Marshall University Marshall University
Marshall Digital Scholar Marshall Digital Scholar
Humanities Faculty Research Humanities
10-2014
Metaphysics, Deep Pluralism, and Paradoxes of Informal Logic Metaphysics, Deep Pluralism, and Paradoxes of Informal Logic
Jeremy Barris
Follow this and additional works at: https://mds.marshall.edu/humanities_faculty
Part of the Metaphysics Commons
Metaphysics, Deep Pluralism, and Paradoxes of Informal Logic
Jeremy Barris
Philosophy Department
Marshall University
Huntington, WV 25755
USA
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
1
Abstract
The paper argues that metaphysical thought, or thought in whose context our general
framework of sense is under scrutiny, involves, legitimates, and requires a variety of
informal analogues of the “true contradictions” supported in some paraconsistent formal
logics. These are what we can call informal “legitimate logical inadequacies.” These
paradoxical logical structures also occur in deeply pluralist contexts, where more than
one, conflicting general framework for sense is relevant. The paper argues further that
these legitimate logical inadequacies are real or inherent in sense itself rather than
conventional, shows how they can feature in argumentative practice in these
metaphysical and pluralist contexts, and discusses some of their implications for
metaphysical truth and for philosophical inquiry and disagreement.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
2
Metaphysics, Deep Pluralism, and Paradoxes of Informal Logic
1
In this paper, I shall try to show that metaphysical thought, or thought in whose context
our general framework of sense is under scrutiny, involves, legitimates, and requires a
variety of informal analogues of the “true contradictions” supported in some
paraconsistent formal logics.
2
These are what we can call “legitimate logical
inadequacies.” By this I mean that in this kind of context informal fallacies like, for
example, (informal) contradiction, non sequitur, circularity, equivocation, and category
confusion can be elements of legitimate argumentation and thinking, and in fact are often
necessary to adequate reasoning. I do not mean that they cease to be fallacies, but that
they are logically legitimate elements precisely and paradoxically in virtue of their logical
flaws. I use the term “legitimate” to cover both “valid” and “adequate or helpful as
reasoning,” since some fallacious argumentative structures, like circular reasoning, are
technically valid.
I shall argue that these legitimate logical inadequacies occur both in strictly
metaphysical contexts and in the related (as I shall also argue) contexts in which more
than one comprehensive and conflicting framework for meaning or sense is relevant,
which I shall call deeply pluralist contexts. I explain what I mean by these two contexts
and make this argument in the first section below. I subsequently try to show some
implications of these legitimate logical inadequacies for reasoning and argumentation in
these kinds of contexts.
I argue that in these, frequently occurring contexts there is a type of inadequacy
and sometimes even incoherence in the nature of the sense itself of the relevant issues.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
3
Because in these contexts this inadequacy is in the nature of the sense of the issues, it
follows from that sense, and as a result we need to think of it as something like a
legitimate variety of logical inadequacy or incoherence. For the same reason, it is also an
inadequacy or incoherence that we cannot avoid by, for example, reconstructing our
language or suitably selecting our patterns of expression or argument, as philosophers
like Bertrand Russell and Richard Rorty have famously undertaken in responding to
related concerns. Instead, our understanding and teaching both of metaphysical thought
and of legitimate reasoning and argument needs to acknowledge this kind of inadequacy
or incoherence, find ways of giving an account of it, and develop ways of negotiating it.
3
I discuss ways of working with this kind of incoherence and arriving at adequate
sense in the third and fifth sections below, but let me note here that, like the
paraconsistent “true contradictions” mentioned above, it does not “explode” into
undermining the sense of anything else that can be said, but is limited and manageable. I
make this argument in detail elsewhere, and I will only sketch it briefly here.
4
This kind
of incoherence is limited because it occurs only in the kinds of contexts I have
mentioned, where relevant sense as such is in question. As will become clear in the
following sections, these contexts are specialized and so have definite boundaries. Once
these contexts are no longer relevant this incoherence no longer has relevance or, in fact,
even meaning. This kind of incoherence is also manageable, because it is built into it that
it cancels itself. Since, as I have proposed and will become more clear below, it is an
incoherence that applies to the nature of relevant sense as such or in general, it also
applies to its own sense, and consequently renders its own sense as “incoherence”
meaningless and so inapplicable. As a result, it itself necessarily takes us out of those
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
4
contexts where it has relevance and meaning. Despite its self-cancellation, however, we
cannot simply dispense with it as self-contradictory. As I argue below, this kind of
incoherence emerges necessarily from coherent sense itself in these situations, and so is
not an avoidable error but a self-reflexive paradox, like the liar’s paradox. But because it
is less limited than that paradox, it applies even to its own character as a paradox, and
consequently undoes itself.
I give a first example of this kind of legitimate logical inadequacy at the start of
the first section below. But that there are occurrences that are logically vexed in this kind
of way is often immediately visible in the issues and situations we encounter. These
include, for example, tragic situations, and those involving moral dilemmas or, in
politics, “dirty hands,” where equally obligatory moral requirements are in irresolvable
conflict with each other.
5
A famous example of a moral dilemma is the one presented in
the book and movie Sophie’s Choice, where a mother must choose which of her two
children will be shot, while if she does not choose both of them will be shot. Whatever
decision she makes in this situation will violate the very moral requirement it exists to
honor, the requirement to avoid doing great harm to her children. In fact, since the child
she saves will only live because of the involuntary death of the other child, the child who
lives may understandably feel responsible for that death. Consequently, honoring the
requirement to do no great harm to the child who lives may violate that same requirement
for that very child. In this kind of case, then, it is evidently at least arguable that the
contradiction in moral principles is not an avoidable flaw of understanding the situation
but part of its correct description.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
5
Again, certain types of humor work on the basis of logical errors, and there are
real situations whose overall sense is humorous in these kinds of ways. So, for example,
if someone claims invariably unflappable dignity and then sees a mouse and shrieks and
leaps up on a restaurant table, the humor depends on the contradiction between the
person’s claim and the evidence his behavior gives. In these kinds of situations, if we
eliminate the logical errors, we eliminate the humor. Consequently, we can only describe
the reality of these humorous situations as humorous if we retain the logical errors as part
of their meaning or, in other words, as part of the sense they make.
In these various contexts, the articulations of the logical flaws represent or
recapitulate logical incoherencies or inadequacies that are an inherent part of the sense of
a real situation itself.
This thesis that there are legitimate logical inadequacies involves two connected
lines of thought. The first is the proposal I have already mentioned about the role of
legitimate fallacies in metaphysics and the related deeply pluralist contexts. The second is
that these paradoxical structures of argumentationand by extension the structures,
patterns, or devices that are the topic of informal logic or argumentation theory in
generalare not simply human constructs or conventions, but are real.
6
Since these
“legitimate fallacies” follow from the sense itself of the issues, they are at least to some
substantial extent inherent in the nature of meaning or sense, independently of our
invented contributions to sense-making.
We could go further and say they are in the nature of the things themselves, which
are and work according to that sense. For if these patterns are inherent in meaning, they
are inherent in anything we might mean by “things,” and so in anything we might mean
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
6
in referring beyond our concepts to “things.” Here, however, my focus is on the nature of
sense in the relevant contexts, and correspondingly on “metaphysics” as referring to the
discipline which is the conceptual study of reality rather than to the structure of reality
itself. Elsewhere, I do discuss incoherence and confusion as elements of the structure of
reality itself and in general, but here my concern is only with the structure of sense.
7
As I
have insisted, this sense is the sense of things and situations; but this is not to deny that it
is nonetheless discriminable as an object of analysis in its own right, as we standardly
take it to be, and that is how I take it here.
In describing these structures of argumentation as real, then, I do not mean they
are Platonic entities, but only that, however else we understand their reality, they are not
the product of our conventions or choices of theoretical approach. As I shall argue, in a
sense they pre-exist any conventions or conceptual choices we might make, since those
conventions and choices depend on them. The point of insisting that they are real in this
sense is that it underscores the claim that they are not artifacts of a misguided approach
that can and should therefore be dismissed or avoided. Instead, they are necessary to
making adequate sense of the relevant contexts, and so to an adequate account of sense
itself in these contexts.
As I mentioned, the reality of these structures of sense also has further
implications for our understanding of metaphysical and deeply pluralist argument and
inquiry, and I shall explore some of these implications.
Recognizing this real and legitimate type of logical inadequacy or incoherence in
the metaphysical and deeply pluralist contexts where, I argue, it occurs has the advantage
of allowing us to connect the deepest concerns and insights of philosophy with
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
7
admittedly in an odd and paradoxical waythe everyday, nuts-and-bolts pragmatics of
argumentation and its devices. First, it allows us to recognize some metaphysical or
existential dimensions of our concrete argumentative experience, involving contexts
where our general sense framework reaches its limits. Second, since these logical
inadequacies are legitimate and real aspects of sense itself, they are not only flaws in
sense but also means of making sense and engaging with it. As a result, they are
themselves what enable us to negotiate their own inadequacy and incoherence.
Recognizing them therefore allows us further to identify and develop the logical skills
necessary to deal with these contexts and negotiate what I argue are legitimate confusion
and incoherence. That is, it adds to our resources for negotiating the deep issues of sense
associated with the pluralist and metaphysical contexts that give rise to these
incoherencies. It is also important that the recognition of legitimate logical inadequacy
allows us to set our expectations appropriately for the kinds of logically confused
situations that we do in fact encounter. It allows us to identify and foster the attitudinal
aptitudes necessary to deal, for example, with the fundamental kind of resourcelessness in
which a real or objective failure of sense leaves us.
In the first section below, I shall try to show that there are legitimate inadequacies
or failures of logical sense. In the second, I shall argue that these inadequacies are real
rather than conventional. In the third section, I shall try to show how these legitimate
logical inadequacies can feature in argumentative practice in the relevant metaphysical
and pluralist contexts. Finally, I shall discuss some of their implications both for
metaphysical truth and for philosophical inquiry and disagreement.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
8
1. Legitimate Failures of Logical Adequacy and Coherence
I have mentioned two contexts in which logical incoherence and failures of logical
adequacy are logically legitimate. One of these is that of metaphysical thought, that is,
thought in which our general framework of sense is under scrutiny. The other occurs
when there is more than one relevant global framework for making sense or for settling
the meanings of things in general, or what I shall call deeply pluralist contexts. (There are
objections to the meaningfulness of this idea of global frameworks for sense, in either
context, and I shall discuss these objections shortly below.) As I try to show in this
section, these two kinds of contexts are really different aspects of one and the same more
general context. This is the context of reflection on sense as a whole, whether in its own
right or in comparison with other versions of sense as a whole. Each context simply
emphasizes a different aspect of that more general context. Since, as I shall argue, the
logical anomalies that are my topic arise from this more general context, these anomalies
occur in and are relevant in many of the same ways to both metaphysical and deeply
pluralist contexts. As a result, once I have explained the relevance of each of these
contexts to legitimate logical inadequacies, I shall discuss the two contexts
interchangeably as I pursue the significance of these anomalous logical structures for
reasoning and argumentation.
In this section, I first discuss the deeply pluralist context and its relevance to
legitimate logical inadequacies, and I discuss the metaphysical context and its relevance
immediately after. I then discuss the objections to the idea of global frameworks. In the
last portion of the section, I briefly discuss some prominent but, I believe, inadequate,
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
9
attempts in both philosophy and argumentation theory to acknowledge and work with
deep pluralism.
In the deeply pluralist context, whatever topic is under discussion actually means
two different things at the same time. For example, as I shall discuss below, in a debate
between Western religious and materialist perspectives on whether abortion destroys a
life, the idea of a soul is central to the meaning of “life” in the religious perspective, so
that the absence of that idea cannot be given a coherent sense while still talking about
life; but the idea of a soul cannot be given a coherent sense in the system of meanings
that constitute the materialist perspective. Consequently, a meaning that is basic to the
whole system in one case cannot exist at all in the other case. As a result, the only way to
understand what the issue is, is to grasp its role within each framework’s whole system of
meanings. The issue can only be grasped, then, can only be given sense, as
simultaneously having two meanings that are not compatible with each other.
In this context, that the topic means two different things does not simply mean
that it is really two different topicsthat there is no disagreement because there is no
common issue. As Alasdair MacIntyre notes about debate between incommensurable
standpoints, “each community, using its own criteria of sameness and difference,
recognizes that it is one and the same subject matter about which they are advancing their
claim; incommensurability and incompatibility are not incompatible.”
8
In at least one
phase of the interaction between the frameworks, part of the dispute is exactly whether or
not one or both of the proffered meanings is the appropriate meaning, so that it is the
appropriate meaning of this one thing that is in dispute. And since there is no ground
independent of some framework on which to stand and refer to the thing whose meaning
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
10
is being disputed, we can only refer to “it” in both relevant, incompatible terms
simultaneously. It may be easier to see this in cases where a framework undergoes a
revolutionary change into a framework with incommensurable meanings, as, for example,
Thomas Kuhn argues occurs in the history of science.
9
There is a phase in the process of
change of these meanings where it is unclear which framework constitutes the meaning,
or, differently expressed, where it is undecidable which the meaning is. To describe this
state of the meaning, we need to make use of both meanings simultaneously. In phases
like these, then, the topic of argument is inescapably an equivocation or a category
confusion, even before we go any further.
For similar reasons, too, it is not possible to resolve the problem by
disambiguating our terms. This is not the kind of case where, for example, one of the
conflicting meanings expresses the topic in one respect or under one description while the
other meaning expresses it in another. Instead, what characterizes this situation of global
or comprehensive frameworks of meaning is that each conflicting meaning wholly
excludes the other, not just as applicable in some respect but as being a relevantly
conceivable meaning. Each of the conflicting meanings, as located in a different
framework of sense as a whole, does not function in keeping with the criteria for meaning
that make the other possible at all. To approach the same point from a different angle,
each comprehensive framework provides a construal of every possibly meaningful
respect and description of the topic. As a result, the conflicting meanings cannot be said
to focus on different aspects of the same thing, but instead conflict with respect to what
that “same” thing is, and so with respect to what any aspect of it is. In this context, to
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
11
disambiguate, then, would be to repeat the paradox, since it would be to describe one and
the same thing in two wholly mutually exclusive ways at once.
The second, strictly metaphysical context occurs when our general framework of
sense is under scrutiny simply in its own right. Here, if we rely on our fundamental
categories of sense or meaning in order to evaluate them, or even to identify them, we
proceed circularly. But if we do not rely on them, we are no longer guided by our
standards of coherent sense, and we proceed in some degree incoherently or in ways that
involve logical confusion. And as I am about to explain, we do need to account for our
general framework of sense, and consequently to commit one of these logical
inadequacies.
In both contexts, these elements of incoherence or logical inadequacy do not
simply occur as avoidable and regrettable products of lines of inquiry or forms of
expression that we can or should avoid. Instead, they are required by sense itself in these
situations. This is why they are not just artifacts of a certain approach to description or of
a certain misguided conception of what contexts can be meaningfully discussed, but are
logically legitimate. They are parts of the operation of sense itself. The metaphysical
reflection on our general framework of sense as a whole is required in order to account
for that framework, given the possibility of alternative and conflicting general ways of
making sense of things, and it is also required to account for sense as such.
10
Without
that, we are left either without foundations or without an account of why we do not need
such foundations. This situation itself involves standard kinds of logical inadequacy:
either logical arbitrariness (perhaps a kind of non sequitur) or circularity. The pluralist
context also arises as a requirement of sense itself, because the necessary metaphysical
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
12
step of accounting for our general sense of things already implies a contrast with other
possible general senses of things. Without a contrast with other possible frameworks, the
concept of “our” framework does not pick out anything in particular, and so does not
mean anything.
The metaphysical and pluralist contexts, then, are really different sides of the
same coin. They are different aspects of reflection on sense as a whole, whether in its
own right or in comparison with other versions of sense as a whole. And because they
arise from the requirements of sense itself, the elements of incoherence and logical
inadequacy they involve are parts of the operation of sense itself. These elements are
failures of sense that are part of how sense functions.
There are powerful objections to the idea that we can meaningfully talk about
these kinds of contexts. Donald Davidson, for example, argues that we cannot attach
sense to the idea of globally different frameworks of sense, or even of a single global
framework of sense (that we can scrutinize “outside its standards for sense”), in his paper
on “the very idea of a conceptual scheme.”
11
One of his central argumentative strategies
relies on the idea that, very roughly, for us to be able to mean anything by a different
“conceptual scheme” we would need to be able to translate it into the meanings that
belong to our “conceptual scheme.” In other words, we cannot even consider the problem
without regarding at least some of the “other” framework’s meanings as translatable into
our own. Consequently, we cannot intelligibly regard its meanings as globally different
from ours. As I noted above, it follows that we cannot have the idea even of a single
global framework for sense, either. If there is no meaning to the idea of alternative
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
13
overall frameworks, then the idea of a single overall framework does not contrast with
anything, and so says nothing in particular (198).
But this argument is not conclusive. MacIntyre, for example, argues that the
meanings of a language cannot be so intimately tied to the possibility of translation, since
we have all learned a first language when we had no language to translate its meanings
into.
12
And Peter Winch notes in response to a similar argument to Davidson’s, in this
case an argument about our general standards of rationality rather than about our
meanings (in fact, an argument put forward by MacIntyre in an earlier phase of his
career), that it “does not in fact show that our own standards of rationality occupy a
peculiarly central position. . . . [A] formally similar argument could be advanced in any
language containing concepts playing a similar role in that language to those of
‘intelligibility’ and ‘rationality’ in ours.”
13
More generally, it is arguable that Davidson’s general idea of how meaning works
itself belongs to a globally different framework from the general conception of meaning
in the standpoints that argue for the possibility of a global framework of sense. His idea
of meaning certainly contrasts deeply with a variety of other philosophical approaches to
meaning, so much so that it leads to conclusions their proponents find strikingly counter-
intuitive. He insists, for example, that “there is no such thing as language, not if a
language is anything like what many philosophers and linguists have supposed.”
14
But
the debate about the sense of the idea of global systems of meaning depends precisely on
our conception of meaning, and Davidson proceeds on the assumption that his conception
of this issue is commensurable with and so responds to and communicates with the
opposing positions’ conception of it, in this very debate. In other words, at least in the
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
14
case of the relation between his own standpoint and those opposed to it with respect to
the meanings (of meaning) that are part of the medium of this debate itself, his argument
presupposes that the relevant meanings are necessarily compatible. As a result, he does
not so much establish that meanings must be compatible across positions as circularly
presuppose it.
I should perhaps note that, while my aim is to defend circular presupposition as
sometimes legitimate, Davidson’s argument (and others I criticize below) does not
benefit from this possibility. It is only in contexts where globally different positions are
being taken into account that this legitimacy applies, and Davidson’s whole point is to
deny that there could be such contexts. In fact, if he did acknowledge this possibility, and
take it properly into account in his argumentation, then by the standards I am defending
there would be room for a legitimate kind of circularity in his argument. This would then
take us in the direction of very different possible kinds of outcomes and their assessment,
a kind of direction I shall discuss below.
A different and equally influential kind of objection to talking about global
frameworks of sense is the pragmatist argument that a logically contentious way of
talking about things is unproductive, and we can simply adopt ways of talking about
these issues that are more useful because they do not result in this kind of distracting
complexity. Richard Rorty is perhaps the best known contemporary proponent of this
kind of argument.
15
But this begs the very large question of how we assess “more useful.”
For all we know, it might be useful and productive in all sorts of unpredictable ways to
make room for the possibility of systematic incomprehension and of a logically legitimate
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
15
role for logical incoherence. It is precisely my aim here to argue for a variety of
significant functions for this kind of logical paradox.
There is, however, also a widespread endorsement of the idea of globally different
frameworks of meaning. Among philosophers, many defend this idea, and also recognize
the absence of coherent means of debate between such “incommensurable
frameworks.
16
As these philosophers typically note, each framework automatically
registers any of the other’s statements as meaning something different from what it
means in the context of the other frameworkincluding statements that aim to clarify
these meanings. In light of this incoherence of meaning between such frameworks,
however, none of these thinkers tries to map the logical elements of the interactions and
negotiations between them. On the other hand, some philosophers, like MacIntyre and
Charles Taylor, defend the idea of globally different frameworks of meaning, but propose
ways in which they can rationally evaluate their comparative merits.
17
But this seems to
me inconsistent, since, as in the case of Rorty’s reliance on what is “useful,” the
standards by which we identify the “same” kind of merit in each framework will mean
something different in each of them.
There is also an extensive literature in argumentation theory, communication
studies, and approaches to critical reasoning that recognizes globally different or
“incommensurable” frameworks of meaning, as well as the breakdown of rational debate
between them.
18
Like the philosophical authors, these theorists do not attempt to map the
logical elements of the “broken down” communication, other than to identify them
simply as problems we need to find a way around or to accept. This literature also often
looks to overcome this problem by focusing on the skills of receptiveness required to
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
16
come to understand such radically different perspectives, and then to hold out the hope
that once each party has achieved this understanding of the other it may become possible
to construct a common ground on a reasonable basis. This seems to share the
inconsistency of the philosophical attempts to allow for rational comparison. If the
frameworks constitute meaning differently from each other, they continue to do so once
we have come to understand them.
These characteristics of both literatures prevent their respective approaches from
being genuinely the “deep pluralism” of my title. On the one hand, insofar as they aim for
common ground or shared standards of evaluation, they eliminate the relevance of
pluralism of perspectives itself. On the other hand, insofar as they recognize the
incoherence of interaction between frameworks but regard it as containing no connection
in itself with legitimate sense, they allow nothing that connects with rational negotiation
between the frameworks. As a result, they establish relativism as the exclusive, and so
absolute, overarching perspective. This is both self-contradictory and, paradoxically, also
eliminates pluralism again, in that it denies the truth of all frameworks that reject
relativism. Expressing this slightly differently, a genuine pluralism has to be able to make
room for and endorse frameworks that reject pluralism. I shall return to this genuine
pluralism and make a case for its sense in the context of “legitimate logical inadequacies”
in the final two sections on some of the consequences of these logical anomalies.
Paolo Virno recognizes both globally different frameworks of meaning, in the
context of radical socio-political change, and to a large extent the incoherence of
negotiation between them, and on this basis he makes a particularly interesting attempt to
map these negotiations in terms of standard fallacies.
19
But he balks at regarding logical
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
17
sense itself as capable of legitimate violation. Instead, he argues that the mappable “space
between” the frameworks is not truly without coherent meaning, because meaning has a
pre-conceptual, pre-linguistic, quasi-biological basis, independent of frameworks (115,
121-125). Consequently, the “fallacies” that occur in the negotiation between frameworks
do not truly violate sense and therefore only look like fallacies without truly being so
(139, 151-152). Again, this seems inconsistent. Clearly, we mean something that belongs
within our framework of meaning by this “meaning independent of frameworks”: we
cannot specify it independently of our frameworks.
In contrast with these bodies of work, my aim is to combine the consistent
recognition that the negotiation of globally different frameworks of sense or meaning is
logically incoherent, with Virno’s interest in mapping the logical elements in this
incoherence. I also want to go further, in two ways. First, as I have discussed, this kind of
incoherence also occurs when we inquire into any given framework of sense as a whole.
This means that the mapping of the logical elements in this incoherence is relevant to the
exploration of metaphysical and meta-logical issues. Second, I want to show that these
logical elements and consequently their incoherence are real, that is, that they are part of
the reality of sense itself in these contexts. In other words, as I have suggested, they are
not just aberrations we should try to find a way around, but are legitimate and inescapable
operations of sense itself. This is already a meta-logical implication, in this case one that
just the general fact of this kind of incoherence allows us to establish.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
18
2. The Reality of Legitimate Failures of Logical Adequacy and Coherence
As I explained in the introductory section, in describing these structures of logic or sense
as real I mean only that, however else we understand their reality, they are not the
product of our conventions or choices of theoretical approach. In other words, an
adequate account of sense in the relevant contexts cannot avoid taking them into account.
I am not, here, arguing that they are ontological structures in any further sense.
It seems clear, in principle alone, that the connections on which argument relies
must already exist for us to draw on prior to our arguing. If we had to construct them, we
would have to rely on them to do so. Similar lines of thought have been recognized since
ancient times. Epictetus, for example, pointed out that in order to assess an argument that
logic is necessary, we would need to rely on logic: consequently, “logic is necessary;
since without it, you cannot even learn whether it is necessary or not.”
20
In recent
philosophy, both Wittgenstein and Heidegger make related points. Wittgenstein argues,
for instance, that “I did not get my picture of the world by satisfying myself of its
correctness; . . . No: it is the inherited background against which I distinguish between
true and false.”
21
A system of meanings and of their relations must already be in place
before I can begin to make meaningful decisions about anything. Without such a system,
there is nothing meaningful to make decisions about. Heidegger, for his part, argues that
“the account of the laws governing thinking pushes us back into the question of the
conditions of their possibility. . . . In measuring itself up to that about which it thinks, true
thinking seeks in the being itself that on which it supports and grounds itself.”
22
Here, however, I want to make the case specifically with respect to the contexts of
incoherence I have begun to discuss. As I mentioned in the introductory section of this
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
19
paper, contexts simply do seem to exist whose logic requires that they can only be
described or grasped in ways that involve elements of incoherence or logical inadequacy.
I mentioned there tragic situations, or those involving moral dilemmas or, in politics,
“dirty hands”; and certain types of humor and the real situations that are humorous in
those ways. The metaphysical and pluralist contexts I have been discussing are another
case. In all of these cases, the articulations of the logical flaws represent or recapitulate
logical incoherencies or inadequacies that are an inherent part of the sense of a real
situation itself.
The reality of logical connections means that conventionalist and pragmatist
accounts of informal logic and argumentation, while illuminating and indispensable
within their limits, are not enough.
23
How we connect things may, for example, be partly
constituted by our interests and our goals, but the logical materials we manipulate to
achieve our ends must pre-exist those manipulations. Otherwise we could not even
calculate which means would get us to our ends. That kind of calculation already
presupposes that some things connect in certain ways with others and do not connect with
them in other ways.
But even more than this, given the reality of elements of logical incoherence and
inadequacy in particular, there are logically significant situations in which we are simply
not in a position to know the relevance of our interests and goals to the issues under
discussion, because the sense of those issues, what we ourselves mean by them, is no
longer clear. In these situations we can no longer rely even on the sense of things that is
already available to us, whether in our individual projects or our social practices. Instead,
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
20
we need to let truth emerge independently of our no longer functional assumptions and
abilities to construe.
Here we can begin to see one of the further metaphysical implications of the
recognition of elements of “legitimate incoherence,” in this case an implication for our
conception of truth and our relation to it. I shall return to this kind of issue in the final
sections.
3. Legitimate Logical Inadequacies in Argumentative Practice
In this section I want to show how various standard fallacies are legitimate elements of
the negotiation between globally different frameworks of sense or of reflection on a
single framework of sense as a whole. (We can usefully regard “negotiation” in this
context as referring both to “bargaining” and to “making one’s way through obstacles.”)
As I pointed out in the first section, the topic of discussion in negotiation between
different frameworks of sense as a whole is necessarily an equivocation or category
confusion from the start. Each framework constitutes the sense of the topic differently,
and there is no neutral standpoint to fix what we mean by “this” topic: what we mean by
it is therefore constituted in two different ways simultaneously. For example, in a debate
between Western religious and materialist perspectives on whether abortion destroys a
life, the idea of a soul is central to the meaning of “life” in the religious perspective, so
that the absence of that idea cannot be given a coherent sense while still talking about
life; but on the other hand, the idea of a soul cannot be given a coherent sense in the
system of meanings that constitute the materialist perspective at all. Consequently, a
meaning that is basic to the whole system in one case cannot exist at all in the other case.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
21
The only way to understand what the issue is, is to grasp its role within each framework’s
whole system of meanings. But to do that is also to grasp each contrasting meaning as not
belonging to the opposed system of meaning, and so in that context to see it as
unintelligible. The issue can only be grasped at all, can only be given sense, as
simultaneously having two meanings that are not compatible with each other.
As is the case with all the logical inadequacies that are the consequence of this
kind of conflict of systematic meanings, then, the equivocation here partly constitutes the
meaning of the issue under discussion, and so is not simply an error but an expression of
the real sense of the situation. It is valid. It may then happen that the discussion proceeds
so that, for whatever motives, one of the frameworks is given up for the other (say, a
“conversion” in either direction: as Kuhn argues occurs regularly in science, for
example),
24
or a third, compromise framework is established. In that new context, the
equivocation is no longer valid, but describes a meaning situation that is no longer
relevant to the debate. For the debate at that point, the only meaningful logical content of
the equivocation is its character as a logical error.
Given these possible shifts of relevant context, the fallacy is valid at two moments
in the process of the negotiation between the frameworks. First, it is valid when both
meanings are in play, either because the disputants have not yet sorted out that there are
two meanings or, at a later point, because they have not yet established one of them (or
an alternative) as the right one. When they have not yet sorted out that there are two
meanings, both meanings are a real part of the conceptual situation the disputants are
working on or in. Both meanings therefore play a necessary role in the process of the
disputants’ working intelligently with that situation, and both are therefore necessary to
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
22
describe the situation. And when the disputants have not yet eliminated one of them, they
have to think in terms of both at once in order to compare them and make that decision.
We should be careful to note that this is not like the case where one considers
alternative construals of something that exists independently of these construals, so that it
can act as a neutral basis of comparison with reference to which their different
perspectives on it can be set side by side and compared. Here, the topic does not exist
independently of the two construals. Each meaning, as part of a global system of
meanings that excludes the other, claims to be the whole relevant meaning of the topic,
and consequently the conflict about the topic cannot be described at all without
employing both meanings at once in all the same respects. If we describe the conflict in
terms of one meaning only in any respect at any time, we have already wholly excluded
the claims of the other to be the (wholly exclusive) relevant meaning, and so we have
already decided the debate rather than still being in process of deciding it. The
equivocation, then, is part of the real sense of the situation.
The second moment at which the fallacy is valid occurs after everything is sorted
out and decided (should this happen), when we describe the whole process. In that
description, the situation where both meanings are in play becomes relevant again. Since
here, too, there is no neutral standpoint to fix the meaning of the topic independently of
the two construals, the equivocation between them becomes necessary to the description
itself, and so enters into its own meanings. Again, it is part of the real sense of the
situation and, equally, a necessary part of the expression of that sense.
As I mentioned in the introductory section, the reality of legitimate logical
inadequacies does not only mean that they are a fact we have to negotiate as a dimension
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
23
of sense itself. It is also what allows us to negotiate and come to grips with them, and also
with the deep issues of sense associated with the pluralist and metaphysical contexts that
give rise to them. Since these are logical inadequacies that are also legitimate, and so are
real aspects of sense itself, they are not only flaws in sense but also means of making and
engaging with it. What is more, as inadequacies of sense, they allow us to learn and
establish sense from a point before it is already in place, and so allow us to come to
engage with frameworks whose sense we do not yet have any grip on. This gives us the
tools to deal with either the pluralist or the metaphysical contexts.
In the case of equivocation, for example, the persistent and specific type of failure
of sense allows us to establish that two meanings are in play. This in turn alerts us to the
need to learn the framework in which the other meaning has its sense, and also gives us a
relevant starting issue or question on whose basis to proceed. In this process, we also
establish a sense of the contrast of our own system of meanings as a whole with the new
one, and so get a grasp of our own whole framework, either for the first time or in a new
way.
I have described equivocation in this context as applying conflicting meanings to
the same thing in the same respect at the same time. In other words, equivocation here is
also contradiction. More precisely, statements that incorporate the conflicting meanings
would be contradictory, but in this context only statements that incorporate both
meanings can accurately describe the situation. The equivocation, then, sets up
contradictions, and these are equally parts of the very sense of the situation.
25
(We could
describe this in reverse: the contradictory character of the situation establishes
equivocations. This interchangeability is also the case with the other violations of sense
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
24
and fallacies I shall discuss. Fallacies notoriously blend into each other, and it can be a
judgment call which “standard fallacy” we select to name a particular breach of sense.)
In a related way, the equivocations also set up non sequiturs as part of the
situation’s sense. Each meaning provides the material for lines of thought leading to
conclusions to which the other meaning cannot lead. And since each meaning is both
necessary and claims to constitute the whole sense of the issue, some conclusions that
legitimately follow from the meaning of the issue are nonetheless also non sequiturs with
respect to that meaning. They are part of the situation’s sense, and so are legitimate.
Henry Johnstone argues that philosophical positions involve comprehensive
systems of meaning in the sense I have discussed, and that consequently “a philosophical
argument cannot be valid unless it is addressed ad hominem” (Validity, 53). Any attempt
to appeal to facts or evidence independent of the addressed philosophical position “is
doomed, because a philosophical position always is, or implies, a decision as to what is to
count as facts or evidence” (55). The valid way—and in fact the only valid wayto argue
with a philosophical position is in terms of the idiosyncratic features of its framing of the
situation: that is, ad hominem. These considerations apply, for the same reasons, to
argument with any comprehensive framework for meaning. (It follows from Johnstone’s
view that all philosophical discussion occurs in the kind of contexts I discuss here, and so
in the medium of legitimate logical inadequacy. Presumably the reverse also applies, that
in encountering these contexts we are engaging in what defines philosophy.)
Tautology or circularity also has a place here. Since the sense of a framework
only occurs once the basic elements of the framework are already in place, these elements
themselves cannot be justified, and there is no meaning to the idea that they be justified.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
25
Justification itself only has sense within a framework that enables sense. Wittgenstein, for
example, points out that “all confirmation and disconfirmation of a hypothesis takes place
already within a system,” and, further that “If the true is what is grounded, then the
ground is not true, nor yet false” (On Certainty, 16e, no. 105, 28e, no. 205). And Rorty
argues that our perspectives each rest on what he calls a “final vocabulary,” by which he
means that “if doubt is cast on the worth of these words, their user has no noncircular
argumentative recourse. Those words are as far as he can go with language.”
26
In debates between scientific theories of evolution and religious ideas of creation,
for instance, it is basic to the scientific position that our senses and rationality are the
touchstones of reliable conclusions, while it is basic to the religious position (or at least to
some versions of it) that human rationality is so feeble and human senses so limited that
we cannot rely on them for anything fundamental (as, for example, the experience of
dreaming suggests). In each case genuine justification of these ideas does not come into
play, because these ideas are a basis for proceeding in all argument. Consequently they
are asserted as self-evident, and the side that rejects them is dismissed as being
intellectually blind or defective in such fundamental ways that genuine discussion is
precluded from the ground up. Because these ideas are the basis for proceeding
rationally, regarding them as self-certifying is legitimate: their self-certifying character is
part of what constitutes the sense of the situation, and so it is inherent in that sense. As
the Wittgenstein quote about the necessary context of a system above continues, “this
system is not a more or less arbitrary and doubtful point of departure for all our
arguments: no, it belongs to the essence of what we call an argument. The system is not
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
26
so much the point of departure, as the element in which arguments have their life” (16e,
no. 105).
In addition to fallacies and logical incoherence, there is another type of logically
inadequate rhetorical form that is legitimate in these contexts. This is ornamental or
display rhetoric, which, precisely because it bypasses logical connection altogether, is
neutral with respect to either framework in these kinds of dispute. As a result, it offers
neutral ground on which to reconsider the issues, and also on whose basis each disputant
can gain entry to and learn the new sense of the other framework, in a context free of the
distorting patterns of her own framework. On the other hand, analogously to the role of
circularity and ad hominem discussed above, this neutral ground constituted by
ornamental rhetoric helps to establish the sense in question as, in Wittgenstein’s phrase,
the “element in which it has its life,” and as a result it enters into that sense, or “belongs
to its essence.” That is, it is both entirely irrelevant to legitimate connection, and part of
it. Ernesto Grassi, for example, argues that since argumentative procedures like
Aristotelian “demonstration” cannot argumentatively demonstrate their own premises,
those premises can only be established by non-argumentative rhetoric, in which he
includes rhetoric designed to elicit feeling: by the kind of rhetoric that “exhibits,” that
allows its objects to emerge to the receptive apprehender and in this way certify
themselves.
27
4. An Implication for the Nature of Metaphysical and Deeply Pluralist Truth
The fact of and the encounter with real, objective failure of sense automatically raises the
question of and offers some insights into the nature and status of sense and meaning
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
27
themselves. One insight this kind of encounter offers is that in the context of conflicting
frameworks for the whole of sense, it is less appropriate to think of truth as relative or as
needing to be reduced to an overarching absolute truth than as consisting in a variety of
absolute truths. As I have argued, there must be more than one conceivable framework:
the concept of a single framework requires the contrast of a possible alternative
framework to be meaningful. But each framework considered in its own terms constitutes
the meaning of the whole of things, and so within each framework there simply is no
meaningful alternative. Within each framework, then, there is no sense to the idea of
relative truth. When we are considering more than one framework, however, sense fails,
and so any relevant questions and issues do not make clear or proper sense. They only
make clear sense once we are no longer negotiating frameworks (or reflecting on our own
from the “outside”): and at that point we are within one or another framework again, and
there are no meaningful alternatives. It is true that the phrase “a variety of absolute
truths” is incoherent. But that phrase has its place in reflecting on frameworks as a whole,
and so it occurs in the kind of context of legitimate failures of sense I have been
discussing.
This idea of alternative absolute truths also allows what I have called a genuine
pluralism. I have discussed how the relativist version of pluralism self-contradictorily
eliminates all frameworks that reject relativism; in fact, in being relativist, it arguably
eliminates much of what goes with a claim to truth, as what just is the case, in any
framework. In contrast, the idea of alternative absolute truths in the contexts I have
discussed makes room for genuine claims of truth in different global frameworks, not
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
28
excluding claims denying its own senseand it also offers the means for negotiating the
failures of sense that this kind of “making room” involves.
5. Some Consequences for the Nature of Philosophical Inquiry and Disagreement
Debate about metaphysical issues and between philosophical systems is clearly situated
in the kinds of contexts I have been discussing. Let me suggest, however, that
philosophical inquiry and disagreement in general are distinguished from other kinds of
discussion by being largely concerned with the nature of relevant sense as such. In other
words, rather than focusing, for example, only on the correct application of a concept to a
given issue, distinctively philosophical thought also focuses on the correct
characterization of the concept itself. And insofar as philosophical thought deals with
concepts or sense as such, it operates in the contexts of reflection on sense that I have
discussed. Philosophical inquiry and disagreement, then, typically invoke issues that
involve the kinds of necessary and legitimate failures of sense that I have explored here.
In the following comments on the consequences of these legitimate logical
inadequacies for philosophical debate, therefore, I shall discuss not only debate between
philosophical systems but philosophical deliberation generally. Even if the reader finds
this extension implausible, however, the following discussion of philosophical
deliberation still usefully applies, I hope, to debate about metaphysical issues and
between philosophical systems.
Philosophical deliberation and disagreement, then, typically do not consist in
weighing one perspective straightforwardly against another, but in the logically
paradoxical process of seeing everything relevant to the issue under discussion one way,
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
29
without conceivable exception or remainder, and seeing everything relevant similarly
comprehensively another way. That is, it involves seeing each wholly to the exclusion of
the other. For the same reasons that produce the legitimate logical inadequacies I have
discussed and that make, say, non sequitur part of the accurate description of the mutual
engagement of the two views, the kind of “weighing” of each against the other that
occurs here involves the entire meaninglessness and unintelligibility of the other as each
is considered.
As a description of “weighing,” this is of course incoherent. This process and
therefore also the description of it, however, occur in the kind of context of conflicted
meaning where these legitimate logical inadequacies hold, like the phrase “a variety of
absolute truths” in the previous section. As a result, their sense and articulation
appropriately involve elements of the failure of that sense.
For the same reasons, again, the outcome of philosophical disagreement and
inquiry too does not consist in deciding straightforwardly in favor of one perspective over
the other, or in favor of a compromise or a third alternative. Instead, it consists either in
an alternating understanding of both without the resources to decide between them (since
each contains all the conceivable resources to the exclusion of the other) or in emerging
into one in such a way that the other can satisfactorily be regarded as unintelligible, that
is, without any need to pursue the process further to allow the other’s potential
intelligibility to emerge again. The other view then has no meaning as an alternative or
candidate for deliberation at all, and the issue is thenin that contextabsolutely
decided.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
30
One way in which this kind of satisfactory decision can happen is if we find that,
in the end, one of the perspectives is just not a live or honest option for us, while the
other is. This kind of consideration is in fact one whose legitimacy we already recognize
intuitively or at the level of common sense in many contexts involving general
worldviews. For example, when someone is faced with a decision between religious
standpoints, or between a scientific and a religious worldview, or between a current and
an emerging scientific paradigm, or between giving herself over primarily to one or some
world causes (for example, that of the environment, gender, or world poverty) rather than
the unmanageably many possible others, or, for that matter, between comprehensive
philosophical frameworks, we recognize the sense and at least the possible legitimacy of
saying that this is a personal decision, that no one can decide for that person or produce
considerations that should in the end securely tilt the decision one way or the other for
her.
Before I pursue further the role of live or honest options in philosophical
deliberation, let me note that their role does not make philosophical decisions subjective.
First, the criteria for truth depend in part on the meaning of the relevant issues, and the
kind of decision at stake here is precisely about the nature of relevant sense and so the
relevant meanings themselves. As a result, the decision is part of establishing what the
criteria for relevant truth or falsehood might be. Consequently, it is prior to their
applicability and, with it, the applicable distinction between objective truth and subjective
conviction. Second, the meanings of the issues we are inquiring into are themselves
partly constituted by the concerns we have in asking our questions, and these concerns in
turn are partly constituted by our social and historical particularities, what Wittgenstein
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
31
called our forms of life. That is, at the level of the structure of meaning or sense itself,
our particularities as the specific creatures that we are, with the specific lives we live, are
internal to the character of that meaning or sense, including what it demarcates as
objective. As Dewey similarly argues, for example, “nature is an environment only as it
is involved in interaction with an organism, or self,” and he understands the propositions
that resolve inquiry to have their meaning essentially as resolutions of the specific,
contextualized doubts that we, the inquirers, experience. In contrast to my own view, he
sees this as true (and, further, as significantly or non-trivially true) of the results of all
inquiry, but as he clarifies it in connection with the kind of context that I discuss here, the
inquiry into logic or sense itself: “This conception implies much more than that logical
forms . . . come to light when we reflect upon processes of inquiry that are in use. Of
course it means that; but it also means that the forms originate in operations of inquiry. . .
. Primary inquiry is itself causa essendi of the forms which inquiry into inquiry
discloses.”
28
To return to the role of live or honest options, then: Raimond Gaita, in his work
on moral judgments, makes a case against what he calls “blackboard conclusions” about
moral appropriateness. As he points out, “if I am deliberating about what morally to do,
then I cannot pass my problem over to anyone else. It is non-accidentally and inescapably
mine.”
29
Consequently, “we can of course extract arguments from what [anyone] says
and write them on a blackboard, and we can try to improve on them, but until someone is
prepared to assert them seriously in his own name, then they are arguments only in
inverted commas for they yield only inverted commas conclusions—‘conclusions,’ that
is, which no one is seriously prepared to conclude” (316, my insertion). In reasoning
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
32
purely impersonally or in the abstract about moral issues, then, we are in fact avoiding
the kind of thinking they require, which requires us to be able stand behind our
conclusions sincerely, that is, to be committed to them as the particular, concrete, and
irreplaceable persons we are (149).
I propose that the same is true of all philosophical deliberation and disagreement.
Johnstone, for example, argues of philosophical debate in general, for reasons, as I noted
above, like those I offer here, in debates between “rival philosophical systems . . . the
partisan of each system is, in principle, incapable of conceiving the system espoused by
the other” (Validity, 114). But he points out that a philosopher nonetheless “stands
outside his own view” and so is capable of being “both totally immersed in his point of
view and not totally immersed in it.” This is possible because, as this capability itself
shows, a human self is “a being which in its being is what it is not, and is not what it is”
(121). He concludes that “the self . . . is the perspective from which the poles of a
contradiction are unified,” so that “the self is the pivot of philosophical controversy”
(121). Philosophy that is not just “an exercise in logic-chopping” (122), then, turns on the
kind of personal commitment for which Gaita argues in the case of morality: “Unless a
man is willing to reveal the stake he has in criticizing another position, we need not listen
to his criticism” (122).
Peirce, more generally and simply, points out that doubt which we develop on
abstract principle “will be a mere self-deception, and not real doubt. . . . Let us not
pretend to doubt in philosophy what we do not doubt in our hearts.”
30
Philosophical questions are not resolvable in the abstract, that is, on the basis of
impersonal principles of logic or justification, alone. As I have argued, in the kind of
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
33
context in which they distinctively arise the character and working of pure principles of
sense and evidencethat is, of the criteria for impersonal resolutionare precisely what
is at issue. But once, as we often can, we establish what truly is a lived consideration for
us in the concrete particularity of our lives and what is not, these same questions become,
in that context, not only resolved, but in many cases, as I have proposed, absolutely
resolved. (Gaita argues that this is true of our properly moral responses.)
We need not take too narrowly the idea that what is live for us involves the self.
In the context I have tried to establish here for the role of what is live for us, we can think
of it more broadly as whatever occurs as an actual issue for us as we go about our lives
with our actual commitments. This will then be an issue we can and should take
seriously: because it is part of our lives it is real for us, it has weight we should take into
account. Our lives do in their own course produce conflicts of understanding and
decision-making in which the sense as such of the relevant issues comes into question. If,
on the other hand, we artificially raise such conflicts, they are subject to the kinds of
objections of self-deception and pretence raised by Gaita, Peirce, and Johnstone above.
It may seem that our own honest and lived considerations must necessarily be so
obvious to us that they are not the kind of thing that needs to be established, so that if
they play a deciding role then the problem is not a philosophical or deep one, but one in
which, in a moment of aberration, we have somehow overlooked the obvious. But
establishing our own most fundamental lived considerations typically really is a
discovery, since we typically do not reflect on these very basic issues of sense. As
Wittgenstein notes, “ The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden
because of their simplicity and familiarity. (One is unable to notice somethingbecause
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
34
it is always before one’s eyes.) The real foundations of his enquiry do not strike a man at
all. . . . And this means: we fail to be struck by what, once seen, is most striking and most
powerful.”
31
It is one of the distinctive contributions of philosophy that it provokes and
enables this kind of discovery.
In fact, it does so partly in virtue of the elements of failure of sense that make
abstract philosophizing on its own inadequate. Because the sense of philosophical
deliberation is unsettled in the ways I have discussed, it allows us to recognize the
fundamentals of our own lived sense that we otherwise take for granted.
What is more, in addition to coming to this kind of recognition, precisely because
we have come to recognize ways in which issues are not live for us, and the consequent
irrelevance of that dead abstraction, we are then justified in settling into the ways in
which they are live for us, rather than simply being blindly dogmatic in doing so.
32
This
is another distinctive and important contribution of philosophical inquiry.
This picture of philosophical debate has consequences not only for deciding
between philosophical views, but also for the subsequent interaction between the
disagreeing persons or positions. Having undergone this process of reflection via
legitimate failures of sense, we are in a position both to be responsibly committed to our
own sense framework (to the extent, of course, that it meets its own particular standards
of sense), and also to be able to understand, in the abstract, others (again, to the extent
that they meet their own standards of sense) that are, strictly, inconceivable within our
own. And given this understanding, we are also in a position to understand how this for
us strictly inconceivable purported worldview is for its inhabitants the honestly lived and
therefore, equally with ours, the legitimately and responsibly grasped reality for which
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
35
ours is in turn strictly inconceivable and without force to convince. In this light,
interaction between the two viewpoints allows for both the firm conviction that the other
is wrong, with the conduct that follows on that conviction, and simultaneously an
understanding of the reverse perspective, with the conduct that follows on that insight.
So, for example, while we may appropriately fight for the dominance of our view, we
will not demonize the other for doing the same, and may be sympathetic and motivated to
help the opponent in the many contexts that are to some degree independent of the
directly conflicted issues, and perhaps even in some contexts that are directly part of the
conflict.
That there are elements of legitimate failure of sense in philosophical thought has
consequences, too, for the procedures of philosophical deliberation and disagreement. For
example, reliance on our intuitions or on what is currently intelligible to us is insufficient
in this kind of inquiry. Since mutually exclusive construals of relevant sense or of sense
in general characterize the contexts in which this kind of deliberation occurs, the failure
of a line of thought to meet our intuitions or standards of intelligibility may signal not the
inadequacy of that line of thought, but the role of a sense framework or conceptual order
that is not currently available to us, and so the need to develop new conceptual resources
with their corresponding intuitions.
What is more, because elements of failure of sense necessarily characterize these
contexts, and because here this failure is part of the working of sense itself, it is generally
the case that the procedure of philosophical reasoning and disagreement requires us to
negotiate failure of sense, and to do so in this non-dismissive way. That is, it necessarily
involves moments on our own part, as arguers or reasoners, of deep conceptual confusion
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
36
and incapacity to find our way with respect to the issues under discussion, and it requires
suspension of judgment with respect to the ultimate import of that confusion, a patient
making room for the unfolding of what may be sense in a framework or conceptual order
not yet available to us. (It may happen, of course, that in the end we find there is no
relevant alternative framework that can be established, and then the incoherence we have
encountered is simply incoherence, and warrants dismissal of the view in question. But
we cannot legitimately decide that in advance.) Similarly, it requires us to treat those
same kinds of loss of resource in those we are debating with not as an indication of the
likely inadequacy of their stance, but as possibly a phase of their competence in their own
negotiation of a logically anomalous situation. Again, the immediate unintelligibility of
another view or of its presentation, or of our own to the other person or position, in
contexts where relevant sense as such is in question, requires not dismissal but
suspension of judgment about what counts as sense.
On the other hand, as I discussed in section 3, because these logical anomalies are
part of the working of sense itself, they also give us clues as to how to resolve the
confusion. It is part of the philosopher’s capable procedure, then, to work with and under
the guidance of moments of incapacity to make sense, whether these moments are our
own or of those with whom we engage. I began this section by saying that philosophical
argument is not and should not be understood as a straightforward balancing of views.
Instead, as a procedure that involves accepting the confusion and failure of our
conceptual capabilities in order to reconstitute them in this way, it is the exercise of that
aspect of reasoning which is our access to a deeper or renewed sense of our lives, of the
world, and of our place in it.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
37
As a final note, let me suggest that we ourselves consist partly in awareness and in
activities of sense-making, and that the reality of sense for which I have argued is in our
case therefore also a matter of our ontology, and so of metaphysics in the sense of the
structure of reality and not only of its study. This is a case where the reality of sense and
reality in the more fully ontological meaning coincide. If this is true, then for us the issue
of the nature of sense and meaning themselves is not only an intellectual or cognitive
question, but one that engages our very substance as creatures ourselves partly consisting
in awareness and its fabric of meanings. The fact of and encounter with real failure of
sense in the context of philosophical argumentation is then not only a cognitive or
observational engagement with deep questions about meaning and reality, but is also an
encounter with and an activation or quickening of our own meaningful being, and of our
relation, in which we ourselves partly consist, to meaning as a whole. That is,
philosophical argumentation is then, in part, our being carrying itself out and in that sense
emerging.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
38
Works Cited
Barris, J. (2012). The convergent conceptions of being in mainstream analytic and
postmodern continental philosophy. Metaphilosophy, 43, 592-618.
Barris, J. (2009). The Crane’s Walk; Plato, Pluralism, and the Inconstancy of Truth. New
York: Fordham University Press.
Barris, J. (2014). Sometimes Always True: Undogmatic Pluralism in Politics,
Metaphysics, and Epistemology. New York: Fordham University Press.
Bremer, M. (2005). An Introduction to Paraconsistent Logics. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.
Collingwood, R. G. (1940). An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1984). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In Inquiries into Truth
and Interpretation, New York: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and
Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Cambridge,
MA: Blackwell.
Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt.
De Wijze, S. (2007). Dirty hands: Doing wrong to do right. In I. Primoratz (Ed.), Politics
and Morality, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Eemeren, F, H. van, R. Grootendorst, and F. S. Henkemans (Eds.). (1996). Fundamentals
of Argumentation Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and
Contemporary Developments. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Epictetus. (1964). Moral Discourses. Trans. E. Carter and T. W. Higginson. Ed. T.
Gould. New York: Washington Square Press.
Gaita, R. (2004). Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception, 2
nd
ed. New York: Routledge.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
39
Grassi, E. (2001). Rhetoric as Philosophy: The Humanist Tradition. Trans. J. M. Krois
and A. Azodi. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
Hall, E. W. (1960). Philosophical Systems: A Categorial Analysis. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Heidegger, M. (1984). The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Trans. M. Heim.
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Johnstone, H. W., Jr. (1978). Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument: An
Outlook in Transition. University Park, PA: The Dialogue Press of Man and World.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2
nd
ed. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1989). Relativism, power, and philosophy. In M. Krausz (Ed.),
Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press.
McConnell, T. (2010). Moral dilemmas. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Summer 2010), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/moral-dilemmas/>.
Nagel, T. (1979). The absurd. In Mortal Questions, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Paul, R. W. (1992). Teaching critical reasoning in the strong sense: Getting behind
worldviews. In R. A. Talaska (Ed.), Critical Reasoning in Contemporary Culture,
Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
40
Pearce, W. B. and S. W. Littlejohn (1997). Moral Conflict: When Social Worlds Collide
Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.
Peirce, C. S. (1958). Some consequences of four incapacities. In P. P. Wiener (Ed.),
Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings, New York: Dover Publications.
Perelman Ch. and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969). The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on
Argumentation. Trans. J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver. Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press.
Priest, G. (2001). An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Putnam, H. (1990). Realism with a Human Face. Ed. James Conant. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers Volume 1.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Russell, B. (1963). The study of mathematics. In Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays.
London: Unwin Books.
Schiller, F. C. S. (1930). Logic for Use: An Introduction to the Voluntarist Theory of
Knowledge. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Taylor, C. (1985). Rationality. In Philosophical Papers Volume 2: Philosophy and the
Human Sciences, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
41
Winch, P. (1964). Understanding a primitive society. American Philosophical Quarterly
1, 307324
Virno, P. (2008). Multitude between Innovation and Negation. Trans. I. Bertoletti, J.
Cascaito, and A. Casson. New York: Semiotext(e).
Willard, C. A. (1983). Argumentation and the Social Grounds of Knowledge. University,
AL: The University of Alabama Press.
Walton, D. (1996). Argument Structure: A Pragmatic Theory. Toronto: University of
Toronto Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty. Ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright.
Trans. D. Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: Harper & Row.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Malden,
MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
42
Notes
1
I would like to thank one of the journal’s anonymous referees, who made several
suggestions that helped to make this a significantly better paper.
2
There is a growing literature on paraconsistent formal logics, some of which allow and
manage “true contradictions.” See, for example, Manuel Bremer, An Introduction to
Paraconsistent Logics (Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 2005), e.g., 16, 19ff.; Graham Priest, An
Introduction to Non-Classical Logic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001),
e.g., 67ff., 151.
3
I discuss the character, legitimacy, and negotiation of this kind of incoherence, as well
as some of its consequences, in other connections at length elsewhere. See, for example,
Jeremy Barris, “The Convergent Conceptions of Being in Mainstream Analytic and
Postmodern Continental Philosophy,” Metaphilosophy 43 (2012): 592-618; The Crane’s
Walk; Plato, Pluralism, and the Inconstancy of Truth (New York: Fordham University
Press, 2009); Sometimes Always True: Undogmatic Pluralism in Politics, Metaphysics,
and Epistemology (New York: Fordham University Press, 2014).
4
For this more developed argument, see Sometimes Always True, especially chapters 1-3.
5
For an overview of the debate on moral dilemmas, and a useful bibliography, see
Terrance McConnell, “Moral Dilemmas,” in Edward N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/moral-dilemmas/>. On “dirty hands,”
see, for example, Stephen de Wijze, “Dirty Hands: Doing Wrong to Do Right,” in Igor
Primoratz, ed., Politics and Morality (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), 3-19.
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
43
6
As Russell, for example, puts it in connection with the standard laws of logic (although
not the “legitimately inadequate” structures I am proposing), they are a matter of “the
very heart and immutable essence of all things actual and possible,” and not “something
more or less human and subject to our limitations”; Bertrand Russell, “The Study of
Mathematics,” in Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays (London: Unwin Books, 1963),
55.
7
For this more properly ontological focus, see, for example, “Convergent Conceptions”;
Sometimes Always True, especially chapters 6 and 8.
8
Alasdair MacIntyre, “Relativism, power, and philosophy,” in Michael Krausz, ed.,
Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1989), 190.
9
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2
nd
ed. (Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press, 1970).
10
See, for example, Thomas Nagel, (1979) “The Absurd,” in Mortal Questions
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), on the meaningful continuity between
the requirement for an account of issues within the context of our general sense of things
and a requirement for an account of that general sense of things itself.
11
Donald Davidson, “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme,” in Inquiries into Truth
and Interpretation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), 183-198.
12
Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1988), 374.
13
Peter Winch, ‘‘Understanding a Primitive Society,’’ American Philosophical Quarterly
1.4 (1964): 307324, 318. Hilary Putnam makes the further point that if we recognize
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
44
that Davidson’s translator “himself may have more than one ‘home’ conceptual scheme,
and that ‘translation practice’ may be governed by more than one set of constraints, then
one sees that conceptual relativity does not disappear when we inquire into the
‘meanings’ of the various conceptual alternatives: it simply reproduces itself at a
metalinguistic level!”; Hilary Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. James Conant
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 104.
14
Donald Davidson, “A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs,” in Ernest Lepore, ed., Truth and
Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson (Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell, 1986), 446.
15
For example, Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers
Volume 1 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 42: “All the pragmatist can do
is . . . point to the seeming futility of metaphysical activity.”
16
See, for example, R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1940); Everett W. Hall, Philosophical Systems: A Categorial Analysis (Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press, 1960); W. V. O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and
Other Essays (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969); Henry W. Johnstone, Jr.,
Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument: An Outlook in Transition (University
Park, PA: The Dialogue Press of Man and World, 1978), e.g., chapters 7 and 16.
17
For MacIntyre, see, for example, Whose Justice? For Taylor, see, for example,
“Rationality,” in Charles Taylor, Philosophical Papers Volume 2: Philosophy and the
Human Sciences (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 134-151.
18
See, for example, Richard W. Paul, “Teaching Critical Reasoning in the Strong Sense:
Getting Behind Worldviews,” in Richard A. Talaska, ed., Critical Reasoning in
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
45
Contemporary Culture (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1992), 135-
156; W. Barnett Pearce and Stephen W. Littlejohn, Moral Conflict: When Social Worlds
Collide (Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 1997); Frans H. van Eemeren, Rob
Grootendorst, and Francisca Snoeck Henkemans, eds., Fundamentals of Argumentation
Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments
(Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1996), 341-342; Charles Arthur Willard,
Argumentation and the Social Grounds of Knowledge (University, AL: The University of
Alabama Press, 1983).
19
Paolo Virno, Multitude between Innovation and Negation, trans. Isabella Bertoletti,
James Cascaito, and Andrea Casson (New York: Semiotext(e), 2008), part 2.
20
Epictetus, Moral Discourses, trans. Elizabeth Carter and Thomas Wentworth
Higginson, ed. Thomas Gould (New York: Washington Square Press, 1964), 142-143.
21
Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright,
trans. Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: Harper & Row, 1969), 15e, no.
94.
22
Martin Heidegger, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, trans. Michael Heim
(Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1984), 19-20.
23
For examples of conventionalist accounts, see Chaim Perelman and L. Olbrechts-
Tyteca, The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation, trans. John Wilkinson and
Purcell Weaver (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1969); Willard,
Argumentation. For examples of pragmatist accounts, see F. C. S. Schiller, Logic for Use:
An Introduction to the Voluntarist Theory of Knowledge (New York: Harcourt Brace,
Metaphysics, Pluralism, Informal Logic
46
1930); Douglas Walton, Argument Structure: A Pragmatic Theory (Toronto: University
of Toronto Press, 1996).
24
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2
nd
ed. (Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press, 1970), e.g., 111-112.
25
On the admissibility of contradiction in informal contexts, see, for example, Johnstone,
Validity, 45. For the permissibility and manageability of contradictions in paraconsistent
formal logics, see the references in note 2.
26
Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 1989), 73.
27
Ernesto Grassi, Rhetoric as Philosophy: The Humanist Tradition, trans. John Michael
Krois and Azizeh Azodi (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001
[1980]), e.g., 24-27.
28
John Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (New York: Henry Holt, 1938), 1056, 4.
29
Raimond Gaita, Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception, 2
nd
ed. (New York:
Routledge, 2004), 103.
30
Charles Sanders Peirce, “Some Consequences of Four Incapacities,” in Philip P.
Wiener, ed., Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings (New York: Dover Publications, 1958),
40.
31
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Malden,
MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1958), 50e, no. 129.
32
I discuss this kind of justification at length in “Convergent Conceptions”; Sometimes
Always True, especially chapter 2.