesong 121
Chomsky, N. and Herman, E. 101
Chong, Dennis 282
Christensen, T. 332
Chung, K.H. and Cox, R.A.K. 282
Chwieroth, J. 239
Clark, C.D. and Russell, C.S. 22
Clark, J. 406, 410
Clark, William R. 59
Clarke, L.B. 490
Clasen, J. and Clegg, D. 32
Clasen, J. and Siegel, N.A. 32, 37
Clayton, R. and Pontusson, J. 34
Cobb, R.W. and Elder, C.D. 18, 167, 175, 176,
177, 190, 200, 205
Cobb, R.W. and Elder, C.W. 5
Cobb, R.W. and Ross, M.H. 175, 193
Cobb, R.W., Keith-Ross, J. and Ross, M.H. 18,
177, 190
Cobden, R., Mitrany, D. and Ohmae, K. 63
Coglianese, C. 357
Cohen, Bernard C. 205
Cohen, M., March, J. and Olsen, J. 51, 54, 278,
303, 320, 321
Cohen, W.M. and Levinthal, D.A. 24
Cole, R. and Caputo, D. 338
Coleman, Eric 121
Coleman, J.S. 238
Coleman, J.S. and Skogstad, G. 235
Coleman, W.D. and Perl, A. 47, 52
Coleman, W.D. and Skogstad, G. 19, 47
Coleman, W.D. and Tangermann, S. 479
Coleman, W.D., Skogstad, G.D. and Atkinson,
M.M. 405, 474
Author index
497
Coleman, William D. 24
Collier, D. and Collier, D. 402
Collier, D. and Messick, R.E. 34, 406
Collier, R.B. and Collier, D. 323
Collins, M.L. and Kapuçu, N. 184
Compston, H. 153, 158
Conlan, T.J. et al. 324
Considine, Mark 336
Conybeare, John A.C. 84
Cook, D.D. and Campbell, D.T. 9
Cook, F.L. et al. 205
Cook, P. and Mosdale, S. 66, 67
Corbett, J.B. and Durfee, J. 208
Corburn, J. 352
Cortell, A.P. and Peterson, S. 62
Coulter, Ann 200
Crecine, John 280
Crepaz, M.M.L. 31, 37
Cropper, S. 369, 370
Crosby, N. and Nethercut, D. 441
Crouch, C. 469
Crouch, C. and Farrell, H. 469, 470
Crozier, M. and Friedberg, E. 299
Curtain, R. 438
Czarniawska, B. 103
Dahl, R.A. and Lindblom, C.E. 21, 218, 287, 290
Dahl, Robert A. 296
Daniels, M.R. 34
Dar, S. and Cooke, B. 374
Das, J., Shantayana, D. and Hammer, S. 416,
42829
Daugbjerg, C. and Swinbank, A. 474, 477, 479
Daugbjerg, Carsten xii, 466, 47383
Davenport, T.H. and Prusak, L. 368
David, P.A. 402
Davidson, E.J. 485, 487
Davis, Charles 184
Dawson, R. and Robinson, J. 125
de Bruijn, J. and ten Heuvelhof, E. 260
de Bruijn, J., ten Heuvelhof, E. and in t Veld, R.
255, 260, 266
De Castro, Fabio 120
De Francesco, F. 246, 247
de la Porte, C. and Nanz, P. 407
de Ridder, W. 245
de Ridder, W. et al. 246, 248, 249
de Sousa Briggs, X. 350
de Vries, Michiel S. 452
Dearing, J.W. and Rogers, E.M. 205
Deaton, A. 416, 421, 422, 423, 42425, 426
deLeon, P. and Hernández-Quezada, J.M. 34
deLeon, P. and Varda, D.M. 161
deLeon, Peter 34, 105, 175, 255, 257, 258, 260
Dempster, M. and Wildavsky, A. 410
Derrida, Jacques 100
Derthick, Martha 5, 402, 403
Dessler, David 59
DeYoung, Sarah E. xii, 17588
DiMaggio, P. and Powell, W. 106
Djelic, M.-L. and Quack, S. 403
Dodd, V. and Davies, C. 195
Dolan, J. and Rosenbloom, D.H. 337
Dolan, Julie 337
Dolowitz, D. and Marsh, D. 8, 35, 404, 406
Dolsak, Nives 121
Donnelly, Kevin P. xii, 189203
Donnelly, Shanon 121
Donovan, Mark 143
Doolittle, F. and Traeger, L. 415
Douglas, Mary 100
Dowding, Keith 20, 64, 158, 159
Dowie, J. 245, 250
Downs, Anthony 76, 78, 80, 81, 176, 177, 205,
331, 332, 333, 335
Drake, W.J. and Nicolaïdis, K. 232
Drezner, D.W. 34, 37
Dror, Y. 255, 263
Druckman, James N. 192, 206
Dryzek, John S. 102, 103, 260, 293, 294, 437,
438, 444n1
Dryzek, J.S. et al. 37
Dudley, G. and Richardson, J.J. 234
Duo, E. 416
Duo, E. et al. 419, 424, 425
Duggan, Mark 196
Duit, A. and Galaz, V. 299
Dunleavy, P. 484
Dunlop, C.A. and James, O. 239, 404
Dunlop, C.A. and Radaelli, C.M. 409
Dunlop, Claire A. xiii, 19, 22943, 407
Dunn, Delmer D. 334
Dunn, W.N. 248, 255, 256, 259, 261
Dunsire, Andrew 22
Dunt, Ian 196
Durning, D. 260
Durning, D. and Osuna, W. 255, 263
Dutil, P.A. et al. 443
Dwyer, Devin 199
Dye, T.R. 29
Dyson, Kenneth 46
Eales, R. et al. 248
Easterly, W. 374
Easton, David 125
Eckstein,
Otto 5
Edelenbos, J.
255, 261
Edelenbos, J. and Klijin, E.H. 341
Edelenbos, J., van Schie, N. and Gerrits, L. 101
Edelman, Murray J. 178, 190, 207, 300, 490
Egeberg, Morten 338
Eiji, Kawabata 337
Eilders, C. 205, 206
Einsiedel, Edna F. 184
Author index
498
Einsiedel, E.F., Jelsøe, E. and Breck, T 438
Eising, R. 24
Eisinger, Peter K. 363
Eisner, Marc Allen 5, 407
Elazar, Daniel J. 362
Eldredge, N. and Gould, S. 150n2
Elkins, Z. and Simmons, B. 34
Elkins, Z., Guzman, A.T. and Simmons, B.A. 34
Elliott, C. and Schlaepfer, R. 234
Elliott-Teague, Ginger 121
Elmore, Richard F. 365
Elster, Jon 20
Emanuel, Rahm 492
Emerson, K. et al. 358
Engeli, I., Green-Pedersen, C. and Larsen, L.T.
170
Entman, Robert M. 178, 193, 206, 207
Epstein, S. 235
Esman, M. 375
Esping-Andersen, G. 34
Esty, D.C. and Porter, M.E. 31, 33
Etheredge, L.S. and Short, J. 405
Etzioni-Halevy, Eva 50, 334
Evans, M. and Davies, J. 404, 405
Evans, P., Jacobson, H. and Putnam, R. 53
Eyestone, Robert 5, 406
Faiola, Anthony 196
Falleti, T. and Lynch, J. 457
Farazmand, Ali 341
Farnsworth, S.J. and Lichter, S.R. 207
Farnsworth, Stephen J. xiii, 20414
Feldman, Martha 301, 307
Feldman, M.S. et al. 103
Fenger, M. and Klok, P.J. 130
Fenno, Richard F. 23132, 324
Fernandes, R. and Simon, H.A. 278
Ferrara, M. 36
Finlayson, A. 232
Finnemore, M. 240
Fischer, F. and Forester, J. 98, 102, 103, 190, 255,
257, 259, 435, 490
Fischer, Frank 102, 108, 194, 207, 250, 257, 259,
260, 261, 267, 301, 352, 436, 438, 485, 487
Fisher, R. and Ury, W. 348, 359n1, 359n3
Fisher, R., Ury, W. and Patton, B. 105
Fisher, Ronald A. 415, 422, 424
Fishkin, J. 260, 441
Fishman, Donald A. 185, 186
Fiske, S. and Taylor, S. 275
Flickinger, Richard 205
Foley, Henry A. 337
Folke, C. et al. 341
Forester, John 11, 21, 205, 352, 355, 436, 438
Foucault, Michel 101
Fowler, A. 376
Frank, D.J., Hironaka, A. and Schofer, E. 34
Frantz, J.E. 34
Freedman, D.A. 431n21
Freeman, Gary P. 24
Freeman, J. Leiper 18, 125
Freeman, R. 404
Fuente, David xiii, 41533
Fuller, Boyd xiii, 34760
Fung, A. 437, 439, 442
Furlong, F.R. 339
Gabaix, X. 282
Galaskiewicz, J. 157
Galland, D. and McDaniels, T. 185
Galton, Francis 282; Galtons problem 4067
Gamson, W.A. 2067
Gamson, W.A. and Modigliani, A. 206, 207
Ganghof, S. 37
Garcia-Zamor, Jean-Claude 340
Garvey, Gerald 334
Gastil, J. and Levine, P. 439, 442
Gauss-Markov theorem 424
Gawthrop, Louis C. 20
Gerring, John 457
Gerrits, L. 299
Geva-May, I. 34
Gibson, C.C., Andersson, K.P. and Shivakumar,
S. 121
Gibson, C.C., Williams, J.T. and Ostrom, E. 119
Giddens, Anthony 107
Gieryn, T.F. 239
Giest, Sarah xiii, 1728
Gigerenzer, G. and Goldstein, D.G. 283
Gigerenzer, Gerd 283
Gilardi, F. 405
Gilardi, F., Fuglister, K. and Luyet, S. 406, 410
Gillespie, P., Girgis, M. and Mayer, P. 381
Giné, X. et al. 431n23
Givel, Michael 146, 150n2, 150n6
Glascock, Jack 178
Glennerster, R. and Kremer, M. 416
Goeller, B. et al. 259
Goetz, A.M. and Gaventa, J. 436, 444
Goffman, Erving 102, 107
Goldnch, Shaun 8
Goodin, R.E. and Dryzek, J. 442
Goodnow, Frank J. 333
Goodsell, Charles T. 334
Gore, Al 209
Gormley, W.T. and Balla, S.J. 334
Gourevitch,
Peter 46
Graddy, E.A.
and Ye, K. 34
Granovetter, M.S. 282
Grant, W. 160
Gray, Barbara 366, 367
Gray, Virginia 34, 219
Green, M.T. and Thompson, F. 279
Green-Pedersen, C. and Krogstrup, J. 169
Author index
499
Green-Pedersen, C. and Mortensen, P.B. 16869
Green-Pedersen, C. and Wilkerson, J. 169
Green-Pedersen, Christoffer xiii, 32, 34, 37,
16774, 185
Greenaway, J., Salter, B. and Hart, S. 159
Greener, I. 403, 464, 468, 470, 471
Grifth, Ernest 125
Grifth, Samuel W. 121
Grindle, M.S. and Thomas, J.W. 379
Grossback, L.J., Nicholson-Crotty, S. and
Peterson, D.A.M. 405, 407
Guba, E.G. and Lincoln, Y.S. 261, 394, 43536,
438
Gulick, Luther 375
Gulrajani, N. 377, 378
Gunningham, N. and Young, M.D. 22
Gunningham, N., Grabosky, P. and Sinclair D. 22
Gunter, Valerie J. 178
Gupta, Dipak K. 336, 485
Guseld, Joseph R. 179, 192
Ha, E. 37
Haas, Peter M. 19, 48, 22930, 23132, 23334,
235, 23637, 23839, 240, 241n1, 405
Haas, P.M. and Adler, E. 235
Habermas, Jürgen 23, 1045
Hacker, J.S. 34, 402, 403, 464
Hahn, R.W. and Tetlock, P.C. 245
Hajer, M.A. and Wagenaar, H. 103, 436
Hajer, Maarten A. 102, 442
Halachimi, A. and Holzer, M. 437
Hall, J.A. and Ikenberry, G.J. 61
Hall, P.A. and Taylor, R.C.R. 36, 463
Hall, Peter A. 35, 37, 49, 50, 60, 248, 322, 403,
404, 405, 453, 464, 467
Hall, P.G. 486
Hall, R.H. and Quinn, R.E. 332
Hall, Richard H. 332
Hall, T.E. and OToole, L.J. 365
Halliday, Josh 197
Halpin, D. 282
Hamilton, Alexander 90
Hammond, T. and Miller, G.J. 283
Hampton, Greg 103
Handa, S. and Maluccio, J. 430n5
Hanf, K., Hjern, B. and Porter, D.O. 366
Harrington, W., Morgenstern, R.D. and Nelson,
P. 248
Harrison, G.W. 430n4
Harrison, K.A. 233
Harsanyi, John C. 83
Hartz-Karp, J. 442, 443
Hashimoto, Ryutaro 489
Häusermann, S. 32, 36
Hawkesworth, Mary 59, 255, 258
Hawkins, K. and Thomas, J.M. 22
Hay, C. and Wincott, D. 59, 470
Hay, Colin 467, 468, 471, 47778
Haydu, Jeffrey 456, 475, 47677, 479, 481
Hayek, Friedrich 292
Hayes, Michael xiii, 139, 28798
Hayes, Tanya 120
Haynes, Philip 299
Head, B.W. 437, 439, 490
Heady, Ferrel 338
Healey, Patsy 105
Heberlein, T.A. 440
Heckman, J.J. 416, 422, 426, 428
Heckman, J.J. and Smith, J.A. 419, 422, 423, 424,
426
Heckman, J.J. and Vytlacil, E. 426
Heclo, Hugh 125, 301, 323, 404, 405, 408, 451,
478
Hedberg, B. 404
Hedström, P. and Swedberg, R. 238
Heffernan, Richard 8
Heichel, S., Pape, J. and Sommerer, T. 34
Heikilla, T., Schlager, E. and Davis, M.W. 121
Heikkila, T. and Isett, K.R. 437
Henderson, Jeffrey 337
Hendriks, Carolyn M. xiii, 43448
Hendriks, C.M. and Carson, L. 444
Henry, A., Lubell, M. and McCoy, M. 129
Henry, Adam 129
Heraclitus 451
Herman, E.S. and Chomsky, N. 207
Hertin, J. et al. 246, 247, 248, 249
Hess, C. and Ostrom, E. 121
Higgins, R.S. et al. 84
Hilgartner, J. and Bosk, C. 175, 181
Hinich,
M. and Munger,
M. 278
Hinrichs, K. and Kangas, O. 403
Hintze, Otto 60
Hira, A., Huxtable, D. and Leger, A. 66
Hirschman, Albert 191
Hix, Simon 338
Hjern, B. and Porter, D. 125, 365, 366
Ho, A.T. 437
Ho, Khai Leong 338
Hobbes, Thomas 78
Hodgson, S.M. and Irving, Z. 490
Hogwood, B. and Gunn, L. 255, 256
Hogwood, B.W. and Peters, G.B. 34, 402, 451,
484
Holliday, Ian 62
Holzer, M. and Kloby, K. 436, 437
Holzinger, K. and Knill, C. 34
Holzinger, K., Knill, C. and Sommerer, T. 34, 37
Hood, C. and Margetts, H.Z. 484
Hood, C. and Peters, B.G. 249
Hood, C. and Scott, C. 65
Hood, C. et al. 64
Hood, Christopher 22, 245, 363, 491
Hoogerwerf, A. 303
Author index
500
Hopf, T. 239
Hopkins, R.F. 339
Hoppe, R. 255, 257, 490
Horner, L., Lekhi, R. and Blaug, R. 436, 438,
440
Hotelling, Harold 80
House, P. and Shull, R. 255, 258, 259
House, Ruth Schuyler xiiixiv, 11524
Howard, C. 436, 43940
Howarth, J. 235
Howlett, M. and Cashore, B. 37, 452
Howlett, M. and Lejano, R. 21718
Howlett, M. and Ramesh, M. 20, 29, 31, 33, 107,
244, 336, 341
Howlett, M. and Rayner, J. 35, 105, 106, 406,
410, 47374, 475, 476, 480
Howlett, Michael xiv, 4, 1728, 34, 244, 300,
369, 456, 48485
Huber, E. and Ray, L. 32
Huber, E. and Stephens, J.D. 32, 37
Hull, C.J. with Hjern, B. 366
Hunold, C. and Young, I.M. 438
Hurwitz, J. and Pefey, M. 125
Husserl, Edmund 106
Huxham, C. and Vangen, V. 369, 370
Huxham, Chris 370
Ikenberry, G.J. 235, 238
Imbeau, L.M., Petry, F. and Lamari, M. 168
Imbens, G.W. 416, 425
Imbens, G.W. and Angrist, J.D. 431n17
Imbens, G.W. and Wooldridge, J.M. 430n12
Immergut, E.M. 407
Immergut, E.M. and Anderson, K.M. 36
Immergut, E.M., Anderson, K.M. and Schulze, I.
32, 37
Ingold, Karin 129, 133
Ingram, Helen 225, 365, 367
Ingram, H.M. and Mann, D.E. 23
Innes, J.E. and Booher, D.E. 105, 107, 370
int Veld, Roeland J. 22
Inwood, G.J. 405, 408
Iyengar, S. and Kinder, D.R. 2078
Iyengar, Shanto 142, 193, 207
Jacob, K. et al. 246, 247, 248, 249, 250
Jacobs, S.H. 247, 248
Jacobson, H.K. 239
Jacobsson, K. 407
Jacques, Elliot 333
Jagger, Pamela 121
Jahn, D. 31
Jahn, D. and Müller-Rommel, F. 37
James, O. and Lodge, M. 406
Jameson, Frederic 103
Jänicke, M. 31
Jarvis, Darryl S.L. xiv, 5975
Jasanoff, S. 239, 260
Jay, S. et al. 245
Jayasuriya, Kanishka 65
Jefferson, Thomas 101
Jenkins-Smith, H. and St. Clair, G. 129
Jenkins-Smith, H., St. Clair, G. and Woods, B.
128, 129
Jenkins-Smith, Hank 125, 130, 131, 134, 134n1,
255, 263
Jennings, B. 20
Jennings, W. and John, P. 168
Jennings, W. et al. 168
Jenson, J. 408, 409
Jervis, Robert 455, 476
Jessop, B. 310
Jeuland, M. and Whittington, D. 42728
Jillson, C.C. and Wilson, R.K. 121
Jobert, B. 51
Jobert, B. and Muller, P. 49
John, P. 250
John, P. and Jennings, W. 168
John Henry effects 422, 431n15
Johnson, G.F. 442
Jones, B.D. and Bachelor, L.W. 278
Jones, B.D. and Baumgartner, F.R. 139, 141, 142,
143, 145, 146, 147, 148, 281, 282, 283, 490
Jones, B.D. and Williams, W. 278, 281
Jones, B.D. et al. 144, 147, 148, 149, 281, 283
Jones, Bryan D. xiv, 14142, 146, 27386
Jones, Charles O. 290
Jones, G. 310
Jones, M.D. and McBeth, M.K. 193, 195, 201
Jordan, A. and Liefferink, D. 37
Jordan, A. and Schout, A. 247
Jordan, A., Wurzel, R.K.W. and Zito, A.R. 37
Jordan,
Andrew xiv, 19,
34, 24454
Jordan, G. and Schubert, K. 19, 48
Jordan, Meagan 144, 147, 148
Jørgensen, T.B. and Bozeman, B. 436
Jreisat, Jamil E. 342
Jupille, J. and Caporaso, J. 36
Kaelberer, M. 233
Kagan, Robert A. 22
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. 276
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. and Tversky, A. 217,
219, 221
Kamenka, Eugene 333
Kamieniecki, S. 233
Kanbur, R. 416
Kaplan, Thomas J. 102, 104, 194
Karch, Andrew 144, 218, 219
Karlan, D. 415
Karlan, D. and Appel, J. 416
Karlan, D. and Zinman, J. 431n23
Karvonen, L. 405
Kassim, Hussein 52
Author index
501
Kathelene, L. and Martin, J. 440
Kato, J. 403
Katzenstein, P. 156
Kauneckis, Derek 121
Kavanagh, Steve 197
Kay, Adrian xiv, 402, 403, 456, 46272
Keane, M.P. 416
Keck, M. and Sikkink, K. 234
Kelly, J.M. 439
Kemp, P. 464, 466, 468, 471
Kenis, P. and Schneider, V. 154
Keohane, R. and Nye, J. 46
Kerber, W. and Eckardt, M. 407
Kerr, D.H. 484
Kersbergen, K. van 37
Keynes, J.M. (and Keynesian ideas) 322, 323
Khagram, S. and Thomas, C.W. 108
Kickert, W.J.M., Klihn, E.-H. and Koppenjan,
J.F.M. 107, 299, 310, 438
Kilduff, M. and Tsai, W. 364
Kim, Doo-Rae 334
Kim, S. 370
King, C.S., Feltey, K.M. and Susel, B.O.N. 441
Kingdon, John W. 7, 18, 55, 105, 141, 143, 167,
198, 205, 206, 223, 278, 282, 402, 405, 452,
455; focusing events and policy windows
17577, 178, 182, 184, 185; garbage can model
(GCM) and study of the policy-making process
320, 322, 32324, 325, 326, 327; models for
research into decision-making processes 299,
300, 303, 304
Kirkpatrick, C. and Lee, N. 246
Kirkpatrick, C. and Parker, D. 246, 247
Kirkpatrick, C., Parker, D. and Zhang, Y.-F. 247
Kisby, B. 158
Kiser, L.L. and Ostrom, E. 117, 118
Kiser, L.L. and Percy, S. 91
Kitschelt, H. 32, 34, 37
Kitts, K. 491
Klein, N. 492
Klijn, E.-H. and Edelenbos, J. 36768
Klingemann, H.-D., Hofferbert, R. and Budge, I.
173
Knill, C., Debus, M. and Heichel, S. 32
Knill, C., Schulze, K. and Tosun, J. 34
Knill, C., Tosun, J. and Heichel, S. 37
Knill, Christoph 22, 34
Knoke, D. et al. 155, 157
Knoke, David xiv, 19, 15363
Knoke D. and Laumann, E.O. 155
Kohler-Koch, B. 239
Koliba, C. 335, 342
Kooiman, Jan 47, 361, 438
Koppenjan, J. 303
Koppenjan, J. and Klijn, E.H. 101, 363, 368, 438
Korpi, W. and Palme, J. 34, 37, 403
Kramer, M.S. and Shapiro, S.H. 420
Krane, D. and Wright, D.S. 362
Krasner, Stephen D. 60, 61, 474
Krause, G.A. and Meier, K.J. 341
Krauthammer, Charles 198
Krebs, R.R. and Jackson, P.T. 193
Kremer, M. 415
Kremer, M. et al. 415
Krislov, Samuel 337
Kristof, Nicholas 199
Krugman, Paul 198
Kübler, Daniel 134
Kuhn, Thomas 467
Kühner, S. 32
Kuklinski, J. and Quirk, P. 275
Kunda, Ziva 278
LaFollette, Robert 5
Laitin, David 276
LaLonde, R.J. 415, 416
Larsen, J.B., Vrangnaek, K. and Traulsen, J.M.
132
Larson, Stephanie 207
Lascoumes, P. and Le Galès, P. 245
Lasswell, Harold D. 17, 105, 207, 222, 245, 250
Latour, Bruno 100, 106, 107
Laudan, Larry 126
Laumann, Edward 155
Laumann, E.O. and Knoke, D. 48, 155, 157
Laumann, E.O. and Pappi, F.U. 15657
Laumann, E.O., Galaskiewicz, J. and Marsden,
P.V. 157
Law, John 106
Lawlor, Andrea xv, 20414
Lawlor, E. 256, 265
Lawrence, Regina G. 178, 181, 184
Lawrence, R.G. and Birkland, T.A. 175, 181
Laws, D. 355
Lax, D.A. and Sebenius, J.K. 359n1
Le Gales, P. and Thatcher, M. 48
Lee, N. 248
Lee, N. and Kirkpatrick, C. 248
Leech, B.L. et al. 282
Legaspi, Perla E. 65
Lehmbruch, G. 157
Lejano, R., Ingram, H. and Ingram, M. 103, 107
Lejano, Raul Perez xv, 98112
Lemer, D. and Lasswell, H.D. 125
Lenschow, A., Liefferink, D. and Veenman, S. 34
Lerner, D. and Lasswell, H.D. 29, 257
Levi-Faur, David 64, 65, 67
Levitt, B. and March, J.G. 404, 405, 406, 407
Lewicki, R.J. and Gray, B. 352
Lewis, O. and Steinmo, S. 451
Lichter, S. Robert 208
Lichter, S.R. and Rothman, S. 208
Lidskog, R. and Sundqvist, G. 239
Limbaugh, Rush 200
Author index
502
Lindahl, Erik 79
Lindblom, C.E. and Woodhouse, E.J. 301
Lindblom, Charles E. 3, 21, 61, 104, 125, 139,
140, 250, 277, 287, 288, 290, 29293, 294,
29596, 297, 335, 405, 478
Linder, S.H. and Peters, B.G. 18, 217
Lipsky, Michael 7, 107, 339
Liu, X.S., Lindquist, E. and Vedlitz, A. 178
Lock, Karen 9
Lodge, M. and Taber, C. 278
Lohmann, Susanne 282
Loomis, Burdett A. 456
Lord, C., Ross, L. and Lepper, M. 126
Lord, W.B. 353
Lorenz-Meyer, Dagmar 233
Loughlin, John 362
Lovell, H. and MacKenzie, D. 235
Lowi, T.J. 402, 438
Lowry, William 185
Lubensky, R. 443
Lucas, Robert E. 85
Lukensmeyer, C.J., Goldman, J. and Brigham, S.
442
Lundquist, Lennart 59, 459
Lupia, A., McCubbins, M.D. and Popkin., S.L.
275, 276
Lynch, J. 32
Lynn, Lawrence E. Jr. 255, 341, 365
Lyotard, Jean-François 100, 103, 104
McCain, John 22122
McChesney, Robert 207
McComas, K.A. 440
McComas, K.A. and Shanahan, J. 208
McComas, K.A., Besley, J.C. and Black, L.W. 441
McCombs, M. 206
McCombs, M. and Shaw, D.L. 205
McCombs, M., Shaw, D.L. and Weaver, D. 206
McConnell, Allan xv, 48494
McCraw, Thomas K. 5
McCright, A.M. and Dunlap, R.E. 208
McDonald Commission in Canada 408
McGann, J. and Johnson, E. 6
McGann, J. and Sabatini, R. 157, 15960
McGinnis, M.D. and Ostrom, E. 121
McGinnis, Michael D. xv, 8797
McGoldrick, D.E. and Boonn, A.V. 22
McGuire, Michael xv, 36173
McGuire, T., Coiner, M. and Spancake, L. 84
Mackay, Charles 282
McKelvey, Richard D. 79
Mackintosh, J.P. 310
McLendon, Michael K. 326
McLennan, Gregor 61
McQuail, D. 206
MacRae, D. and Whittington, D. 255, 259
MacRae Jr., Duncan 19
Madison, James 90
Mahoney, J. and Thelen, K. 452, 453, 475
Mahoney, James 452, 474, 47576, 477
Mahwinney, Hanne B. 454
Majone, Giandomenico 24, 6365, 6566, 76,
127, 178, 190, 250, 435, 436, 440, 490
Mandell, Myrna P. 366
Mannheim, Karl 98
Mansbridge, J.J. 351, 355
Maoz, Z. 154
March, J. and Simon, H. 105
March, James A. 274, 275, 276
March, J.G. 404, 405
March, J.G. and Herbert, A.S. 332
March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. 61, 106, 303
Marier, Patrik xv, 40114, 439
Marin, B. and Mayntz, R. 19, 299
Markoff, J. and Montecinos, V. 405
Marmor, Theodore R. 337
Marquez, Lilian 121
Marsh, D. and McConnell, A. 484
Marsh, D. and Rhodes, R.A.W. 15758, 160, 341
Marsh, D. and Sharman, J.C. 34, 404, 406, 409
Marsh, D. and Smith, M. 158, 364
Marsh, D. et al. 160
Marsh, D., Lewis, C. and Fawcett., P. 440
Marsh, David 15657, 341
Martin, J. 32, 103
Martinez, J., Susskind, L.E. et al. 350, 356
Mashaw, J. and Marmor, T.R. 339
Mashaw, Jerry 339
Mason, R. and Mitroff, I. 261
Matthews, D.R. and Stimson, J.A. 282
Matti, S. and Sandström, A. 129
May, P., Sapotichne, J. and Workman, S. 185,
490
May, Peter 176, 177, 178, 404, 491
Mayer, Igor S. xv, 25569
Mayer, Robert N. 205
Mayntz, Renate 23, 29
Mazmanian, D. and Sabatier, P. 125, 379
Mazur, A. and Lee, L. 208
Mazur, Allan 125, 208
Meier, K.J. 334
Meijerink, S. 234
Melis,
T.S. and Pulwarty,
R.S. 184
Melo, M.A. 233
Menard, C. and Shirley, M.M. 116
Merriam, Charles 274
Merton, Robert K. 282, 338
Meseguer, C. 35
Mettler, S. and Soss, J. 222
Mieszkowski, P. and Zodrow, G.R. 81
Migué, J-L., Bélanger, G. and Niskanen, W.A. 84
Miguel, E. and Kremer, M. 415
Mikkelson, M. 159
Miliband, Ed 196
Author index
503
Miliband, Ralph 295
Mill, John Stuart 101
Miller, G.J. 280
Miller, G.J. and Moe, T.M. 84
Miller, J.H. and Page, S.E. 282
Miller, S.M., Evers, A. and Winterberger, H. 208
Milleron, J.C. 79
Mills, C. Wright 191
Milward, H.B. and Provan, K.G. 367
Minicucci, Daniela 197
Minogue, Martin 67
Mintrom, M. and Vergari, S. 178
Mintrom, Michael xv, 316, 20, 178, 405, 407
Mintzberg, H. 299, 300
Mintzberg, H., Raisinghani, D. and Therot, A.
303
Miser, H.J. and Quade, E.S. 255, 259
Mitchell, N.J. et al. 232
Mitchell, William C. 79, 85, 93
Mnookin, R. 353
Molotch, H. and Lester, M. 177, 184
Mommsen, Wolfgang J. 335
Montjoy, R.S. and Watson, D.J. 334
Montpetit, Eric 127, 134
Mookherjee, D. 416
Mooney, Christopher Z. 13, 207
Moore, Mark Harrison 341, 369, 436
Morgan, G. 300
Morgan, S.L. and Winship, C. 430n6
Mortensen, P.B. et al. 168, 169
Mortensen, Peter B. xv, 16774
Mosher, Frederick C. 334, 337
Mosley, P. and Dowler, E. 381
Mouritzen, Hans 339
Mowles, C. 377, 378, 381
Moyer, H.W. and Josling, T.E. 479
Mucciaroni, Gary xvxvi, 32028
Mueller, Dennis C. 77, 7879, 8081, 82, 83, 84
Muldoon, J.P., Aviel, J.F. and Reita, R. 339
Munger, Michael C. 10
Munro, G.D. et al. 126
Munro, John 129
Murray, D., Schwartz, J. and Lichter, S.R. 208
Murray, G. and Pacheco, D. 8
Mwangi, Esther 121
Myers, Samuel L. 9
Myint, Tun 121
Myles, J. and Pierson, P. 403
Nachmais, David 23
Nakamura, Robert T. 175
Nedergaard, P. 407
Nelson, Barbara 13
Ness, B. et al. 248
Nettl, J.P. 60
Neumann, J. van and Morgenstern, O. 98
Newell, A. and Simon, H.A. 277, 278, 283
Newell, Allen 274, 275, 277, 283
Niemann, A. 239
Niemeyer, S. 438
Nilsson, M. 249
Nilsson, M. et al. 246, 248
Nisbet, M.C. and Myers, T. 208
Nisbet, Robert 453
Niskanen, William A. 7, 8, 78, 84, 331, 340
Noakes, J.A. and Johnston, H. 192
Nohrstedt, D. and Weible, C.M. 126, 132
Nohrstedt, Daniel xvi, 12537, 177
Nooteboom, B. 467
North, Douglass C. 67, 115, 116, 121, 462, 466,
469
Northrup, T.A. 353
Nussbaum, Martha 103
Nutley, S.M., Walter, I. and Davies, H.T.O. 250
Oakerson, R.J. 88, 90, 95n4
Oakerson, R.J. and Parks, R.B. 121
Oakley, M.R. 182
OFaircheallaigh 434
Ogden, J., Walt, G. and Lush, L. 235
OLeary, R. and Bingham, L.B. 341
Oliver, W. Hugh 7
Olsen, Johan P. 335, 408
Olsen, J.P. and Peters, B.G. 24, 337
Olsen, Mancur J. 76, 78, 295, 438
Orenstein, M.A. 404, 405
Orren, K. and Skowronek, S. 61, 62
Osborne, D. and Gaebler, T. 7, 340, 439
Ospina, S.M. and Dodge, J. 103
Ostrom, E. and Crawford, S. 119
Ostrom, E. and Ostrom, V. 87, 88, 91, 92,
9495n1, 95n4
Ostrom, E., Gardner, R. and Walker, J. 95n4
Ostrom, E., Schroeder, L. and Wynne, S. 88, 121
Ostrom, E., Walker, J. and Gardner, R. 82
Ostrom, Elinor 60, 76, 8283, 87, 88, 89, 91, 93,
95n4, 11517, 11718,
11920, 121, 126,
299,
452, 463
Ostrom, V., Bish, R. and Ostrom, E. 88
Ostrom, V., Tiebout, C.M. and Warren, R. 89,
95n2
Ostrom, Vincent 89, 90, 94, 95n2. 95n3, 95n5,
95n7, 121
OToole, Laurence J. 361, 363, 366
Ouchi, William G. 335
Overbye, E. 34
Owens, S., Rayner, T. and Bina, O. 245, 249,
250
Oyerinde, Oyebade Kunle 121
Pacheco, Diego 120
Padgett, John F. 147, 283
Page, B.I. and Shapiro, R.Y. 172
Page, C. and Jenkins, B. 339
Author index
504
Page, S. 466, 471
Palin, Sarah 101
Palumbo, D.J. 250
Pappi, Franz 155
Pareto, Vilfredo 27475
Park, Y.H. 409
Parkinson, J. 436, 437, 442
Parks, R.B. 91, 121
Parks, R.B. and Oakerson, R.J. 91
Parsons, Wayne 336
Patriotta, Gerardo 103
Patterson, M. and Monroe, K.R. 193
Patterson, Thomas E. 207
Patton, C. and Sawicki, D. 255, 259
Patton, Michael Quinn 9
Pawson, R. and Tilley, N. 431n24
Pawson, Ray 20, 108, 245, 250
Pefey, M. and Hurwitz, J. 125, 126
Peltzman, Sam 85
Pemberton, H. 403, 464, 466, 468, 471
Pena, Jim 221
Pentland, Brian 107
Perl, A. and Dunn Jr., J.A. 45
Perl, A. and White, D. 50
Perl, Anthony xvi, 4456
Perri 12
Perrow, Charles 179
Persha, Lauren 120
Persson, Torsten 85
Peters, B.G. and Van Nispen, F.K.M. 22
Peters, B.G., Pierre, J. and King, D.S. 403
Peters, B. Guy 333, 334, 335, 336, 337, 338, 339,
363
Peterson, J. 238
Peterson, M.J. 235
Picard, L.A. and Buss, T.F. 374
Pierce, Jonathan J. 129
Pierson, Paul 24, 32, 34, 284n3, 323, 402, 403,
452, 464, 466, 473, 474, 475, 476, 478, 480,
481n1
Plümper, T. and Neumayer, E. 34
Pollit, Christopher 456
Pollitt, C. and Bouckaert, G. 340
Poocharoen, Ora-Orn xvi, 33146
Popper, Karl 104, 295
Poteete, A., Janssen, M. and Ostrom, E. 95n4
Power, Nina 196
Pralle, Sarah 144, 146
Prasser, S. 491
Premfors, R. 408
Pressman, Jeffrey L. 365
Pressman, J.L. and Wildavsky, A. 7, 106, 125,
127, 339, 365, 379
Price, V. and Tewksbury, D. 206
Prince, M.J. 182
Prince, R. 233
Pritchard, David 205
Pritchett, L. and Woolcock, M. 375
Pross, A. Paul 19
Provan, K.G. and Kenis, P. 161, 341
Przeworski, Adam 59, 60, 61
Putnam, R. and Leonardi, R. 121
Putnam, Robert D. 46, 53, 125, 126, 437
Quade, Edward S. 248, 259, 307
Quattrone, G.A. and Tversky, A. 126
Raadschelders, J.C.N. 462, 465
Rabin, J. and Bowman, J.S. 334
Rabinow, P. and Sullivan, W. 103
Radaelli, C.M. 35, 230, 238, 244, 246, 247, 249,
250, 404, 405, 406
Radaelli, C.M. and Connor, K. 232
Radaelli, C.M. and Meuwese, A.C.M. 249
Radin, B.A. et al. 363
Radin, Beryl A. 3, 255
Rae, Douglas W. 79
Ragin, Charles 455
Raiffa, H. 357, 359n1
Raiffa, H., Richardson, J. and Metcalfe, D. 357
Ramseyer, J.M. and Rosenbluth, F.M. 337
Ranney, Austin 125
Rapley, John 99
Rawls, John 83
Ray, James Lee 59
Rayner, S. 245
Razin, A. and Sadka, E. 62
Reddel, T. and Woolcock, G. 438, 440
Redford, Emmette S. 172
Rein, M. and Schön, D. 192, 193, 359n8
Renda, A. 248, 249
Renn, O., Webler, T. and Wiedemann, P. 437
Repetto, Robert 144
Rethel, L. 235
Rethemeyer, R.K. 160
Rhoads, Steven E. 7
Rhodes, R.A.W. 47, 62, 157, 158, 299, 310, 341,
362, 363
Rhodes, R.A.W. and Dunleavy, P. 310
Rhodes, R.A.W. and Marsh, D. 363, 474, 477
Richardson, Jeremy 157
Richardson, J.J. and Jordan, A.G. 477
Richardson, T. 248
Ricoeur, Paul 102
Riggs, Fred W. 338
Riker, William 76, 78, 80
Riper, Paul P. Van 334
Risse-Kappen, T. 52
Rittel, H. and Webber, M. 99, 303
Robbins, M.D., Simonsen, B. and Feldman., B.
442
Roberts, N. 439, 441
Robertson, D.B. 405, 410
Robinson, Scott E. 140, 144
Author index
505
Robinson, S.E. and Caver, F.R. 147
Robinson, S.E. and Eller, W.S. 327
Robinson, S.E. and Meier, K.J. 140
Robyn, Dorothy 324
Rochefort, D.A. and Cobb, R.W. 191
Rochefort, D.A., Rosenberg, M. and White, D.
201
Rochefort, David A. xvi, 189203
Rodrik, D. 424, 426
Roe, Emery 102, 103
Roederer-Rynning, C. and Daugbjerg, C. 478
Romney, Mitt 200
Roosevelt, F.D.R. 279
Rose, R. and Davies, P.L. 468
Rose, Richard 24, 35, 36, 323, 402, 404, 405,
406, 473
Rosenau, Pauline V. 207, 310
Ross, Marc H. 19495, 402, 403, 410
Rossi, P.H., Lipsey, M.W. and Freeman, H.E.
250
Roth, C. 233
Rothstein, B. 402
Rothstein, Robert L. 29091
Rourke, Francis E. 337
Rowley, C.K. and Schneider, F. 77
Rudd, Kevin 48889
Ruggie, J.G. 405
Russel, D. and Jordan, A. 245, 248
Rutgers, Mark R. 334
Ryan, Marie-Laure 103
Ryan, Paul 200
Saari, Donald G. 80
Sabatier, P.A. and Brasher, A.M. 129
Sabatier, P.A. and Jenkins-Smith, H.C. 48, 55,
107, 125, 126, 129, 130, 131, 132, 134n1, 195,
452
Sabatier, P.A. and Mazmanian, D. 31
Sabatier, P.A. and Weible, C.M. 126, 128, 129,
130, 132, 134n1, 359n7, 452
Sabatier, P.A., Hunter, S. and McLaughlin, S. 126
Sabatier, Paul A. 17, 19, 35, 120, 125, 126, 130,
134, 134n1, 175, 234, 235, 301, 307, 325, 453
Sabet, Daniel M. 121
Sacks, Jonathan 197
Saint-Martin, Denis 340
Saint-Onge, H. and Armstrong, C. 361
Salamon, Lester M. 22, 363
Saleth, R.M. and Dinar, A. 120
Salter, L. 43839, 440
Sanderson, I, 20, 245, 250
Sandler, Todd 13
Sandström, A. and Carlsson, L. 160
Sato, H. 302
Satterthwaite, Mark A. 79
de Saussure, Ferdinand 100
Savas, E.S. 7
Sawyer, A. 121
Scharpf, Fritz W. 36, 48, 299, 303, 305, 363, 365
Scharpf, F.W., Reissert, B. and Schnabel, F. 304
Schattschneider, Elmer, E. 141, 143, 145, 167,
172, 175, 177, 178, 179, 190, 402, 491
Schelling, Thomas C. 98, 282
Scheufele, D.A. and Tewksbury, D. 206
Schmidt, Manfred G. 168
Schmidt, V.A. 230
Schmidt, Vivien A. 19
Schmitt, Sophie xvi, 2943
Schneider, A. and Ingram, H. 102, 105, 143, 178,
179. 192, 217, 218, 219, 222, 223, 224, 22526
Schneider, A.L. and Ingram, H. 437
Schneider, Anne L. xvi, 144, 21728
Schneider, Saundra 179
Schoeld, Norman 79
Schön, D.A. and Rein, M. 12, 49, 55, 102, 105,
193, 301, 352, 353, 359n8
Schön, Donald A. 11, 218
Schot, J. and Schipper, F. 235
Schout, A. and Jordan, A. 245
Schout, A., Jordan, A. and Twena, M. 101
Schrad, Mark Lawrence 278, 281
Schram, S. and Neisser, P.T. 103
Schröder, Gerhard 492
Schulman, Paul R. 19
Schwarz, Herman 466
Scotchmer, S. 81
Scott, Colin 63
Scott, James C. 99
Scott, W. Richard 332
Scruggs, L. 31, 32
Sebenius, James K. 234
Seeberg, Henrik 169
Seldon, Sally Coleman 337
Self, Peter 9
Selznick, Philip 99
Sen, Amartya K. 375
Sewell, William H. 476, 477
Shafritz, J.M. and Hyde, A. 332
Shafritz, J.M. and Ott, J.S. 332
Shanahan, E., Jones, M.D. and McBeth, M.K.
127, 134, 195
Shankland, A. and Hasenclever, L. 235
Shapiro, I. and Bedi, S. 491
Shapiro, Ian 13
Sharman, J.C. 490
Sheriff, P.E. 408
Shiffman, J., Beer, T. and Wu, Y. 144
Shiller, R.J. 282
Shipan, C.R. and Lowry, W.R. 37
Shipan, C.R. and Volden, C. 404
Shughart, W.F. and Razzolini, L. 77, 78
Shughart, William F. 77, 81
Shulock, N. 255
Siegel, J. 161
Author index
506
Silvia, C. and McGuire, M. 367
Silvia, Chris xvi, 36173
Simek, J., Zamykalova, L. and Mesanyova, M. 233
Simmons, B.A. and Elkins, Z. 406
Simon, Herbert A. 20, 93, 118, 125, 126, 245,
250, 27476, 277, 279, 283
Skelcher, Chris 363
Skinner, B.F. 27980
Skocpol, T. and Weir, M. 322
Skocpol, Theda 6162, 402, 466
Sköldberg, Kaj 103
Skowronek, Stephen 61, 362
Slovak, Paul 276
Smith, Adrian 48, 133
Smith, G. and May, D. 21
Smith, Gilbert 20, 439
Smith, James A. 6
Smith, Mark A. 145
Smith, Martin J. 19, 299, 310, 334
Smith, S.R. and Lipsky, M. 362
Snider, J.H. 440, 441
Sniderman, P.M., Brody, R.A. and Tetlock, P.E.
207
Somaiya, Ravi 196
Sommerer, T. 37
Sorenson, E. and Torng, J. 363
Sornette, D. 282
Soroka, Stuart N. xvi, 172, 20414
Sowell, Thomas 292, 293, 295
Spector, M. and Kitsuse, J.I. 207
Speers, K. 444
Spicer, Michael 292
Stanley, N. and Manthorpe, J. 491
Starke, P. 34
Starke, P., Obinger, H. and Castles, F.G. 34
Staronova, K. 246
Steed, B. 120
Stephens, J.C. et al. 235
Stephens, J.D., Huber, E. and Ray, L. 32
Stevens, Joe B. 9
Stevens, W.K. 208
Stewart, J. 435, 444
Stigler, George 85
Stillman, Peter G. 23
Stimson, James 220
Stinchcombe, Arthur L. 466
Stokey, E. and Zeckhauser, R. 10
Stone, D. and Denham, A. 6
Stone, D. and Garnett, M. 407
Stone, Deborah A. 11, 102, 103, 178, 179, 181,
191, 194, 196, 218, 223, 490
Stone, Diane L. 6, 35, 37
Strand, R. 299
Strange, Susan 62, 63, 64
Streeck, W. and Schmitter, P. 54
Streeck, W. and Thelen, K.A. 36, 452, 469, 475
Sulkin, Tracy 171
Sundquist, James L. 36465
Sunstein, C.R. 353
Surowiecki, James 282
Susskind, L., Thomas-Larmer, J. and McKearnen,
S. 105
Susskind, L.E. 359n9
Susskind, L.E. and Cruikshank, J.L. 359n9
Susskind, L.E. and Field, P. 353
Susskind, L.E. and Thomas-Larmer, J. 354
Svara, James H. 333, 334, 337
Sveiby, K.-E. 368
Swank, D. 32, 36, 37
Swidler, Ann 51
Sykes, R., Palier, B. and Prior, P.M. 37
Tabb, William K. 13
Tabellini, Guido 85
Tamborra, M. 248
Tavits, M. 406
Taylor, M. 79
Taylor-Gooby, P. 37
Teisman, Geert R. xvii, 299319
Teisman, G.R. and Klijn, E.H. 299
Teisman, G.R., van Buuren, A. and Gerrits, L.
299, 300
Termeer, C. 309
Tetlock, Philip 276
Tews, K., Buschand, P.-O. and Jörgens, H. 37
Thaler, Richard H. 276
Thatcher, M. 236
Thelen, K. and Steinmo, S. 474
Thelen, Kathleen 468, 47475
Therborn, Göran 60
Thiel, A. 248
Thiel, A. and König, B. 249
Thomas, A. 374
Thomas, C.W. 233
Thomas III, Herschel F. xvii, 27386
Thompson, Grahame F. 363
Thompson, J.A. 334
Thomson, A.M., Perry, J.L. and Miller, T.K. 369
Throgmorton, J.A. 105
Tiebout, C.M. 81, 82
Tilly, Charles 59, 457
Tocqueville, Alexis de 90
Todd, P.E. and Wolpin, K.I. 415
Toke, D. 233
Toonen, Theo A.J. 89
Topal, C. 441
Torgerson, Douglas 20, 194
Torriti, J. 248, 249
Tovey, Craig A. 80
Tribe, L.H., Schelling, C.S. and Voss, J. 353
True, J. and Minstrom, M. 9
True, J. and Utter, G. 144
True, J., Jones, B. and Baumgartner, F. 140, 142,
147
Author index
507
Trumbo, Craig 208
Tsebelis, George 36, 140, 407, 409
Tullock, Gordon 76, 81
Tuohy, Caroline 24
Tupper, A. and Doern, G.B. 22
Turnpenny, J. et al. 245, 24748, 249
Turnpenny, John xvii, 24454
Twaalfhoven, P. 263
Tyran, J.-R. and Sausgruber, R. 34
Urwick, Lyndall 375
Urzua, S. and Heckman, J.J. 431n17
van Bueren, A. et al. 300, 308
van Buuren, A. and Gerrits, L. 299, 301, 307, 308
van Buuren, Arwin xvii, 299319
van Creveld, Martin 62
van Daalen, Els xvii, 25569
van de Riet, O. 257
Van den Ven, Andrew H. 134
van Eeten, M. 257, 259
van Herk, S. et al. 301
van Laerhoven, Frank 121
Van Slyke, David 363
van Waarden, F. and Drahos, M. 232, 233
van Waarden, Frans 19, 47, 48
Vaughan, S.K. and Arsneault, S. 182
Vedung, Evert xvii, 22, 387400
Verdun, A. 238
Verhulst, J. and Walgrave, S. 184
Vickers, Geoffrey 307
Vis, B. 32, 37
Vis, B. and Kersbergen, K. van 37
Voets, J., Van Dooren, W. and de Rynck, F. 160
Vogel, David 24
Volden, C., Ting, M.M. and Carpenter, D.P. 34
von Winter, T. 159
Wade, Robert 337
Wagenaar, H. 299
Walgrave, S. and Van Aelst, P. 205
Walgrave, S. and Varone, F. 141
Walgrave, S. and Verhulst, J. 178
Walgrave, S., Soroka, S. and Nuytenams, M. 206
Walker, Jack L. 125, 175, 217, 404, 406
Walker, K.J. 239
Walker, W. 257
Wälti, S. 31
Walton, Jeff 197
Wang, Jianxun 120
Wanna, J. 437
Warren, M. and Pearse, H. 442
Watts, Ronald L. 362
Weaver, K. 403, 409
Weaver, R.K. 402, 407, 491
Weber, Max 47, 60, 99, 154, 156, 331, 332, 335,
342
Weible, Christopher xvii, 12537
Weible, C.M. and Sabatier, P.A. 129, 161
Weible, C.M. et al. 128, 13132, 134n1, 236
Weible, C.M., Sabatier, P.A. and McQueen., K.
454
Weick, K.E. 103, 106
Weidner, H. and Jänicke, M. 37
Weimer, D.L. and Vining, A.R. 7, 10, 255,
256
Weir, M. and Skocpol, T. 402
Weiss, A. and Woodhouse, E. 293, 294, 295, 296,
297
Weiss, C. and Bucuvalas, M. 259
Weiss, Carol H. 9, 125, 23536, 250
Weiss, Linda 63
Wenger, E. 234, 368
Wesselink, A. and Warner, J. 102
West, William F. 338
Westney, D.E. 406
Westoby, Adam 335
Weyland, K. 404, 406
Wheare, K.C. 407
Whitaker, G. 91
White, Leonard D. 255, 333
Whiteford, P. 32
Whitford, Andy xviixviii, 7686
Whittington, D. et al. 42728, 431n25
Whittington, Dale xviii, 41533
Wildavsky, A., Swedlow, B. and White, J. 336
Wildavsky, Aaron 3, 6, 140, 255, 260, 277, 289,
293, 336, 455
Wilensky, H.L. 32
Wilkerson, John 146
Wilkins, L. and Patterson, P. 208
Wilkinson, D. et al. 248
Williams, Claire xviii, 316
Williams,
Rowan 197
Williams, Russell
A. 454
Williams, Walter W. 365
Williamson, A. and Fung, A. 441, 442, 443,
444
Williamson, John 7
Williamson, Oliver E. 82, 117, 120
Wilsford, David 459, 464, 471
Wilson, James Q. 332, 340
Wilson, Woodrow 333
Windhoff-Héritier, A. 29, 31
Witte, J.M., Reinicke, W.H. and Benner, T.
157
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, treatise on logic 100
Wofford, Harris 18485
Wolf Jr, Charles 7
Wollmann, H. 250
Wood, Christopher 9
Wood, Robert S. 144, 145, 178
Woodside, K. 22
Woolcock, M. 376
Author index
508
Workman, S., Jones, B. and Jochim, A. 139, 140,
141, 280
Wright, K. 231, 232
Wu, Chen-Yu xviii, 15363
Wu, X. et al. 22, 336
Yagade, A. and Dozier, D.M. 206
Yang, K. and Callahan, K. 444
Yanow, Dvora 102, 103, 104
Yergin, D. and Stanislaw, J. 7
Youde, J. 234
Young, Lori xviii, 20414
Youssefmir et al. 282
Zafonte, M. and Sabatier, P.A. 128, 129, 130
Zahariadis, Nikolaos 167, 320, 323, 452;
garbage can model (GCM), work with
32526
Zelikow P. 232
Zhong, L.J. and Mol, A.P.J. 440
Zito, A.R. 233
Zucker, H.G. 206
Author index
509
Subject index
action situations and arenas 11718
actor promoted events (APEs) 184
adaptation, principle of 275
Administrative Behavior (Simon, H.A.) 274
administrative capacity, effectiveness and 245
administrative systems and policy outputs 33536
Advocacy Coalition Framework (ACF) 12534;
advocacy coalitions 12730; aggregation of
actors 126; assumptions 12627; belief
subsystems 126; belief systems, hierarchy and
stability of 129; bounded rationality 126;
bounded rationality, public policy
decision-making and 273; change, policy
dynamics and 452, 454, 455, 456, 457, 458;
coalitions, formulation of 12829; coalitions,
level of conict between 13031; conceptual
categories and relations 127; development of
125; devil shift 126; disagreement and
alternative dispute resolution in policy process
352; focusing events and policy windows 175,
186; framework 12627; hypotheses building
and testing 129, 131, 133; implicit theories and
assumptions 12627; individuals, attributes of
131; interdependencies 133; international
dimensions and dynamics of policy-making 48;
issue networks 125; long-term time perspective
127; momentum of the ACF research program
134; organizations, distinction between
different types of 129; policy brokers 131;
policy change 125, 127, 129, 13233, 133, 134;
policy network models 161; policy-oriented
learning 125, 13032, 133; policy process
research 125; policy subsystems 134; policy
subsystems, composition of 12829; policy
subsystems, policy processes and 126; political
behavior of advocacy coalitions 12930;
scientic and technical information 127; scope
127; stimuli, attributes of 131; stimuli,
processing of 126; subsystem actors 126;
theoretical emphasis 13334; translated beliefs
12627
agenda-setting and political discourse 189201;
agenda building, process of 19091;
agenda-policy hypothesis 17071; agenda
prioritization 193; agenda-setting perspective,
questions central to 189; argumentative turn in
policy studies 190; audience reaction, evocation
of 19293; command issues 189; counting,
language of 191; description, dimensions of
19091; discussion 200201; focusing events as
aspects of agenda-setting 17577; frame analysis
193; framing 190, 19293; inuential and
powerful interests 189; issue attentiveness,
agenda-setting and 2056; metaphor 191;
narrative, explanatory function of 19495;
narrative,
language and 190,
193, 19495;
noncontradictory argumentation 193; Occupy
Wall Street, case of 195, 198200; policy
analysis and agenda setting 56; policy design
192; preference ranking 192; problem
denition 19092; problem description,
anatomy of 191; problem handling 191;
problem ownership 19192; riots in UK, case
of 19598; September 11th, narrative
explanation of 19495; story lines within public
policy discourse 194
Agendas and Instability in American Politics
(Baumgartner, F. and Jones, B.D.) 14950,
150n6, 167
aggregation: of actors in ACF 126; of harms 176;
rules, IAD and 119
alignment of streams in GCM 32324, 32526
ambiguities, dealing with 190, 199, 200, 326, 389,
486, 492
analytical styles 25567; archetypal styles,
denition of 26162; argumentative style 259;
arguments and values, clarication of 257, 258,
264; client advice style 260; combining
activities 26263; democratization 257, 258,
264; design and recommendation 25657, 258,
264; design of policy analysis 26667; diversity
of, untangling and explaining 25556;
510
evaluation criteria 263; evaluation of policy
analysis 267; interacting activities 25658, 267;
interactive style 261; mediation 257, 258, 264;
participatory style 260; perspectives on eld of
policy analysis 26567; perspectives on policy
analysis, framework for understanding and
design 255; policy analysis styles 25862; policy
analyst, role of 26365; process style 26061;
rational style 25859; reection on policy
analysis 26566; research and analysis 256, 258,
264; research approach 256; strategic advice,
provision of 257, 258, 264; values underlying
26365
antecedent conditions in GCM 323
anti-rationalist criticisms of incrementalism
29496
anticipated side-effects 391
applications of: Institutional Analysis and
Development (IAD) framework 12021; policy
analysis 910
appraisal: processes as sites of political behavior
245; systems for, research on design of 249; see
also policy appraisal
archetypal analytical styles, denition of 26162
argumentative style in analysis 259
argumentative tradition in evaluation 435
argumentative turn in policy studies 190
assessment of operation of policy appraisal 248,
24950; see also policy appraisal
Association for Public Policy Analysis and
Management (APPAM) 10
asymmetrical power 154
attention: attention-driven choice in public policy
28081; dynamics in executive speeches 168,
169; public opinion and policy change, linking
of 17072, 173
audience reaction, evocation of 19293
authority rules in IAD 119
availability in policy design and transfer 21920
behavioral theory of choice 274, 27677
behavioral theory of organization 27879
belief subsystems in ACF 126
belief systems, hierarchy and stability of 129
benchmarks, multiplicity of 48586
beneciaries, empowerment of 402
benet-cost analysis 5
best alternative to a negotiated agreement
(BATNA) 349, 356, 35758
Betuwe railway line: events in decision-making
on 31415;
fourfold analysis of 31016; phase
model in
analysis of 311; rounds model in
analysis of 31213; stream model in analysis of
31112; tracks model in analysis of 313
bias: biased results, risk of 34, 37; cognitive biases
and decision heuristics 21922; contribution
bias 220; mobilization of 491; randomization
bias 42122; selection bias 418, 419, 420,
42223, 424, 431n18; substitution bias 42122
boundary rules in IAD 119
bounded rationality: advocacy coalition
framework (ACF) 126; genesis and
development of 27374; institutional analysis
and political economy 92; policy-making
process 2021
bounded rationality and public policy
decision-making 27384; adaptation, principle
of 275; Administrative Behavior (Simon, H.A.)
274; Advocacy Coalition Framework 273;
attention-driven choice in public policy
28081; behavioral theory of choice 274,
27677; behavioral theory of organization
27879; bounded rationality, genesis and
development of 27374; bounded rationality,
policymaking systems and 28384; bounded
rationality, stochastic processes and 28283;
bounded rationality, tenets of 27476; heuristics
27778; human choice, model of 273, 277;
human goals, pursuit of 273;
information-processing 27980; Institutional
Analysis and Development Framework 273;
institutional friction, disproportionate
information-processing and 281; intended
rationality, principle of 27475;
know-recommend strategy 278; lexicographic
strategy 276; Mind and Society (Pareto, V.)
27475; motivated reasoning 278; organizations
27879; positive feedback, disproportionate
information-processing and 28182; problem
from solution spaces, separation of 27778;
Punctuated Equilibrium Theory 273; trade-offs,
principle of 276; uncertainty, principle of
27576; wisdom of crowds argument 282
Breaking through the Bureaucracy (Barzelay, M.) 335
building blocks of governance 36768
bureaucracy and policy process 33142;
administrative
systems and policy
outputs
33536; Breaking through the Bureaucracy
(Barzelay, M.) 335; Our Wonderland of
Bureaucracy (Beck, J.M.) 335; bureaucracy of
small island states 340; bureaucrat bashing 84;
bureaucratic organization, creation of 402;
bureaucratic power and dilemma for democracy
334; bureaucratic structure, policy and 33839;
co-production and co-creation 341; denitions
of bureaucracy 33132; democratic control and
bureaucratic autonomy 334; future studies 342;
governance and bureaucracy 34042;
government, bureaucracy as part of 33335;
institutional structure of 333; international
policy-making 33839; jurisdictional areas
33233; knowledge-based power 336;
leadership role, bureaucracy in 337;
legal-rational foundation of bureaucracy
Subject index
511
33233; lobbying 337; The Managerial
Revolution (Burnham, J.) 335; networks and
collaborations, notion of 341; New Public
Management (NPM) movement 338, 34041;
organizational form, bureaucracy as 33233;
policy implementers, bureaucrats as 33940;
policy-makers, bureaucrats as 33639; political
control of bureaucracy 249; political systems
and decision-making processes 334, 33536,
33738; political systems and economic
systems, interdependencies of 33435;
politics-administration dichotomy debate
33334; The Politics of Bureaucracy (Peters, B.G.)
33536; public managers and public value 341;
Reinventing Government (Osborne, D. and
Gaebler, T.) 340; role of bureaucracy in policy
process 33536; social institution of 333;
street-level bureaucrats 339; super
bureaucracies 337
business advantage in resources 296
calculation, learning as 239
capitalism: capital movements, liberalization of 46;
capitalist societies 296
causality: causal explanations, research methods
and 3638; causal mechanisms 42627, 452,
455, 456, 45759; deterministic causal patterns
476; gold standard in causal identication,
promotion of RCTs as 41720; historical
causality, lack in GCM of 32223; problem for
policy dynamics and change 45455; social
causation 463
central agencies, strength of 78
change, policy dynamics and 45160; Advocacy
Coalition Framework (ACF) 452, 454, 455,
456, 457, 458; causal mechanisms 452, 455,
456, 45759; causality problem 45455;
change, normal status of policy-making
45152; dependent variable problem 45253;
Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD)
framework 456, 457, 458; logic of direction
problem 45354; mechanistic perspective,
positives of 458; Multiple Stream Approach
(MSA) 452, 456, 457; neoinstitutionalist
theories 452; Path Dependence Framework
(PDF) 452, 456, 457; policy actors 453, 458,
45960; policy change, puzzle of 452; policy
change, understanding in order to grasp policy
dynamics 45152; Policy Generations
Framework (PGF) 452, 456, 457; public
policy, dynamic phenomenon of 451;
Punctuated
Equilibrium Framework (PEF)
452,
454, 457; puzzle and agents 45960; sequence
of policy dynamic development 456; temporal
problem 45556; timing of policy dynamics
and change 455
circumstantial reactors 176
citizen-led performance management 43637
citizen surveys 43940
citizens juries 44142
city design and, policy design and 219
Clean Air Amendments Act (1970) 290
client advice style of analysis 260
client-orientation: client focus in evaluation 436;
in evaluation, model of 39294; in evaluation,
pros and cons of 39394
climate change debate 2078
club goods 8182, 119
coalitions: advocacy coalitions 12730;
co-production and co-creation 341;
formulation of 12829; interest groups, experts,
advocacy coalitions, and bureaucrats with
vested interests 172; level of conict between
13031; see also Advocacy Coalition
Framework (ACF)
cognitive biases and decision heuristics 21922
collaboration: collaborative web technologies
44243; combining activities in analysis
26263; convening, getting problem and parties
right 35455; governance, networks and
intergovernmental systems 361, 367, 369, 370;
networks and collaborations, notion of 341
collective choice and action: collective action,
problematic circumstances of 94; collective
choice, public choice perspective and 7879;
collective choice level rules 117; collective
goals 121
collegial models of evaluation 39799
command issues 189
commissions: membership of 409; policy impact
of 4089; role in defeating policy feedback and
policy learning barriers 4079
common-pool resources (CPRs): institutional
analysis and political economy 92; public choice
perspective 8283
communities of practice 368; attributes of
community 11920; counter-epistemic
communities 23435; see also epistemic
communities; policy communities
comparative approaches to study of public
policy-making 2939; biased results, risk of 34,
37; causal explanations, research methods and
3638;
comparative case studies, policy
feedback and 406;
comparative public policy
analysis 2930, 38; comparative public policy
research, varieties of 3036; demographic
change 32; generalizability 35, 36, 3839;
impact of policies, measures of 3032;
incomparability and incommensurability 31;
institutionalism 36; models for research on
decision-making processes, comparative analysis
of 3089; outcomes of policies, measures of
3132; outputs of policies, measures of 31, 33;
pattern-oriented studies 2930, 3335, 38;
Subject index
512
patterns of policy-making 2930; pension
politics 3233; policy agendas, comparative
studies of 16870, 173; policy change literature
29, 37, 38; policy convergence 29, 34, 36, 37,
39; policy diffusion 34, 36, 37; policy
dismantling 29, 30, 34, 35, 37, 38; policy
learning 35, 36; policy termination 29, 30, 33,
34, 35, 36, 37, 38; policy transfer or emulation
35, 36; process-oriented approaches 29, 30,
3536, 38; public expenditure, data on 32;
quantitative and qualitative studies, division
between 37; quantitative comparative
environmental policy research 33; replacement
rates, measurement of 32; research methods and
causal explanations 3638; veto players,
concept of 37
competency trap 4056
competitive public economies 8788, 89
complexity: assumption of increase in 299300;
constituencies, complex or unorganized,
representation of 35051; of institutional
analysis 121; policy problems, variable
complexities of 490; of policy process 350
Compliance Cost Assessment (CCA) 246
conicts: coalitions, level of conict between
13031; conict assessment 35455; dealing
with 486; policy communities, conict over
policy and 51; of values 35253; see also
disagreement and alternative dispute resolution
in policy process
Congressional Budget Ofce (CBO) 6
congressional dominance 81
consensual knowledge 29192
consensus building 34748; mediation theory and
35357
constituents, representation of 8081
consumer producers 9192
consumer protection 205
contested knowledge 35152, 359
contribution bias 220
coproduction 9192
Le Corbusier 9899
counter-epistemic communities 23435
counting, language of 191
crises as sources of nonincremental change
28990
critiques: anti-rationalist criticisms of incrementalism
29496; criticisms and limitations of GCM
32125; of goal-orientation and claried
ends
293; incrementalism in
analysis, critique of
hostility to 293; policy learning, criticisms of the
literature on 406; of randomized control trials
42029; rationalist criticisms of incrementalism
29394; of reactive nature of incrementalism
294; on training for policy analysis 11
cross-national differences in issue politicization
16970
decision-making: Betuwe railway line, events in
decision-making on 31415; bounded rationality,
public policy decision-making and 273;
decentralized decision-making 5; decision
environments, typology of 291; decision
heuristics 21922; democratic decision-making
7677; disagreement and alternative dispute
resolution in policy process 35657; expert
decision-making, theories of 217; horizontal
classication of 306; imposed decisions, fairness
and authority of 437; models for research on
decision-making processes, comparative analysis
of 3089; organizational settings,
decision-making and 21; over time, accounts of
46567; phase model of 300, 3023, 304, 306,
307, 308, 309, 311, 314, 315, 316;
policy-making process 2021; political systems
and decision-making processes 334, 33536,
33738; representation of 300, 3012; rounds
model of 300, 301, 302, 303, 3046, 308, 309,
310, 312, 314, 315, 316; styles of 21; tracks
model of 302, 3068, 309, 310, 313, 314, 315,
316; vertical classication of 306; see also
bounded rationality and public policy
decision-making; models for research on
decision-making processes, comparative
analysis of
decision theory 220
deductive social theories 5960
Deepwater Horizon oil spill 177, 178
denitions: bureaucracy 33132; evaluation 387;
institution, multiple denitions of term
11617; policy analysis 4; policy appraisal
24546; randomized control trials 41719
deliberation: deliberative forms of public
participation 442; nding and packageing
options 356
democracy: in arguments on evaluation 396; in
decision-making 7677; democratic control
and bureaucratic autonomy 334; in social
planning 98
Democracy in America (de
Tocqueville, A.) 90
democratization:
analytical styles 257, 258, 264;
evaluation, public participation and 437
demographic change 32, 180, 423
dependent populations 226
dependent variables 236; problem of 45253
description, dimensions of 19091
design: designing process 21819; of policy
analysis 26667; principles in IAD,
identication of 121; and recommendation of
analytical styles 25657, 258, 264
deterministic causal patterns 476
development management and policy
implementation 37482; constituencies,
building up 380; developing countries, context
of 381; development, management for and of
Subject index
513
374; development administration 374;
development management, perspectives on
37576, 38182; development management
debates 37778; diagnostic and analytic tools
381; donor-driven development policy 381;
impact monitoring 380; institutional agendas,
means to 376; international development policy
implementation 37980; legitimacy, creation of
37980; modernization 37576;
multidimensional denition of development
management 37677; multiple modernities
376; Organisation for Economic Co-operation
and Development (OECD) Paris Principles
378; organizational structures, modication of
380; planning and management toolkit,
provision of 37677; policy implementation,
development management and 37879; policy
implementation management 38081; process
dimension of development management 377;
radicalism 377, 378; reformism 377, 378, 381;
resources, accumulation of 380; resources,
mobilization of 380; values associated with
development management 376
devil shift 126, 128
diagnostic and analytic tools 381
disagreement and alternative dispute resolution in
policy process 34759; Advocacy Coalition
Framework (ACF) 352; best alternative to a
negotiated agreement (BATNA) 349, 356,
35758; complex or unorganized constituencies,
representation of 35051; complexity of policy
process 350; conict assessment 35455;
conicts of values 35253; consensus building
34748; consensus building, mediation theory
and 35357; contested knowledge 35152, 359;
convening, getting problem and parties right
35455; decision-making 35657; deliberation,
nding and packaging options 356;
disagreement, natural feature of policy process
347; disagreement and negotiation 347, 358;
group polarization 353; implementation 357;
interests and positions, separation of 34849;
mediation theory 34748, 35357; negotiation
theory 347; negotiation theory, consensus
building theory and 35354; negotiation
theory, starting point 34849; negotiations (and
disagreements)
in policy processes,
reasons for
difculties with 34953, 35859; negotiations
and mediations in public sector, evaluation of
35758; problem denition 34849; process
benets 358; relationship benets 358; rules and
responsibilities, clarication of 35556; scale of
policy process 350; Seven Elements Framework
(Harvard Negotiation Project) 349; stakeholder
identication 355; substantive benets,
improved outcomes and 35758; values, frames,
and belief systems 35253
discussion: after focusing events, differences in
substance of 18082; agenda-setting and
political discourse 200201
donor-driven development policy 381
dual federalism in US 362
economic models of evaluation 388
educational products 91
e-governance 44243
empirical analysis: empirical and experimental
research, IAD and 12021; empirical
approaches in punctuated equilibrium theory
(PET) 14649; of epistemic communities
23036; focusing event theory and 180;
policy design and transfer, empirical perspective
on 223
Employee Retirement Income Security Act
(ERISA, 1974) 4023
engagement 115, 189, 231, 239, 368, 381, 444;
economic and political engagement 63;
e-engagement 443; evaluation, public
participation and 444; innovative forms of
public engagement 44143; public engagement
(or citizen engagement) 47, 50, 435, 437,
44142, 44344; stakeholder engagement 67,
438, 488, 491; transnational engagement 51
Environmental Impact Assessment (EIA) 246, 248
environmental media coverage in Canada,
expository analysis 20811
epistemic communities 22941; as analytical
frameworks, challenge of 23233; calculation,
learning as 239; counter-epistemic communities
23435; decit model of learning 23637;
dependent variables 236; in dynamic policy
environments 23334, 235; empirical analysis of
23036; in European Union (EU) 233; expert
inuence
over decision-maker learning
230;
governance, networks and intergovernmental
systems 368; identication of epistemic community
belief systems, challenge of 23031; independent
variables 238; instrumental, learning as 238;
knowledge consensus and temporally bounded
truth 235; knowledge elements within belief
systems 22930; learning interactions between
epistemic communities and policy elites 23840;
learning process 23637; legitimacy, learning as
239; microfoundations of learning and 238;
persuasion and socialization, learning as 23839;
policy cycles and 23536; politics of ideas and
22930; in real world of politics 234; relating
micro world of learning to macro world of
policy outputs 240; renaissance of knowledge
230; resonance across social scientic disciplines
23132; theoretical challenges 23640;
unreective, learning as 23940
European Union (EU): Common Agricultural
Policy (CAP) of 477, 479, 480, 489; epistemic
Subject index
514
communities in 233; European Commission
Impact Assessment system 24647
evaluation, models of 387400; anticipated
side-effects 391; choice of evaluation models
399; client-oriented evaluation, pros and cons
of 39394; client-oriented model 39294;
collegial models 39799; denition of
evaluation 387; democratic arguments 396;
economic models 388; goal-attainment model,
strength and shortcomings of 38990;
goal-attainment model (effectiveness model)
38890; goal catalogs 390; group deliberations
396; haziness argument 38990; indeterminate
goals 389; knowledge argument 396; merit
criteria 38788; null effects 391; peer review,
self-evaluation and combinations thereof
39799; perverse effects 391; relevance model
392; resource-demands of stakeholder model
39697; responsive evaluation 39497;
self-evaluation 397; side-effects model 39092;
stakeholder evaluation, upsides and downsides
of 39697; stakeholder model 39497; subject
matter to be appraised 388, 390; Swedish
National Agency for Higher Education
ten-steps evaluation policy 398; unintended
side-effects 390; utilization argument 396
evaluation, public participation and 43444;
argumentative tradition 435; citizen-led
performance management 43637; citizen
surveys 43940; citizens juries 44142; client
focus 436; collaborative web technologies
44243; deliberative forms of public
participation 442; democratization 437;
e-governance 44243; engagement 444; fourth
generation evaluation 436; imposed decisions,
fairness and authority of 437; innovative forms
of public engagement 44143; knowledge,
accommodation of alternative forms of 444;
managerial efciency 43738; New Public
Management (NPM) 436; Organisation for
Economic Co-operation and Development
(OECD) 437; participation in policy evaluation,
role of 43537; participation in policy evaluation,
who and how? 43839; participatory mechanisms
439; participatory policy evaluation, challenges
of 44344; performance management 436;
political nature of policy evaluation 435; public
meetings and hearings 44041; public
participation in policy, drivers for 43738;
public value 436; publics, communities and
43839;
rationalistic or traditional models of
policy analysis 43435;
stakeholder groups 438;
tensions, generation of 44344; tokenism 443
evaluation criteria: analytical styles and 263;
evaluation and evaluation criteria, shifting from
government to governance approach 30910;
evaluation of policy analysis 267
event-driven policy change and learning, theory
of 186
event-triggered group mobilization 179
evidence-based policy, calls for 415
exogenous change and policy trajectories 469
exogenous problems in process sequencing 477
external variables in IAD 11820
Exxon Valdez disaster 178, 181, 184, 185
failure: cultivation of 492; exploitation of 492;
generating risk of 49192; masking of 49091;
media interest in 487; methodological
difculties of ascertaining success and
failure 48487; toleration of 48990; see also
learning, success or failure and
falsiability 321
federalism and separation of powers, principles of 90
The Federalist 90
feedback: comparative case studies, policy
feedback and 406; feedback loop and
policy-making process 24; indicators,
interconnections with focusing events and
feedback 185; institutional choice, positive
feedback cycles and 14244; institutions and
negative feedback cycles 14041; negative
feedback cycles 13839; policy feedback,
learning and precedent 47880; policy
incrementalism, negative feedback cycles and
13940; positive feedback, disproportionate
information-processing and 28182; positive
feedback cycles 139; in process sequencing
47879; see also policy feedback, learning
nancial feasibility 36667
scal authority 63
focusing events and policy windows 17586; actor
promoted events (APEs) 184; Advocacy
Coalition Framework (ACF) 175, 186;
agenda-setting, focusing events as aspects of
17577; agenda-setting process, focusing events
in 175; aggregation of harms 176; circumstantial
reactors 176; Deepwater Horizon oil spill 177,
178; discussion after focusing events, differences
in substance of 18082; empirical applications
of focusing event theory 180; event-driven
policy change and learning, theory of 186;
event-triggered group mobilization 179; Exxon
Valdez disaster 178, 181, 184, 185; focusing
event idea, broader applications of the 18285;
focusing
events and policy
change 18586;
focusing events in attracting media 206;
foundations of focusing event theory 17778;
group activity 178; group coalescence and
mobilization, special role of 17879; group
competition 175; Hurricane Katrina 177;
indicators, interconnections with focusing
events and feedback 185; internal mobilization
178; language, use of 178; negative attention
Subject index
515
177; non-actor promoted events (NAPEs) 184;
political mobilization, role of 17677; potential
focusing events 177; September 11 terrorist
attacks 177, 180, 185; sudden events 176;
symbol propagation 176; Three Mile Island
nuclear accident 178, 179; Type One and Type
Two events 185, 186
frameworks: advocacy coalition framework (ACF)
12627; Institutional Analysis and Development
(IAD) framework 116
framing: agenda-setting and political discourse
190, 19293; frame analysis, agenda-setting and
193; framing effects in policy design and
transfer 222; framing theory 2067
future research: bureaucracy and policy process 342;
international dimensions and dynamics of
policy-making 55; policy appraisal 251; policy
network research 16061; process sequencing 481
game models: games and decisions, theory of 98;
institutional analysis and political economy 93
garbage can model (GCM), study of policy-making
process and 32028; alignment of streams
32324, 32526; antecedent conditions 323;
Birklands work 32627; criticisms and
limitations of GCM 32125; falsiability 321;
focus of GCM 320; hypotheses derived from
GCM, testing of 327; international dimensions
and dynamics of policy-making 51;
McLendons work 326; origins and description
of GCM 32021; paradigmatic problems 325;
policy formulation and adoption 323; politics
and problems, links between 324; politics
stream 32021; problems and solutions, links
between 32425; problems stream 32021;
randomness and separation of streams 32325;
September 11 terrorist attacks 327; situational
versus structural levels of analysis 32122;
solutions and politics, links between 324;
solutions stream 32021; studies employing
GCM 32527; Zahariadis work 32526
gender analysis 9
generalizability: comparative approaches to study
of public policy-making 35, 36, 3839; state
theory, regulatory state and 59
Germany, policy network analyses in 157
global warming debate 2078
globalization: nancial crisis, policy analysis and 8;
global communication, velocity and volume of 51;
and global dynamics 4445, 5455; inuences on
policy-making 46, 47; interest in, policy network
models
and 15960; policy
analysis and 7
goal-attainment model (effectiveness model) 38890;
strength and shortcomings of 38990
goals: goal catalogs 390; goal-orientation and
claried ends 293; indeterminate goals 389;
policy design and transfer 223
governance, networks and intergovernmental
systems 36171; building blocks 36768;
characteristics of network functioning 364;
chartered networks 364; collaboration 361, 367,
369, 370; communities of practice 368; dual
federalism doctrine in US 362; epistemic
communities 368; nancial feasibility 36667;
governance networks and added value 36970;
governance networks and public policy
36465, 371; intergovernmental relations,
transformation of 36265. 37071;
intergovernmental relations (IGR) 362, 363,
36465; learning and network management
36871; legal dimension, networked actions
and 366; market superiority 36263; network
activation 36667; network constructs 36364;
network formation 36567; network
management, learning and 36871; network
operation 36768; networks working 36364;
New Public Management (NPM) 363;
organized actors outside government 362;
policy design and implementation 370; policy
implementation 36566; politics of activities
between and among organizations 367; social
policies 362; welfare state 362, 36465
Government Accountability Ofce 6
granularity of perspective, issue of 46869
groups: coalescence and mobilization, special role
of 17879; deliberations within 396;
event-triggered group mobilization 179;
exchange of resources between lawmakers and
interest groups 158; group activity, focusing
events and policy windows 178; group
competition 175; interest groups, experts,
advocacy coalitions, and bureaucrats with
vested interests 172; interest groups,
participation of 14446; polarization of 353;
stakeholder groups 438; treatment and control
groups, treatment effects and 41719
Guantanamo Bay 48990
Hawthorne effects 422, 431n15
haziness argument 38990
health care 18, 49, 63, 91, 121, 138, 16869,
173,
18485, 193, 201,
362, 399, 405, 442, 464,
47071
heterogeneity 42425
heuristics: bounded rationality and public policy
decision-making 27778; decision heuristics
21922
historical institutionalism: historical institutionalist
theory, policy change in 469; process
sequencing and perspective of 47475; rise of
the broad school of 462, 471
human choice, model of 273, 277
human goals, pursuit of 273
Hurricane Katrina 177, 220
Subject index
516
Hussein, Saddam 485, 491
hypotheses: derived from GCM, testing of 327;
hypotheses building and testing 129, 131, 133
IAP2 439
immigration, politicization of 169
impact monitoring: development management
and policy implementation 380; measures of
impact of policies 3032
implementation: disagreement and alternative
dispute resolution in policy process 357;
structures for, policy design and transfer 224
implicit theories and assumptions in ACF 12627
incrementalism 28797; advantages of 28889; as
alternative to rational ideal 28789; American
context, special problems in 29697; analysis,
critique of hostility to 293; anti-rationalist
criticisms 29496; business advantage in resources
296; capitalist societies 296; Clean Air
Amendments Act (1970) 290; consensual
knowledge 29192; crises as sources of
nonincremental change 28990; decision
environments, typology of 291; federal role
breakthrough policies 292; goal-orientation and
claried ends, critique of 293; incremental
alternatives, limiting focus to 288; incremental
and non-incremental policy change 139;
incremental model of policy-making 21;
incremental rationalizing policies 292; life cycle
of policies 292; majority-building incrementalism
290; margin-dependent choice 28889; mass
public opinion as catalyst for nonincremental
change 290; nonincremental change,
preconditions for 28992; objectives to policies,
adjustment of 288; partisan mutual adjustment
288; policies resulting from, trustworthiness of
29297; policy change, quadrants of 289, 291;
policy-making through social interaction, system
of 29697; policy process, serial or repetitive
nature of 289; rational decision-making,
attainment of conditions for 29092; rationalist
criticisms 29394; rationality, breakdown of
28788; rationalizing breakthroughs 292;
reactive nature of, critique of 294; remediality
288; sleeper effects, inability to deal with 294;
social fragmentation of analysis 288
independent variables: epistemic communities
238; policy-making process 20
individuals, attributes of 131
inductive social theories 5960
informal institutions, importance of 121
informal processes, postpositivism and 107
information-processing 27980
information rules 119
informational weight 405
inquiries: inquiry commissions, expanding learning
potential of government 4078; politics of 491
Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD)
framework 11521; action situations and arenas
11718; aggregation rules 119; applications of
12021; authority rules 119; boundary rules
119; bounded rationality and public policy
decision-making 273; change, policy dynamics
and 456, 457, 458; collective choice level rules
117; collective goals 121; community, attributes
of 11920; constitutional choice level rules 117;
design principles, identication
of 121;
empirical and experimental
research 12021;
external variables 11820; frameworks 116;
informal institutions, importance of 121;
information rules 119; institution, multiple
denitions of term 11617; institutional
analysis, complexity of 121; institutional
analysis, political economy and 9293, 95n4;
institutional change, studies of 120; institutions
11617; linking arenas 120; material context,
attributes of 119; models 116; payoff rules 119;
position rules 119; public choice perspective
8283; rules as shared prescriptions 11617;
rules-in-use 119; scope rules 119; theories 116;
universal elements, identication of 116;
Workshop in Political Theory and Policy
Analysis, Indiana University 11516
institutional analysis and political economy 8795;
bounded rationality 92; collective action,
problematic circumstances of 94; common-pool
resource (CPR) 92; competitive public
economies 8788, 89; consumer producers
9192; coproduction 9192; Democracy in
America (de Tocqueville, A.) 90; educational
products 91; federalism and separation of
powers, principles of 90; game models 93;
Institutional Analysis and Development (IAD)
framework 9293, 95n4; institutionalism 87;
monocentrism and polycentricity 8991, 95n3;
New Public Management (NPM) 89;
organization of metropolitan governance in US
88; political economy and analysis of
non-market decision settings 8789. 9495n1,
95n2; political economy institutionalism
approach 88, 89, 92, 94; polycentricity,
monocentrism and 8991, 95n3; public goods
and services 87; public policy analysis 9394,
95n5, 95n7; rational choice theory (RCT) 93;
service paradox 91; service providers 88
institutional choice, positive feedback cycles and
14244
institutional friction, disproportionate
information-processing and 281
institutional structure of bureaucracy 333
institutionalism: comparative approaches to study
of public policy-making 36; emergence of a
new across social sciences 462; institutional
analysis and political economy 87
Subject index
517
institutions: deconstruction of 101; Institutional
Analysis and Development (IAD) framework
11617; negative feedback cycles and 14041;
social construction of 100
instrumental learning 238, 249
integration of relationships, degree and patterns
of 47
intellectual laziness 220
intended rationality, principle of 27475
interactivity: interacting activities, analytical styles
and 25658, 267; interaction processes,
ingredients of 3068; interactive style of analysis
261; with rounds model 3056
interdependences: advocacy coalition framework
(ACF) 133; international dimensions and
dynamics of policy-making 46
interdisciplinarity, policy network models and 154
interessement 107
interest groups: experts, advocacy coalitions, and
bureaucrats with vested interests 172; interests
and positions, separation of 34849;
participation of 14446
intergovernmental relations (IGR): governance,
networks and intergovernmental systems 362,
363, 36465; negotiations between governments
53; transformation of 36265. 37071
intergovernmental systems see governance,
networks and intergovernmental systems
internal mobilization, focusing events and 178
internal validity of randomized control trials 419,
431n15
international dimensions and dynamics of
policy-making 4455; Advocacy Coalition
Framework (ACF) 48; American auto
manufacturers 4546; capital movements,
liberalization of 46; cultural characteristics 46;
future research 55; garbage can model of
policy-making 51; global communication,
velocity and volume of 51; global inuences on
policy-making 46, 47; globalization and global
dynamics 4445, 5455; integration of
relationships, degree and patterns of 47;
interdependence 46; intergovernmental
negotiations 53; international development
policy implementation 37980; international
forces in policy studies 45; international
policy-making, bureaucracy and 33839;
internationalized policy environments,
mediating inuence of 5154; loose couplings,
context of 54; policy communities 4748;
policy communities, conict over policy and
51; policy network typologies 4849; policy
options, development of alternatives 5051;
policy paradigms and governance networks
4951,
55; policy subsystems 4445, 46, 47,
48,
49, 50, 5354, 55; political authority 48;
political boundaries, erosion of 4647; political
boundaries, policy explanations and
permeability of 4549; public power, sharing of
47; public sector activism 5253; self-regulatory
and private regimes 54; sovereignty, pooling of
47; state and society, interactions between 47;
strategic maneuvering of policy actors 48;
supranational governing arrangements,
institutionalization of 5253; transmission
mechanisms, policy paradigms and 50;
transnational policy communities 49, 53, 54,
55; transnational political forces 46
International Finance Corporation (IFC) 66
interorganizational relations 155
interpretive tendencies 485
Interstate Commerce Commission 5
interventionist and regulatory state, typology of
6872
interventions of interest, randomization concerns
427
Iran-Contra affair to Iraq 99
issue attention cycle 205
issue framing: mass media and policy-making
2067; punctuated equilibrium theory (PET) of
agenda-setting and policy change 145
issue networks 125
issue types 2056
Johnson, Lyndon B. 99
Joint Committees in US 408
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 10, 12
journalistic norms 2078
jurisdictional areas 33233
Kaiser Family Foundation 138, 150n1
knowledge: accommodation of alternative forms
of 444; consensual knowledge 29192;
consensus and temporally bounded truth 235;
contested knowledge 35152, 359; elements
within belief systems 22930; know-recommend
strategy 278; knowledge argument in evaluation
396; knowledge-based power 336; renaissance
of 230; think tanks, knowledge base of 6
language: counting, language of 191; narrative,
language and 190, 193, 19495; public language
of policy and political elites 484; use in focusing
events 178
leadership role, bureaucracy in 337
learning: conceptual learning 249; decit model of
23637; educational products 91; epistemic
communities and learning process 23637;
expert inuence over decision-maker learning
230; as instrumental 238, 249; interactions
between epistemic communities and policy
elites and 23840; as legitimacy 239;
microfoundations of learning and epistemic
communities 238; network management and
Subject index
518
36871; networks, learning and management of
36871; policy feedback and 40110
learning, success or failure and 48493;
ambiguities, dealing with 486; benchmarks,
multiplicity of 48586; blame games 491;
conicts, dealing with 486; discursive
tendencies 485; European Union (EU),
Common Agricultural Policy of 489; failure,
cultivation of 492; failure, exploitation of 492;
failure, generating risk of 49192; failure,
masking of 49091; failure, toleration of
48990; failure and media interest 487;
Guantanamo Bay 48990; inquiries, politics of
491; interpretive tendencies 485;
methodological difculties of ascertaining
success and failure 48487; nature of policy
success and policy failure 48789; perceptions,
differences in 485; placebo policies 490; policy
effect, isolation of 487; policy-making as
juggling of success and failure 48992; policy
problems, variable complexities of 490; policy
success, denition of 487; policy success,
phenomenon of 484, 492; policy success,
realms of 48889; political success 48889;
process success 488; process success and risks of
programme and political failure 49192;
programme success 488; public language of
policy and political elites 484; rational-scientic
tradition 485; shortfalls, dealing with 486;
spectrum of outcomes, possibility for 487;
success for whom? 486; variance over time 486
legal dimension, networked actions and 366
legal-rational foundation of bureaucracy 33233
legitimacy: creation of 37980; learning as 239;
legitimate power, policy network models and 154
lexicographic strategy 276
life cycle of policies 292
linking arenas 120
lobbying 337
logic of direction problem 45354
long-term time perspective 127
loose couplings, context of 54
macro and subsystem politics, conceptions of
17172
macro-level systems, policy network models and
15354
macro political attention, shifts in 13839
macro-political institutions 17071
majority-building incrementalism 290
majority rule 79
managerial efciency
43738
The Managerial Revolution (Burnham,
J.) 335
margin-dependent choice 28889
marginalization of politics 407
markets: globalization and 6263; market
superiority 36263
mass media and policy-making 20411;
agenda-setting and issue attentiveness 2056;
climate change debate 2078; consumer
protection 205; environmental coverage in
Canada, expository analysis 20811; focusing
events in attracting media 206; framing theory
2067; global warming debate 2078; issue
attention cycle 205; issue framing 2067; issue
types 2056; journalistic norms 2078; mass
public opinion as catalyst for nonincremental
change 290; media as policy actor, challenges of
2078; media coverage of complicated policy
domains 2078; media effects, timing of 204;
newsroom norms and long-term policy
domains 208; policy re-framing 207; political
communication 207; political issues in public
discussion 208; problem identication 2067;
thematic frames 207
mechanistic perspective, positives of 458
median voter theorem 80
mediation: analytical styles and 257, 258, 264;
mediation theory 34748, 35357
merit criteria 38788
metaphor 20, 49, 53, 178, 184, 191, 193, 194,
231, 263, 279, 300. 303, 320, 321, 451, 463,
46567, 474, 490
methodologies: difculties of ascertaining
success and failure 48487; methodological
individualism 77
microeconomics: parametric rationality and 467;
policy analysis and 1011, 12
Mind and Society (Pareto, V.) 27475
mobilization 18, 127, 130, 14445, 17679, 184,
190, 296, 32021, 403, 438; of bias 491;
postpositivism and policy process 107
modalities
of governance 6566
models
for research on decision-making processes
299317; comparative analysis of models
3089; complexity, assumption of increase in
299300; decision-making, representation of
300, 3012; evaluation and evaluation criteria,
shifting from government to governance
approach 30910; horizontal classication of
decision-making 306; Institutional Analysis and
Development (IAD) framework 11521;
interaction processes, ingredients of 3068;
interactivity with rounds model 3056; phase
model, concepts within and principles of 300,
3023, 304, 306, 307, 308, 309, 311, 314, 315,
316; policy adoption 30910; policy
formulation 302; reconstruction of
decision-making, models for 299302, 31617;
research questions 300; rounds model 300, 301,
302, 303, 3046, 308, 309, 310, 312, 314, 315,
316; search for and choice of solutions,
problems preceding 303; stream model,
concepts within and principles of 300, 301,
Subject index
519
3034, 305, 306, 308, 309, 311, 314, 315, 318;
tracks model of decision-making 302, 3068,
309, 310, 313, 314, 315, 316; vertical
classication of decision-making 306; see also
Betuwe railway line
modernization and modernization theory 37576
monocentrism and polycentricity 8991, 95n3
motivated reasoning 278
multidimensional denition of development
management 37677
multiple modernities 376
multiple parties, competition between 80
Multiple Stream Approach (MSA) 452, 456, 457
narrative: explanatory function of 19495;
language and agenda-setting 190, 193, 19495;
narrative approaches to policy process 1034,
1078; September 11th, narrative explanation
of 19495; story lines within public policy
discourse 194
negative attention 177
negative feedback cycles 13839
negotiation theory: consensus building theory and
35354; disagreement and alternative dispute
resolution in policy process 347; starting point
for dispute resolution 34849
negotiations: and mediations in public sector,
evaluation of 35758; in policy processes,
reasons for difculties with 34953, 35859
neo-institutionalism 6061; neo-institutionalist
theories 452
networks: activation of 36667; characteristics of
network functioning 364; chartered networks
364; collaborations and, notion of 341;
formation of 36567; management of, learning
and 36871; network constructs 36364;
network theories, core assumptions of 154;
networks working 36364; operation of
36768; see also governance, networks and
intergovernmental systems; policy model networks
New Directions in the Study of Community Elites
(Laumann, E. and Pappi, F.) 157
New Public Management (NPM): evaluation,
public participation and 436; governance,
networks and intergovernmental systems 363;
institutional analysis and political economy 89;
movement for 338, 34041; policy appraisal
250; policy network models 161; practices 7
New Zealand Business Round Table (NZBRT)
78
newsroom
norms, long-term policy
domains and
208
Next Steps programme 64
non-actor promoted events (NAPEs) 184
non-increasing returns mechanisms 466
noncontradictory argumentation 193
nonincremental change, preconditions for 28992
normative perspective: path dependency 47071;
policy design and transfer 222
null effects 391
Obama, Barack (and administration of) 198, 199,
486, 48990
Occupy Wall Street, case of 195, 198200
open subsystems 1920
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and
Development (OECD) 437, 444; core
principles of regulatory reform 24445, 246;
evaluation, public participation and 437; Paris
Principles 378
organization of metropolitan governance in US 88
organizational form, bureaucracy as 33233
organizational learning 405
The Organizational State (Laumann, E. and Knoke,
D.) 157
organizational state model of policymaking
15556
organizations: bounded rationality and public
policy decision-making 27879; distinction
between different types of 129; organized actors
outside government 362; organized interests
145; settings within, decision-making and 21;
structures of, modication of 380
Our Wonderland of Bureaucracy (Beck, J.M.) 335
outcomes of policies, measures of 3132
outputs of policies, measures of 31, 33
paradigmatic problems 325
parliamentary systems 6
parsimony 420, 42425
participation: deliberative forms of public
participation 442; interest groups, participation
of 14446; participatory mechanisms 439;
participatory policy evaluation, challenges of
44344; participatory style 260; in policy
evaluation, role of 43537; in policy evaluation,
who and how? 43839; see also evaluation,
public participation and
partisan mutual adjustment 288
path dependence: concept of 402, 403; distinct
approaches to temporal analysis 47475,
48081; increasing returns and 466; Path
Dependence Framework (PDF) 452, 456, 457;
path-dependent sequencing and process (or
problem solving) sequencing, distinction
between 476; policy trajectories and legacies
46264, 46465, 46571
Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act
(PPACA) 138, 150n1
pattern-oriented studies of policy making 2930,
3335,
38
payoff rules 119
peer
review, self-evaluation and combinations
thereof 39799
Subject index
520
pension politics 3233
pension provision (UK) 464
perceptions, differences in 485
performance management 436
perspectives: on eld of policy analysis 26567; on
policy analysis, framework for understanding
and design 255
persuasion and socialization, learning as 23839
perverse effects 391
phase model, concepts within and principles of
300, 3023, 304, 306, 307, 308, 309, 311, 314,
315, 316
phat dependence 466
phenomenological description 106
placebo policies 490
planning and management toolkit, provision of
37677
policy actors 30, 33, 45, 4748, 4951, 52, 54,
158, 205, 305, 403; epistemic communities
233. 235, 238, 239, 240; policy dynamics and
change 453, 458, 45960; policy evaluation and
public participation 435, 441, 443;
policy-making process 17, 18, 19, 23, 24;
policy problems and 47780, 481; policy
trajectories and legacies 467, 469, 47071;
postpositivism and the policy process 101, 103,
104, 105, 106, 1078
policy adoption: models for research on
decision-making processes 30910; policy
feedback, learning and 406
policy advice: inuence of advisors 7, 8; policy
analysis 4
policy agenda-setting studies 16773;
agenda-policy hypothesis 17071;
agenda-setting approach, tradition of 16768,
173; Agendas and Instability in American
Politics (Baumgartner and Jones) 167; attention,
public opinion and policy change, linking of
17072, 173; attention dynamics in executive
speeches 168, 169; comparative studies of
policy agendas 16870, 173; cross-national
differences in issue politicization 16970;
government change, role of elections and 168;
health care 169; immigration, politicization of
169; interest groups, experts, advocacy
coalitions, and bureaucrats with vested interests
172; macro and subsystem politics, conceptions
of 17172; macro-political institutions 17071;
policy agendas project (US) 17172; public
saliency, concept of 172; public spending as
measure of public policy 171; re-election,
orientation towards 171; societal problems,
provision of solutions to 16869
policy analysis: agenda setting 56; American
constitution, checks and balances in 6; analytical
capabilities available to politicians 6;
applications of 910; Association for Public
Policy Analysis and Management (APPAM) 10;
benet-cost
analysis 5; central agencies, strength
of 78; Congressional
Budget Ofce (CBO) 6;
critiques on training for 11; decentralized
decision-making 5; denition of 4; demand for,
evolution of 410; early representations 34;
gender analysis 9; global nancial crisis 8;
globalization 7; Government Accountability
Ofce 6; government programmes,
effectiveness of 7; Interstate Commerce
Commission 5; Journal of Policy Analysis and
Management 10; microeconomics and 1011,
12; New Public Management practices 7; New
Zealand Business Round Table (NZBRT) 78;
parliamentary systems 6; policy advising 4;
policy advisors, inuence of 7, 8; policy analysis
movement, prospects for 1314; policy analysts,
perceptions of 9; policy development 56;
policy problems, evolution of 5; policy sciences
4; policy solutions, appropriateness of
alternatives 5; policy studies 4; professional
socialization, teaching key components of
1112; public policies 4; race analysis 9;
redistribution, government role in 5; rise of
34; role of appraisal in 244, 250; role of policy
analyst 26365; sources of demand for 4; styles
of 25862; supply of, evolution of 1013;
supply of, trends in 1213; technical skills,
development of 12; think tanks, knowledge
base of 6; tools of 5
Policy and Comparative Agendas projects 149,
150n5, 150n8
policy appraisal 24451; administrative capacity
and effectiveness 245; appraisal processes as sites
of political behavior 245; appraisal systems,
research on design of 249; assessment of
operation of policy appraisal 248, 24950;
bureaucracy, political control of 249;
Compliance Cost Assessment (CCA) 246;
conceptual learning 249; denition of 24546;
Environmental Impact Assessment (EIA) 246,
248; European Commission Impact
Assessment system 24647; future for 251;
instrumental learning 249; New Public
Management (NPM) 250; Organisation for
Economic Co-operation and Developments
(OECD) core principles of regulatory reform
24445, 246; policy analysis, role of appraisal in
250; policy analysis and 244; policy appraisal
systems, diffusion of 247; policy formulation
and 244; policy-making change and 244;
political behavior, sites of 245; positivist
approaches to research 24748; post-positivist
approaches to research 24849; practice of
24647; Regulatory Impact Assessment (RIA)
246; research on 24749;
research-practice
relationships 24950; Strategic
Environmental
Subject index
521
Assessment (SEA) 246; Sustainability Impact
Assessment (SIA) 246
policy brokers 131
policy change: advocacy coalition framework
(ACF) 125, 127, 129, 13233, 133, 134;
literature on 29, 37, 38; orders and rates of 464;
puzzle of 452; quadrants of 289, 291; stability
and 46770; understanding in order to grasp
policy dynamics 45152
policy communities: conict over policy and 51;
international dimensions and dynamics of
policy-making 4748; policy-making
process 19
policy convergence 29, 34, 36, 37, 39
policy cycle model: policy cycles and epistemic
communities 23536; policy-making process 17
policy design and transfer 21727; agenda-setting
and political discourse 192; availability 21920;
benets to contenders 22526, 227; city design
and 219; cognitive biases and decision heuristics
21922; commonly copied policy designs
22527; contribution bias 220; decision
heuristics 21922; decision theory 220;
dependent populations 226; designing process
21819; empirical perspective 223; expert
decision-making, theories of 217; framing
effects 222; fundamental elements of designs
223; goals 223; implementation, boundaries
between 106; implementation,
intergovernmental systems and 370;
implementation, structures for 224; intellectual
laziness 220; normative perspective 222; policy
design as noun (policy content) 22225; policy
design as verb 21922; policy designing as
process 218; policy diffusion 21819; policy
invention, theories of 217; punishment and
discipline designs 226; rationales 22425, 226;
rationalist approach 218; rules 224, 226; target
populations 22324; target populations,
political powers of 22526; tools 224, 225;
underlying assumptions 225; value allocation
224; wildres in Arizona, McCain s response to
22122
policy development: policy analysis and 56; as
policy style 24; process of 17; see also policy
formulation; policy-making process
policy diffusion: comparative approaches to study
of public policy-making 34, 36, 37; policy
design and transfer 21819; policy feedback,
learning and 405
policy direction, notion of 468
policy dismantling 29, 30, 34, 35, 37, 38
policy domain: communication and resource
exchange networks 156; concept of 155
policy dynamics, change and 45160
policy effect, isolation of 487
policy entrepreneurs 14446
policy
evaluation styles 2324
policy
feedback, learning and 40110; American
Association of Retired Persons 403;
beneciaries, empowerment of 402; British
Pension Commission 409; bureaucratic
organization, creation of 402; commissions,
membership of 409; commissions, role in
defeating policy feedback and policy learning
barriers 4079; comparative case studies 406;
competency trap 4056; Employee Retirement
Income Security Act (ERISA, 1974) 4023;
Galtons problem 4067; informational weight
405; initial adoption of policies 402; inquiry
commissions, expanding learning potential of
government 4078; Joint Committees in US
408; McDonald Commission in Canada 408;
marginalization of politics 407; organizational
learning 405; path dependence, concept of 402,
403; policy adoption 406; policy diffusion 405;
policy feedback 4013, 40910; policy
feedback, logic of 403; policy impact of
commissions 4089; policy instruments, policy
diffusion and 405; policy learning 401, 4037,
40910; policy learning, criticisms of the
literature on 406; policy reversal 402; positive
and negative policy feedback, distinction
between 403; process sequencing and
precedent 47880; qualitative research designs
406; Social Security Association 403; terms of
reference 409
policy formulation: adoption and 323; models for
research on decision-making processes 302;
policy appraisal and 244; policy-making process
1820
Policy Generations Framework (PGF) 452, 456,
457
policy implementation: development management
and 37879, 38081; governance, networks
and intergovernmental systems 36566;
incrementalism, negative feedback cycles and
13940; instruments of, policy diffusion and
405; policy implementers, bureaucrats as
33940; postmodern condition and institutions
1045; styles of 2223
policy invention, theories of 217
policy learning: comparative approaches to study
of public policy-making 35, 36; criticisms of
literature on 406; policy feedback, learning and
401, 4037, 40910
policy legacies 468
policy-making process 1724; bounded rationality
2021; bureaucrats as policy-makers 33639;
change
and policy appraisal
244;
decision-making 2021; decision-making, styles
of 21; feedback loop 24; incremental model of
policy-making 21; independent variables 20;
initiation, outside and inside 18; juggling of
Subject index
522
success and failure in 48992; lesson-drawing
24; open subsystems 1920; organizational
settings, decision-making and 21; policy
behavior in policy cycle, styles of 1821; policy
communities 19; policy cycle model 17; policy
development as policy style 24; policy
development process 17; policy evaluation
styles 2324; policy formulation 1820; policy
implementation styles 2223; policy-making
through social interaction, system of 29697;
policy networks 19; policy subsystems 19;
power of ideas 19; procedural instruments
2223; rational model of decision-making
2021; social learning 24; substantive
instruments 22; systemic agenda 18
policy network models 15361; Advocacy
Coalition Framework (ACF) 161; asymmetrical
power 154; exchange of resources between
lawmakers and interest groups 158; future
directions for policy network research 16061;
Germany, policy network analyses in 157;
globalization, interest in 15960;
interdisciplinarity 154; interorganizational
relations 155; key ideas in modern policy
network analysis 158; legitimate power 154;
macro-level systems 15354; network theories,
core assumptions of 154; network typologies
4849; New Public Management (NPM) 161;
organizational state model of policymaking
15556; policy domain, communication and
resource exchange networks 156; policy
domain, concept of 155; policy network
analyses, history and development of 15658;
policy network theory and empirical research
15860; policy networks, as units of analysis
154; policy networks, denition of 153; power
imbalances, policy exchanges and 158;
rationality of actors, assumption of 158; research
on, future challenges 16061; social network
theory 15356; United Kingdom, policy
network analyses in 15758; United States,
policy network analyses in 157
Policy Networks in British Government (Marsh, D.
and Rhodes, R.A.W.) 15758
policy options, development of alternatives 5051
policy-oriented learning 125, 13032, 133
policy paradigms and governance networks 4951,
55
policy preferences, society and 60
policy problems: evolution of 5; policy actors and
47780; variable complexities of 490
policy process: deconstruction of 1058; policy
process research 125; serial or repetitive nature
of 289
policy re-framing 207
policy-relevant social theories 59
policy reversal 402
policy sciences 4
policy solutions, appropriateness of alternatives 5
policy stability and rapid change, forces leading to
139
policy
studies 4
policy subsystems:
advocacy coalition framework
(ACF) 134; composition of 12829;
international dimensions and dynamics of
policy-making 4445, 46, 47, 48, 49, 50,
5354, 55; policy-making process 19; policy
processes and 126
policy success: denition of 487; phenomenon of
484, 492; realms of 48889
policy targeting 22, 23, 102, 143, 145
policy termination 29, 30, 33, 34, 35, 36, 37, 38
policy think tanks 98
policy thought, turning points in 100102
policy trajectories and legacies 46271;
decision-making over time, accounts of
46567; dualism between stability and change
468; exogenous change and 469; granularity of
perspective, issue of 46869; historical
institutionalism, rise of the broad school of 462,
471; historical institutionalist theory, policy
change in 469; institutionalism, emergence of a
new across social sciences 462;
microeconomics, parametric rationality and
467; non-increasing returns mechanisms 466;
normative aspects of path dependency 47071;
path dependency 46264, 46465, 46571;
path dependency, increasing returns and 466;
pension provision (UK) 464; phat dependence
466; policy change, orders and rates of 464;
policy change and stability 46770; policy
direction, notion of 468; policy legacies 468;
policy trajectories and legacies, benets of path
dependency for understanding 46465; policy
trajectories and legacies, problems of path
dependency for understanding 46571; primary
care sector (UK) 467; social causation 463;
social efciency 470; social housing (UK) 465;
social inefciency 47071; temporality, change
and history in social and political analysis,
interest in 462
policy transfer or emulation 35, 36
policymaking in an interpretive world 1024
political behavior: of advocacy coalitions 12930;
sites of 245
political boundaries: erosion of 4647; policy
explanations and permeability of 4549
political economics: analysis of non-market
decision settings 8789. 9495n1, 95n2;
political economy institutionalism approach 88,
89, 92, 94; schools of 8485
politics: actions of politicians, public choice
perspective and 78, 8081;
of activities between
and
among organizations 367; of ideas,
Subject index
523
epistemic communities and 22930; issues in
public discussion 208; mobilization, role in
focusing events 17677; nature of policy
evaluation 435; need for politicians, public
choice perspective and 78, 7980; political
authority 48, 158, 4089; political
communication 207; politics-administration
dichotomy debate 33334; politics stream in
GCM 32021; and problems, links between
324; re-election, orientation towards 171;
success in 48889; systems of, decision-making
processes and 334, 33536, 33738; systems of,
interdependences of economic systems and
33435
Politics (Aristotle) 102
The Politics of Bureaucracy (Peters, B.G.) 335 36
polycentricity, monocentrism and 8991, 95n3
position rules in IAD 119
positive feedback: cycles of 139; disproportionate
information-processing and 28182; positive
and negative policy feedback, distinction
between 403
positive political theory 80
postpositivism and policy process 98109;
communicative model of rationality 1045;
democratic social planning 98; enrollment 107;
games and decisions, theory of 98; informal
processes 107; institutions, deconstruction of
101; institutions, social construction of 100;
interessement 107; Iran-Contra affair to Iraq 99;
mobilization 107; narrative approaches 1034,
1078; phenomenological description 106;
policy appraisal and postpositivist approaches to
research 24748, 24849; policy design and
implementation, boundaries between 106;
policy institutions, postmodern condition and
1045; policy process, deconstruction of 1058;
policy think tanks 98; policy thought, turning
points in 100102; policymaking in an
interpretive world 1024; post-constructionist
understanding of policy process 108; practice of
policy, turning points in 98100;
problematisation 106; rational policy-making
9899; rationalization of society 99; social
construction, problem of 1089; social
experimentation 99; social issues, wicked
problems of 99100; social judgments 1034;
spin doctoring 1034; structural theory of
meaning 100; telos of policy 101; Tennessee
Valley
Authority 99; thinking
about policy,
intellectual revolutions on 100101; Troubled
Asset Relief Program (TARP) 101, 1023;
weapons of mass destruction (WMDs) in Iraq
108; Wittgensteins philosophical treatise on
logic 100
power: agenda-setting and inuential and
powerful interests 189; asymmetrical power
154; beneciaries, empowerment of 402;
bureaucratic power and dilemma for democracy
334; federalism and separation of powers,
principles of 90; of ideas 19; imbalances in,
policy exchanges and 158; knowledge-based
power 336; legitimate power, policy network
models and 154; location of 63; measurement
of 64; public power, sharing of 47; sources of
64; target populations, political powers of
22526; transfer of 63
preference ranking 192
primary care sector (UK) 467
prisoners dilemma 78
problem denition: agenda-setting and political
discourse 19092; disagreement and alternative
dispute resolution in policy process 34849;
problem from solution spaces, separation of
27778; problems stream in GCM 32021;
solutions and problems, links between 32425
problem description, anatomy of 191
problem handling 191
problem identication 2067
problem ownership 19192
problematisation 106
procedural instruments 2223
process-oriented approaches to study of public
policy-making 29, 30, 3536, 38
process sequencing 47381; deterministic causal
patterns 476; European Union (EU) Common
Agricultural Policy (CAP) 477, 479, 480;
exogenous problems 477; feedback 47879;
future research 481; historical institutionalist
perspective 47475; path dependency and,
distinct approaches to temporal analysis 47475,
48081; path-dependent sequencing and
process (or problem solving) sequencing,
distinction between 476; policy feedback,
learning and precedent 47880; policy
problems and policy actors 47780; policy
sequences, shaped and reshaped by creativity
and stubbornness 477; in public policy
47677; reactive sequencing and path
dependency 47576; strategic learning 477 78;
temporal connections between policy events
and policy changes 473; theoretical
underdevelopment of 481
process
style 26061
process success:
learning, success or failure and
488; and risks of programme and political
failure 49192
professional socialization, teaching key
components of 1112
programme success 488
public choice perspective 7685; bureaucrat
bashing 84; club goods 8182; collective choice
7879; common pool resources (CPRs) 8283;
congressional dominance 81; constituents,
Subject index
524
representation of 8081; democratic
decision-making 7677; Institutional Analysis
and Development (IAD) framework 8283;
majority rule 79; median voter theorem 80;
methodological individualism 77; multiple
parties, competition between 80; political
economics, schools of 8485; politicians,
actions of 78, 8081; politicians, need for 78,
7980; positive political theory 80; prisoners
dilemma 78; public choice (and theory of)
7677, 8485; public goods 78, 8182; public
goods research 8283; public policy
implementation 78, 84; rational abstention 81;
Rawls theory of justice 83; social welfare
functions, constitutions as 8384; societal
demands 78, 8284
public expenditure, data on 32
public goods see public choice perspective
public meetings and hearings 44041
public participation in policy, drivers for 43738
public policies: dynamic phenomenon of 451;
implementation of 78, 84; policy analysis 4,
9394, 95n5, 95n7; public spending as measure
of 171
public power, sharing of 47
public saliency, concept of 172
public sector activism 5253
public spending as measure of public policy 171
publics, communities and 43839
Punctuated Equilibrium Framework (PEF) 452,
454, 457
punctuated equilibrium theory (PET) of
agenda-setting and policy change 13850;
Agendas and Instability in American Politics
(Baumgartner, F. and Jones, B.D.) 14950,
150n6; bounded rationality and public policy
decision-making 273; disproportionate
information processing and positive feedback
cycles 14142; empirical approaches in punctuated
equilibrium 14649; general punctuation
hypothesis 143; incremental and non-incremental
policy change 139; institutional choice, positive
feedback cycles and 14244; institutions and
negative feedback cycles 14041; interest
groups, participation of 14446; issue framing
145; macro political attention, shifts in 13839;
negative feedback cycles 13839; organized
interests 145; Patient Protection and Affordable
Care Act (PPACA) 138, 150n1; Policy and
Comparative Agendas projects 149, 150n5,
150n8; policy entrepreneurs 14446; policy
incrementalism, negative feedback cycles and
13940;
policy stability and rapid change, forces
leading to 139;
policy targeting 145; positive
feedback cycles 139; stochastic processes 146,
147, 148, 149; venue shopping 144, 14546
punishment and discipline designs 226
Qadda, Muammar 47
qualitative research designs 406
quantitative and qualitative studies, division
between 37
quantitative comparative environmental policy
research 33
race analysis 9
radicalism 377, 378
randomized control trials 41531; arguments in
favor of 41920; average impact vs.
distributional concerns 426; categories of policy
questions suitable for 42829; causal
mechanisms 42627; critiques of 42029;
current dialog about 416; denition of 41719;
development interventions, identication of
41516; development programs, evaluation of
416; evidence-based policy, calls for 415; gold
standard in causal identication, promotion as
41720; heterogeneity 42425; internal validity
419, 431n15; interventions of interest,
randomization concerns 427; parsimony 420,
42425; practical considerations, departures
from ideal conditions and 42021;
randomization bias 42122; scope of questions
suitable for 42529; selection bias 418, 419,
420, 42223, 424, 431n18; selection issues
42224; substitution bias 42122; summary of
main points 42930; treatment and control
groups, treatment effects and 41719; treatment
compliance 42122; value in rening a single
parameter 42728
randomness and separation of streams in GCM
32325
rational abstention 81
rational choice theory (RCT) 93
rational decision-making: attainment of conditions
for 29092; policy-making process 2021
rationales 22425,
226
rationality: of actors,
assumption of 158;
breakdown of, incrementalism and 28788;
communicative model of 1045;
incrementalism, rationalist criticisms of 29394;
policy design and transfer, rationalist approach
to 218; rational policy-making 9899;
rational-scientic tradition 485; in style in
analysis 25859; in traditional models of policy
analysis 43435
reactive sequencing and path dependency
47576
reconstruction of decision-making, models for
299302, 31617
redistribution, government role in 5, 63
reection on policy analysis 26566
reformism in development management 377, 378,
381
Regulatory Impact Assessment (RIA) 246
Subject index
525
regulatory state 63; conation of debates on 62;
International Finance Corporation (IFC)
perspective on 66, 67; neo-liberal agenda and
64; techniques of 67; theories of 6265
Reinventing Government (Osborne, D. and
Gaebler, T.) 340
relevance model of evaluation 392
remediality 288
replacement rates, measurement of 32
research: and analytical styles 256, 258, 264;
methods and causal explanations 3638; on
policy appraisal 24749; on policy network
models, future challenges 16061; questions on
decision-making processes 300;
research-practice relationships 24950
resources: accumulation of 380; business advantage
in resources 296; communication and resource
exchange networks 156; exchange of resources
between lawmakers and interest groups 158;
mobilization of 380; resource-demands of
stakeholder model 39697; see also common
pool resources (CPRs)
responsive evaluation 39497
riots in UK, case of 19598
rounds model for research on decision-making
processes 300, 301, 302, 303, 3046, 308, 309,
310, 312, 314, 315, 316
rules: policy design and transfer 224, 226; and
responsibilities, clarication of 35556;
rule-making 6365; rules-in-use 119; as shared
prescriptions 11617
scope: in advocacy coalition framework (ACF)
127; of questions suitable for randomized
control trials 42529; rules in Institutional
Analysis and Development (IAD) framework
119
selection: bias 418, 419, 420, 42223, 424,
431n18; issues in RCTs 42224
self-evaluation 397
self-regulatory and private regimes 54
The Semisovereign People (Schattschneider, E.E.)
190
September 11 terrorist attacks: focusing events and
policy windows 177, 180, 185; garbage can
model (GCM), study of policy-making process
and 327; narrative explanation of 19495
service paradox 91
service providers 88
Seven Elements Framework (Harvard Negotiation
Project) 349
side-effects model 39092
sleeper effects 294
social and societal demands 78, 8284
social causation 463
social construction, problem of 1089
social efciency 470
social experimentation 99
social fragmentation of analysis 288
social
housing (UK) 465
social
inefciency 47071
social institution of bureaucracy 333
social issues, wicked problems of 99100
social judgments 1034
social learning 24
social liberties and freedoms 61
social network theory 15356
social policies 362
social scientic theories 59
Social Security Association 403
social welfare functions, constitutions as 8384
solutions: and politics, links between 324; social
problems, provision of solutions to 16869;
solutions stream in GCM 32021
sovereignty, pooling of 47
spin doctoring 1034
stabilization function 63
stakeholders: engagement of 67, 438, 488, 491;
evaluation, stakeholder model of 39497;
identication of 355; resource-demands of
stakeholder model 39697; stakeholder
evaluation, upsides and downsides of 39697;
stakeholder groups 438
state theory, regulatory state and 5972; deductive
social theories 5960; scal authority 63;
generalizability 59; inductive social theories
5960; interventionist and regulatory state,
typology of 6872; markets, globalization and
6263; modalities of governance 6566;
neo-institutionalism 6061; Next Steps
programme 64; policy preferences, society and
60; policy-relevant social theories 59; power,
location of 63; power, measurement of 64;
power, sources of 64; power, transfer of 63;
redistributive function 63; regulatory authority
63; regulatory function 63; regulatory state,
conation of debates on 62; regulatory state,
International Finance Corporation (IFC)
perspective on 66, 67; regulatory state,
neo-liberal agenda and 64; regulatory state,
theories of 6265; regulatory techniques 67;
rule-making 6365; social liberties and
freedoms 61; social scientic theories 59;
stabilization function 63; state and society,
interactions between 47; state-centric
explanations 6162; state theory, focus of
5960; statutory bodies and regulatory agencies,
profusion of 6465
stimuli:
attributes of 131;
processing of 126
stochastic processes 146, 147, 148, 149
strategic advice, provision of 257, 258, 264
Strategic Environmental Assessment (SEA) 246
strategic learning 47778
strategic manoeuvring of policy actors 48
Subject index
526
stream model for research on decision-making
processes 300, 301, 3034, 305, 306, 308, 309,
311, 314, 315, 318
street-level bureaucrats 339
structural theory of meaning 100
substantive benets, improved outcomes and
35758
substantive instruments 22
substitution bias 42122
subsystem actors 126; see also policy subsystems
sudden events 176
super bureaucracies 337
supranational governing arrangements,
institutionalization of 5253
Sustainability Impact Assessment (SIA) 246
Swedish National Agency for Higher Education
ten-steps evaluation policy 398
symbol propagation 176
systemic agenda 18
target populations 22324; political powers of
22526
technical skills, development of 12
telos of policy 101
temporality: change and history in social and
political analysis, interest in 462; temporal
connections between policy events and policy
changes 473; temporal problem in policy
dynamics and change 45556
Tennessee Valley Authority 99
terms of reference 409, 491
thematic frames 207
theories: behavioral theory of choice 274, 27677;
behavioral theory of organization 27879;
challenges for epistemic communities 23640;
consensus building, mediation theory and
35357; decision theory 220; deductive social
theories 5960; expert decision-making,
theories of 217; games and decisions, theory of
98; historical institutionalist theory, policy
change in 469; Institutional Analysis and
Development (IAD) framework 116; median
voter theorem 80; mediation theory 34748,
35357; negotiation theory 347; negotiation
theory, consensus building theory and
35354; negotiation theory, starting point of
consensus building 34849; neoinstitutionalist
theories 452; network theories, core
assumptions of 154; policy invention, theories
of 217; policy network theory and empirical
research 15860; policy-relevant social theories
59; positive political theory 80; public choice
(and theory of) 7677, 8485; rational choice
theory (RCT) 93; Rawls theory of justice 83;
regulatory state, theories of 6265; social
network theory 15356; social scientic
theories 59; structural theory of meaning 100;
theoretical emphasis of ACF 13334;
underdevelopment of process sequencing 481;
see also disagreement and alternative dispute
resolution in policy process; punctuated
equilibrium theory (PET); state theory,
regulatory state and
think tanks: knowledge base of 6; policy think
tanks 98; thinking about policy, intellectual
revolutions on 100101
Three Mile Island nuclear accident 178, 179
timing: decision-making over time, accounts of
46567;
learning,
success
or
failure and variance
over time 486; longterm time perspective of
ACF 127; media effects, timing of 204; of
policy dynamics and change 455; see also
temporality
tokenism 443
tools: diagnostic and analytic tools 381; planning
and management toolkit, provision of 37677;
for policy analysis 5; policy design and transfer
224, 225
tracks model of decision-making 302, 3068, 309,
310, 313, 314, 315, 316
trade-offs, principle of 276
translated beliefs 12627
transmission mechanisms, policy paradigms and
50
transnational policy communities 49, 53, 54, 55
transnational political forces 46
treatment and control groups, treatment effects
and 41719
treatment compliance 42122
Troubled Asset Relief Program (TARP) 101,
1023
Type One and Type Two events 185, 186
uncertainty, principle of 27576
unintended side-effects 390
United Kingdom: British Pension Commission
409; pension provision 464; policy network
analyses in 15758; primary care sector 467;
riots in, case of 19598; social housing in 465
United Nations (UN) 52, 53, 66, 160, 239
United States: American Association of Retired
Persons 403; auto manufacturers in 4546;
Constitution of, checks and balances in 6; dual
federalism in 362; incrementalism, special
problems in American context 29697;
Iran-Contra affair to Iraq 99; Joint
Committees in 408; Occupy Wall Street, case
of 195, 198200; organization of
metropolitan governance in 88; policy agendas
project
17172; policy network analyses in 157
universal elements in IAD, identication of 116
unreective learning 23940
utilization argument in evaluation 396
Subject index
527
values: allocation of 224; arguments and,
clarication of 257, 258, 264; associated with
development management 376; frames, belief
systems and 35253; single parameter in
randomized control trials and 42728;
underlying analytical styles 26365
venue shopping 144, 14546
veto players, concept of 37
weapons of mass destruction (WMDs) in Iraq 108
welfare state 5, 3132, 34, 37, 62, 170, 362,
36465, 4023
wildres in Arizona, McCains response to 22122
wisdom of crowds argument 282
Workshop in Political Theory and Policy Analysis,
Indiana University 11516
World Bank 337
Subject index
528