Marshall University Marshall University
Marshall Digital Scholar Marshall Digital Scholar
Humanities Faculty Research Humanities
3-2010
The logical structure of dreams and their relation to reality The logical structure of dreams and their relation to reality
Jeremy Barris
Follow this and additional works at: https://mds.marshall.edu/humanities_faculty
Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Psychology Commons
The Logical Structure of Dreams and Their Relation to Reality
Jeremy Barris
Philosophy Department
Marshall University
Huntington, WV 25755
U.S.A.
Telephone: (304) 696-2704
Word count: 10,781
Abstract
The contradictions and non-sequiturs often found in dreams (or, equivalently, dream-
narratives) are not in fact logical errors, but express and work with a type of logic that
characterises the deepest dimensions of our waking reality. These are the dimensions in
which we deal with ourselves as a whole, our lives as a whole, or with the sense of reality
as a whole. We do so, for example, in situations of deep personal transformation, or of
recognition of deep difference of outlook. The paper argues that the logic of these
situations is validly one of contradiction and non-sequitur, that dreams sometimes express
and work with these kinds of situation, and that these kinds of dreams therefore validly
involve the same kind of logic. These kinds of dreams consequently also express insight
into the sense that our lives or existence as a whole has for us. In achieving that insight,
they actively orient, situate, or re-situate us in our relation to our lives or existence as a
whole. In this respect they are in themselves a practice of philosophy.
Logic of Dreams
1
The Logical Structure of Dreams and Their Relation to Reality
Dream narratives are very often thought to be full of contradictionsfor example,
of shifts in identity as one thing suddenly turns out to be anotherand of non-sequitur
leaps in continuity. These are the most basic ways of being illogical, of violating the
conditions for making sense. Although, as I shall discuss below, a lot of dream
researchers and theorists defend dream thinking as not typically violating sense in these
ways, I shall endorse the view that dream narratives do often contain contradictions and
non-sequiturs. In doing so, however, I am not accusing dream narratives of the kinds of
irrationality from which those theorists aim to defend them. For I propose, first, that
dream narratives are nonetheless perfectly logically valid, and that they are so not despite
but in these violations of sense. More accurately, I shall try to show that these violations
are logically valid in dream narratives at least in some respects, leaving open whether
there are not also ways in which these narratives are simply nonsensical. Second, I shall
try to show that these violations of sense are logically valid because they accurately
express the logic of certain very deep kinds of issue, and that dreams involving these
otherwise illogical dimensions sometimes deal precisely with these kinds of issue.
In the rest of this paper, I shall refer to dreams rather than dream narratives. This
may give rise to two sorts of objections. First, it is true that there are all sorts of possible
problems, both epistemological and semantic, with the idea of dreams’ existing
independently of our reports of them. So far, however, this debate is far from concluded,
and reference to dreams themselves is still certainly defensible (see, for example, the
essays responding to Norman Malcolm’s seminal book [1959] on this issue in Dunlop,
Logic of Dreams
2
1977). In any event, it does not affect my claims or argument here if we replace “dreams”
with “dream narratives.” If dream reporters can identify with or become caught up in the
attitudes and feelings articulated in the narratives they present, then what I have to say
about dreams applies just as well to those narratives of the dreams. (This has the result
that narratives of other kinds, like artistic fictions or even other people’s dream reports,
can have exactly the same status for these purposes as the person’s own dream reports. I
see no problem with that result.)
1
If, then, the reader is convinced that reference to
dreams themselves is illegitimate or too problematic, she or he may take my use of the
term “dream” as convenient shorthand for “dream report” without affecting the purport of
the discussion.
The second possible objection is that, for those who are committed to the idea that
logical relations characterize only collections of propositions and not the world of events
and things, the claim that dreams are contradictory or contain non-sequiturs is incoherent,
since dreams are events or perhaps “thing”-like experiences or states. These readers, too,
may replace the references to dreams with references to dream narratives without
affecting the gist of the argument. It is not, however, clear to me that dreams are simply
objective events or states, rather than consisting partly in a point of view on things. A
point of view, presumably, can be contradictory or involve non-sequiturs. Further, I do
not believe that this very widespread view of the field of application of logic is tenable. It
is by now a commonplace in a host of philosophical traditions that facts and events are
“theory-laden,” that what we mean by our references to things and events presupposes a
grammar of usage of the terms we are using to refer to them. In other words, anything we
can mean by things and events, including what we can mean by their objectivity and
Logic of Dreams
3
independence of us and of our language, is exactly a matter of grammatical meaning.
Consequently, things and events are not ultimately separable from the relations of the
propositions in which we articulate them, and so from the logic that characterizes those
propositional relations.
My claim that there are logically valid violations of sense may give rise to another
possible immediate objection, that in principle or by definition contradictions cannot
contribute to or be a form of making logical sense. But this is no longer un-
controversially the case even in formal logic. On the formal admissibility of
contradictions see, for example, Priest (2001), and on the formally admissible existence
of true contradictions see, for example, Bremer (2005, pp. 16, 19ff.) and Priest (2001,
e.g., pp. 67ff., 151). For useful discussion on both sides of this debate, see Priest, Beall,
and Armour-Garb (2004).
Despite how formal logic has at times been seen, however, it is not a
representation of the essence of valid inference and so is not the final arbiter of questions
about sense and its violations. On the contrary, it is only one limited model in which to
frame these questions. As Johnstone (1978) argues, ‘in formal systems . . . the axioms
and rules of inference are unambiguously stated and it is irrelevant to consider the
meanings of the symbols. But clearly the assertion of a philosophical thesis is not like
this, for the meanings of the symbols in terms of which the assertion is made are clearly
essential to the enterprise of making the assertion’ (p. 45). What is more, logical systems
are themselves developed and justified on the basis of philosophical considerations,
which are therefore more ultimate arbiters than they are. As Johnstone notes, ‘the very
notion of inconsistency is itself subject to philosophical interpretation’ (p. 45).
Logic of Dreams
4
Philosophical thought occurs at a level before formal systems and their principles acquire
their force. Even where formal systems of logic do forbid contradiction, then, they
meaningfully do so only within their own systems. (For a defense and exploration of
legitimate contradiction in the context of concrete, non-formalized philosophical issues,
see, for example, Priest [2002].)
To see this more clearly, one might ask on what principle, legitimated by what,
can contradictions never conceivably contribute to logical sense? Would this be the
principle of non-contradiction, magically validating itself? If, on the other hand, one says
the principle is self-evident, one is relying on a psychological and therefore empirical fact
the fact of what people happen to find obvious as somehow able to support a principle
that recognizes no empirical circumstances as affecting its validity (see, for example,
Haack, 1978, pp. 235-236). Given the status and difficulties of this debate, it is certainly
legitimate at least to explore the possibility that contradictions may be part of logical
sense. In what follows, therefore, I shall do so.
I now return to my thesis. As I mentioned, I propose that this paradoxical logic of
legitimate violations of sense does not only characterize dreams, but also characterizes
certain very deep kinds of issue. In fact, as I shall argue, it characterizes the deepest, most
meaningful dimensions of our sober, waking reality. And I propose that dreams involve
this type of logic because they accurately express and work with the logic of those real
and deepest dimensions of our lives. These are the dimensions in which we deal, not with
this or that aspect of our selves, our lives, or the world, but with our selves as a whole,
our lives as a whole, or with the sense of reality as a whole.
Logic of Dreams
5
Currently, there are both an influential postmodern and an influential neo-
Wittgensteinian skepticism about the sense of the idea of “things as a whole” or “oneself
as a whole” and so of a view of things or oneself as a whole. On the genuine sense of this
idea, however, see, for example, Nagel (1979, pp. 11-23) and Derrida (1981, p. 6). The
view Derrida expresses in this connection is in fact central (as he insists repeatedly
throughout his work) to the entire project of his version of “deconstruction”: that
traditional metaphysical concepts like that of the “totality of things” are essential, but just
not the last word. Consequently, Derrida’s version of postmodernism is what he calls a
‘double writing,’ always both a ‘most faithful’ reading ‘inside’ the metaphysical tradition
and a reading ‘outside’ it (p. 6). On the sense of an idea of “things as a whole” or
“oneself as a whole” specifically in connection with dreams, see, for example, States
(1988), who writes, ‘my dream . . . is the pulse and direction of my existence. . . . Just as
a child cannot possibly detect the moment at which it became aware of the world . . . the
dreamer cannot detect the beginning of his dream because for that interval the dream is
all of his consciousness that exists. The dream is the center and the horizon of his world’
(p. 85). Another dream theorist, Gendlin (1986), points out that we may have a need ‘to
grow as a whole,’ when it is not enough to ‘keep trying to fix only the situation’ (p. 188,
italics in original). Valberg (2007) focuses specifically on this dimension of dreaming,
and actually uses the all-embracing ‘horizon’ of dreams to demonstrate the necessity of
the idea of a view of the world or one’s life as a whole (e.g., pp. 69-70).
2
Taking the idea of a view of “things as a whole” as legitimate, then, the kind of
situation in which we deal with our selves or our lives as a whole arises when, for
example, we grow in an overall way, our entire sense of ourselves becoming transformed,
Logic of Dreams
6
or when we lose our sense of ourselves. And we deal with our sense of reality as a whole
when, for example, we encounter, in other people or cultures or subcultures, ideas about
reality that do not fit with our sense of what reality can include. (I should note that the
fact that ideas which do not make sense in our terms belong to a different culture or
subculture does not automatically make them valid. They may in fact be simply and
absolutely nonsense. But an encounter even with mistaken ideas about reality that do not
fit with our own overall ways of making sense can produce, by their contrast with our
sense of reality, an awareness of that sense of reality in general, or as a whole.)
I shall argue, then, that dreams express and work with the logic of gaining a sense
of and a relation to ourselves, our lives, or our sense of reality as a whole. These three
senses of things as a whole have in common that they are self-inclusive, or self-reflexive.
For example, the sense that we might have of reality as a whole is itself included in
reality as a whole: this sense is therefore, in at least some respect, partly a sense of itself.
I shall try to show that, because of this self-inclusion, the logic of these senses of things
as a whole, in waking reality as in dreams, is validly one of contradiction and non-
sequitur. (On the theme of the relation between self-reference and true contradiction, see
Priest [2002, e.g., p. 4].)
As I mentioned at the start of the paper, there are researchers or theorists who
argue that dreams are no less logical than waking life, and who show how the apparently
bizarre logic of dreams can be translated into the logic of waking life. Cavallero and
Foulkes (1993), for example, argue that ‘Dreams are not, in general, wildly implausible,
vaguely experienced, or full of nonsensical images or image sequences. They are, rather,
reasonable projections of what we might expect if waking cognition were operating under
Logic of Dreams
7
the somewhat dissociated circumstances generally accompanying sleep’ (p. 11). See also
States (1993, especially chapter one). But given that I do not take waking life to be
essentially describable in keeping with the criteria of standard logic, I do not think these
views are necessarily incompatible with my own.
3
I agree that dreams show the same
basic logic as everyday life, but I also think that everyday life involves dimensions that
are only and legitimately describable in contradictions and non-sequiturs. Consequently,
while dreams do share the same logic with waking life, it is partly a logic of legitimate
violations of sense. In any event, I think these theorists can agree that there are at least
some dreams that involve genuine contradictions and non-sequiturs. With that restriction,
I would be content to argue that, while many dreams may reflect the standard logic of
everyday life, the illogical dreams (at least sometimes or in some part) express the
deeper, paradoxical kind of logic I have proposed belongs to the sense of our lives as a
whole.
Even if there is real and intractable disagreement between these theorists and
myself, however, I do not wish to say that they are wrong. I find their arguments
persuasive and thought-provoking. I am only proposing a possible way of making sense
of dreams and a possible role they play in our lives, with, I hope, enough justification to
show that this proposal is worth exploring further. There is room here to explore
conflicting explanatory proposals without deciding which of them is right.
I shall not explore here whether there are in fact valid methods of dream
interpretation. I shall take it as at least arguable that some of the widely used methods
(say, Freudian, Jungian, Gestalt, or Focusing methods) are valid, so that dreams possibly
express something at least in some way meaningful for the dreamer’s life. What I shall
Logic of Dreams
8
really try to show, then, is that if dreams can be interpreted at all, if they have any
meaning at all, then they are logical in this paradoxical way. This assumption may of
course be wrong, but it is not obviously or un-controversially so.
In the first section, I shall explain why, in those waking situations that involve
dealing with our lives or reality as a whole, logic, or the way sense works, must be
contradictory and discontinuous. (I shall discuss dealing with our selves as a whole in the
second section, as part of an illustration from an actual dream.) In the second section I
shall try to show that dreams do deal with these situations. In the third section I shall
briefly discuss how it follows from this proposal that dreams are not only expressions of
a sense of our lives or reality as a whole, but are at the same time dynamic
transformations of our lives or our relations to reality as a whole. In other words, they are
a form of what we might call existential practice. In the final section I shall try to show
that some of the classical theories of dream interpretation offer partial or indirect support
for my proposal.
1. The Same Logic in Waking Life
To start with an easily recognisable example, when we are depressed, everything
in the world is felt in keeping with that low mood. The blue sky and sunshine are
annoying because they remind me how depressed I am, they rub it in that I cannot enjoy
the beautiful weather. The piece of good news brings into relief how unsatisfying
everything else in my life is, and even makes me feel worse because I cannot enjoy it
properly. When, on the other hand, we are in a good mood, everything in the world is felt
in keeping with our cheerfulness. The gray, rainy weather makes a nice, cosy contrast
Logic of Dreams
9
with the warmth inside; the bad news is a challenge to be overcome, or is only one part,
not especially important, of a basically likeable world.
Now, if we want to explain how one shifts from one of these moods to another, or
how one might debate the truth or value of these two views of reality, we cannot point to
anything in the world. Everything in the world, all of reality, reality itself, is understood
as miserable in the one mood, and as cheerful in the other. Each of these two overall
senses of things includes all the same entities and events, and interprets all of them in
opposed ways. As Wittgenstein pointed out, ‘the world of the happy man is a different
one from that of the unhappy man’; in moving from one to the other it ‘becomes an
altogether different world’ (1961, p. 72, prop. 6.43). There is no way, then, to have a
rational debate between these senses of reality, or to undergo a rationally motivated
transformation of one into the other. Anything one might refer to in the debate or in
motivating the change is already understood by each sense of reality to the exclusion of
the other. As a result, as soon as one refers to or specifies what one means, the ‘debate’ is
already decided. The contrasting version of things one wants to justify is already
excluded as senseless, as not part of the world, as unreal by definition. And there is no
neutral ground that either sense of reality needs to acknowledge. They each already
include everything, reality as a whole. There is nothing left over to be neutral ground.
But one mood does become transformed into another. And the person in each
mood can be (and usually is) aware that the sense given by the other mood exists, that
s/he has felt before and can feel again in ways that are not accessible to her at the
moment. But it still remains true that the two moods grasp the whole of reality
differently, and that there is therefore nothing left out of each sense of reality. As a result,
Logic of Dreams
10
the awareness that both moods are possible can only consist in understanding exactly the
same thingthe world as a wholein different, and in fact in mutually exclusive ways,
at the same time. In other words, this awareness involves contradiction and discontinuity.
The fact of the transition itself from one mood to another is also significant here.
This transition can only consist in one sense or understanding of things itself giving rise
to an incompatible one. There is nothing left out of each sense of the world, so that one
sense of reality can only give rise to the incompatible one out of itself. In other words, it
itself gives rise to the sense it also excludes. In this situation, transformation too, then,
involves contradiction and discontinuity.
It may be objected, and rightly, that standpoints that grasp the whole of reality
differently in this way cannot conflict with each other and therefore cannot contradict
each other. Such standpoints cannot mean and so share the “same” things to disagree
about. But, given that I am arguing that in this kind of situation of understandings of the
whole of things contradictions are both necessary and true, this point is not an objection
to what I am saying, but part of it. One way of expressing my proposal is that wholly
mutually exclusive standpoints both have nothing in common at all and are standpoints
on all the “ same” things. In other words, the objection is true and the contradiction of it
is true. Wholly mutually exclusive standpoints are not about the same things and so
cannot contradict each other, and yet they also are and do. As I have argued, first, since
we understand the whole of everything in each of the two mutually exclusive ways, this is
at least in some sense exactly the same thing we are understanding in each case: there is
nothing left over, nothing else, we can be re-understanding. Second, such standpoints do
become transformed into each other: the unhappy world itself becomes transformed into
Logic of Dreams
11
the happy world. Again, there is nothing else, nothing left over, to undergo this
transformation. It is a shift of one and the same thing into the new sense of it.
Consequently, while the two standpoints cannot refer to the same things and so cannot
conflict with each other, they also cannot but refer to the same things and so cannot but
conflict with each other.
This meta-contradiction, then, about the occurrence of contradiction in cases
involving understandings of the whole of things, is one expression of the type of
contradiction I am defending in general here.
It may be objected even more fundamentally that it is simply not meaningful to
compare two such different ways of making sense at all, so as to say they are in some
sense interpretations of the same thing. Consequently it is literally without meaning to
say that they can conflict with and so contradict each other. But in that case, it is equally
meaningless to compare them so as to say they are in some sense not interpretations of
the same thing, and so equally without meaning to say they cannot contradict each other.
(For a detailed discussion of the implications of this outcome, see Barris [2006], where I
respond to Donald Davidson’s well-known rejection of ‘the very idea of a conceptual
scheme’ or overall framework of sense, and so of whatever lines of thought may be based
on this idea.)
Let me note, then, that if I am wrong about the possibility of contradiction in this
kind of situation, it is not because we already know that “incommensurable” standpoints
(as they are often called, after Kuhn, 1970) cannot contradict each other. I know this too,
and am insisting on it. If I am wrong about the relation between these standpoints, it is
because I fail to demonstrate that this contradiction, as well as not occurring, also, in
Logic of Dreams
12
contradiction to what we know, does occur in this case. And that needs to be judged on
the basis of the discussion supporting it in this section, not on the basis of preconceptions
about what can be said on this issue that miss the point this discussion defends. In fact,
even if these presuppositions were relevant, I have already given explicit reason to
question them in the discussion of contradiction above; there is no justification for taking
them for granted here.
To move from moods to the world of ideas and developed knowledge, it is a
familiar argument in philosophy of science (Feyerabend, 1993, especially chapter 16;
Kuhn, 1970; Wittgenstein, 1979), political philosophy (Lyotard, 1988; MacIntyre, 1988;
Taylor, 1985, especially chapters 3-5), and in treatments of disagreements between whole
philosophical systems (Collingwood, 1940; Hall, 1960), that conflicting understandings
of what reality itself is, of what reality can include, cannot rationally debate with each
other. These kinds of understandings or frameworks do not only see this or that piece of
reality differently, but see reality itself and in general differently. Consequently, as with
moods, anything they might point to, in order to resolve the debate, is already understood
differently in the other framework. More specifically, it is understood in the context of
the other framework’s sense of what reality can include, so that each piece of evidence
already depends on the decision about reality that the debate is supposed to decide.
One cannot appeal, either, to the broad rules of logic or sense-making to decide
between the frameworks. These rules can only work with meanings as they are given to
them, and here the meanings are exactly what are in conflict, exactly what need to be
decided. And, in any event, the rules of sense-making themselves can differ between very
different frameworks of the sense of things.
Logic of Dreams
13
For example, in debates between evolutionists and creationists, evolutionists tend
to have a view of reality as consisting in matter and energy, and of the reality outside our
bodies as having basically reliable connections with our senses. Creationists, by contrast,
tend to have a view of reality as including divine revelation and spiritual dimensions, in
comparison with which our senses and independent human reasoning are entirely fallible.
Now, it is logically impossible for scientific method to prove that there is matter and
energy, since the sensory observations that are essential to its method depend on there
being a material world that can make them sensory observations, at all (rather than, say,
self-produced dream images). And it is logically impossible for revelation to prove the
spiritual world exists, since it depends on the reality of that world to give it any meaning
as revelation in the first place (rather than, say, chemical imbalance).
But, whether or not either or both of these views is true, we are capable of
understanding both. And, as in the case of understanding the possibility of conflicting
moods, this means we understand exactly the same thingthe world as a whole or in
generalin mutually exclusive ways at the same time. Further, we are rationally required
to gain an understanding of both views (assuming both are at least intelligible): we cannot
decide which is true without entertaining both of them. Consequently, at least one phase
of rational thinking about these issues requires us to think about the same things in
mutually exclusive ways at the same time. Again, then, this is a necessary kind of
awareness that involves contradiction and discontinuity.
In fact, one cannot have even one understanding of or perspective on reality as a
whole without automatically also having the idea of possible contrasting alternatives
(Davidson, 1984; as I discuss below, Davidson in fact takes this in the opposite direction
Logic of Dreams
14
from mine). The idea that reality as a whole is to be understood one way implies a
contrast with other possible ways of understanding it, ways that it rejects. Otherwise the
“one way” is not distinguished from any other, and so has no particular content. And
since these are contrasting ways of understanding the sense of things as a whole, they are
mutually exclusive with our current sense of what can be real or of what makes sense.
This means that even a single perspective or sense of reality-as-a-whole necessarily
involves the idea of logical contradictions to or discontinuities with itself.
These kinds of situation are not simply a matter of entertaining conflicting
possibilities about the same thing. In that case, there would be no contradiction, since
possibilities, by definition, do not assert themselves as the unique state of affairs: they
make room for conflicting alternatives. Here, however, there is no sense to the idea of an
“actual thing” apart from each interpretation. As a result, in each case we are
understanding the thing with all its possibilitiesin fact, everything that might be meant
by that thing—in mutually exclusive ways. We are understanding the “same” thing
simultaneously in ways that exclude each other even as possible ways of understanding
“it.” Or, to put the same point differently, because reality itself, as a whole, is what is
differently understood in these two frameworks, with nothing left out in each case, each
interpretation of reality is the unique state of affairs, allowing no meaning to the idea of
conflicting alternatives.
4
The idea that such different understandings of reality are really possible has often
been challenged, perhaps most powerfully by Donald Davidson (1984) and Richard Rorty
(1991). Very roughly, Davidson’s argument is that it is self-contradictory to claim to
conceive contrasting understandings of reality as a whole, since any conception we have
Logic of Dreams
15
can by definition only occur within our understanding of reality as a wholeand this
includes conceptions of contrasting understandings of reality as a whole. I cannot begin
to do justice to their objections here (for a detailed response to their objections on this
issue, see Barris, 2006), so I shall take the fact that the debate is still running strongly as
warrant at least for continuing to explore the idea that such different frameworks are
possible.
I note, howeverand, in the absence of providing the opposing arguments in
detail, I can only do so extremely tentatively and provisionallythat the objections to
this idea are ultimately based on the principle that logical contradiction is always
unacceptable. In that light, any idea that leads to endorsing logical contradiction, as the
idea of such different frameworks does, must have something wrong with it. But, as I
have noted, the exclusive principle of non-contradiction cannot be taken for granted in
this way. And as I have argued, this principle is not, itself, something that can be
defended by the kind of logic that endorses it: that kind of logical argument depends on
it. It is one of the standards for sense-making on which it relies in order to produce its
arguments, including its justifications of the principle itself.
In other words, the exclusive principle of non-contradiction is part of just another
one of those ways of understanding the sense of reality as a whole and in general, that
cannot rationally debate with contrasting frameworks. This principle on its own, then,
cannot justify rejecting a framework that is based on accepting some kinds of
contradiction. And since the argument that we need such a framework is partly based, as I
hope I have illustrated, on implications of non-contradictory sense-making itself, there is
Logic of Dreams
16
reason for adherents of the no-contradiction framework to make room for the legitimacy
of at least exploring the viability of the some-contradiction framework.
Now, assuming that different understandings of reality itself are possible, or even
that one can have an understanding of reality as a whole (and as I have argued, these
come to the same thing), engaging with such understandings is not just a matter of
intellectual vision. Since the self that is doing this understanding is part of reality as a
whole, if this self understands reality in contradictory ways then it automatically
understands itself, as a whole, in contradictory ways. (This is also and more obviously
true, of course, if the understanding is of the self’s life as a whole, rather than of reality in
general as a whole.) That is, its sense of itself as a whole, and so it as a whole, is
automatically caught up in the contradiction.
2. The Logical Structure of Dreams
I shall now try to show that dreams express and work with this kind of situation of
dealing with our selves, our lives, or reality as a whole. If this is true, then at least part of
their contradictory and non-sequitur character expresses the legitimate logic of some
kinds of real situations.
Like different moods or different global understandings of reality in relation to
one other, dreams and waking life deal with all the same particular events and entities as
each other, and consequently grasp them differently only as a whole. The old problem
raised by sceptics, of how we can know whether we are dreaming or awake, is very hard
if not impossible to answer, exactly because we can take everything in waking life to be
equally part of a dream.
5
And when we are dreaming, we can and often do take
Logic of Dreams
17
everything in our dreams as waking reality. In other words, no part of dream life
establishes that it is different from waking reality, and vice-versa. If we want to pinpoint
what makes dreams different, then, we need to look at dream life and waking life with
respect to their sense of the whole of things. And this means that dreams do involve a
sense of the whole of things.
Even some of the kinds of logical impossibilities that are commonly taken to be
parts of dream life that distinguish it from waking reality, are, as I have argued, also
found in waking life. (Whether or not they express the same situations as those in waking
life is a separate issue, which I am only now in the process of discussing.) And Medard
Boss (1957), as I shall discuss in the final section, argues that all the apparent oddities of
dreams are equally present in waking life.
But even without these arguments, it is clear that dreams need not, and often do
not, contain any oddities of sense at all, and yet (at least as we think of them on waking)
would still be radically different from waking life. As a result, even if the presence of
illogic could establish that they are dreams, their dream character is independent of it.
There is still no particular part of dream life, then, that explains its difference from
waking life. The difference must lie in the sense it makes of things as a whole.
Perhaps this is a way of understanding Fechner’s description, made famous by
Freud, of dreams as occurring in a ‘different scene of action’ (Freud, 1953, p. 112). There
is no other setting or place beyond the settings or places in waking life: if there were, it
would be just another place included among the places in waking life. But dreams are
clearly not locatable in the waking world of places. And they deal with all the same
Logic of Dreams
18
events and entities. As a result, the setting of dreams can only be the same whole world
of settings and places as the waking world, experienced differently.
In principle, then, dreams must be understood to be another view or experience of
reality as a whole, or of a life as a whole.
But let me give a concrete illustration of this kind of sense of a whole, and of its
contradictory and non-sequitur logic, within an actual dream of my own. One of the
paradoxes inherent in the contradictory and non-sequitur character of a relation to the
whole of things is that one can engage with the whole even while still in many ways
being within it. As I argued in the previous section, even a perspective on a single “whole
of things” involves logical discontinuities with itself. Differently expressed, the sense of
the whole involves something like its being outside itself. That is, since it is outside itself,
its very inside is outside itself. Consequently, one can engage with the whole even while
still in many ways within it. Equally, one can engage with limited wholes within the
greater whole, each having its own integrity as a whole because it is logically
discontinuous in the relevant respects with the rest of the whole.
6
Here, the dream involves the case I have not discussed very much so far, the self’s
relation to itself as a whole. I dreamed that someone was sneering at me, being
confidently judgmental. I became angry in the dream, and successfully rejected the
appropriateness of his attitude. When I woke, I realized that I was angry with myself for a
recent failure that was a result of circumstances beyond my control, and that the dream
was expressing my feelings in the context of this situation.
It is not important for our purposes here whether or not this particular
interpretation is accurate. It is a kind of interpretation that is often made of dream images
Logic of Dreams
19
and events, and, on the assumption that there are valid ways of interpreting dreams, it is
therefore enough to illustrate the logic that typically belongs to them.
If the combination of the person who is judging and the person who is judged
expresses my being angry with myself, then each person expresses myself. And if it
expresses my self, it expresses my whole self. It is not, in this case, that part of myself is
angry with another part of myself, but that I am angry with my selfthat is, with my self
as a whole. Otherwise there is no reflexive, self-referring anger, but, instead, the different
case of one part of a person’s being angry with another part, or of one person’s being
angry with another, separate person. But where the dream figures express my actually
being angry with myself, they express one and the same thingmy self as a wholeas
two different things, two different ones of myself as a whole.
And, as I shall try to show, they do so rightly. They express a situation in which
one and the same thing really also is, in the same respects, two different things.
Now, it is certainly possible for a part of the self to be angry with other, different
parts of the self. One could, for example, be angry with oneself only for a specific issue,
and then be angry with oneself only for feeling that anger. In these cases there is no self-
including conflict to give rise to contradictions or incompatible identities. But these are
not the cases we are dealing with. It is still possible to be angry with oneself, and not just
with specific aspects of oneself. And my proposal is that it is those kinds of situation that
make sense of the contradictions and incompatible identities we find in dreams.
That, on this interpretation of the dream as being about anger with myself, it is
right to understand the dream figures as in some sense fully expressing the whole self in
each of the two selves, can also be seen by reflecting on the logic of the possible
Logic of Dreams
20
interactions between the two persons in the dream. If, for example, I had quailed in the
face of the judging person’s rejection, I would have been enacting the substance of that
very rejection. To give a parallel, if I condemn myself, and accept the validity of the
condemnation (for example, I feel badly because of it), both the condemnation and the
acceptance of it are the same act of condemnation. They are both my attitude, and they
are both the same attitude, and they are about the same subject, myself. They are, then,
simply different expressions of one and the same thing. In this case, since it is my act of
rejecting my same self, and equally my quailing in the face of my same self, my quailing
is my carrying out of that same rejection: my quailing is continuous with and expresses
that very same act of rejection.
Similarly, if I as the judged self had rejected or condemned the judging self as a
whole for condemning me (rather than just rejecting its condemnatory attitude), then my
rejected or condemned self would have been again, or still, rejecting or condemning
itself. It would have been carrying out the very activity of condemnation of itself that it
was reacting to in the “other” person. This activity would not just have been the same as
the other’s, but would have been one and the same activity.
This continuity between the different expressions of the same self as a whole
applies in waking life as well as in dreams: the same examples and arguments I have just
given apply equally in both contexts. But because of this real continuity between the
expressions of the self, there is a real contradictionagain in waking life as well as in
this kind of dreamwhen a self is in conflict with itself as a whole. For example, the
attitude of rejecting or condemning the worthiness of the self as a whole is itself included
in the self as a whole: that is, what it rejects includes itself, so that the attitude rejects its
Logic of Dreams
21
own worthiness to reject. And for the same reasons of self-inclusion or self-continuity, a
self that is in conflict with itself as a whole is rightly understood contradictorily as one
and the same thing that is also two different things. Each side of the conflict includes the
whole, and as a result leaves nothing out to be another “thing.” And yet, since it is a
conflict, there are two sides to it, each consisting in the one and only “thing.” Here, then,
we have logically necessarythat is, validcontradictions, of exactly the kind that
dreams express.
Now, in resolving the situation in which a self rejects itself, it cannot accept itself
as a whole if it rejects its self-rejection, since its self-rejecting attitude is part of itself.
Consequently, if it is to resolve the situation, it must shift to self-acceptance without
rejecting its self-rejection. What is more, since it is rejecting itself as a whole, it excludes
self-acceptance altogether. For both reasons, it must therefore shift to an understanding of
itself the possible sense of which its current understanding entirely excludes. And here
we have a logically necessary moment of non-sequitur, expressing the logic of real
situations in which we do in fact shift our attitudes towards ourselves as wholes (just as
our moods do in fact change).
There is another relevant side to this kind of resolution. In achieving that shift to
acceptance the self must accept all of itself: and this includes accepting its rejection of
itself (to achieve acceptance of itself). The non-sequitur, then, also involves another kind
of contradiction.
In fact a week later I had a dream in which I was appreciatively delighted by
someone’s silliness. Here, if this dream expressed self-acceptance (and, again, this is a
typical kind of interpretation, and in that way is enough to illustrate the point), the
Logic of Dreams
22
accepting self judged the accepted self as silly, a judgment that is a form of rejection, or
is at least in some sense negative. But I was delighted by that silliness. And, following
the sometimes contradictory logic of a self as a whole, since I was accepting myself, that
is, myself as a whole, which includes the attitudes of the accepting self, I was accepting
my act of negative judgment too. I was accepting myself together with my silliness and
my judging myself as silly.
At least part of the contradictory and non-sequitur logic of dreams, then, is a valid
expression, enactment, and re-working of our sense of ourselves as a whole, or, as the
first part of this section argued, of our sense of reality as a whole.
In the next section I shall explain why I use the language here of “enactment” and
“working.”
3. Dreams as Simultaneously Expression and Transformation
In this section, I shall try to show that if my proposal is right so far, it follows that
dreams are not only expressions or reflections of a sense of our lives or reality as a whole,
but are at the same time dynamic transformations of the sense of our lives or of our
relations to reality as a whole. In other words, they are a form of what we might call
existential practice.
As I argued at the end of the first section, if different understandings of reality as
a whole are possible, then, since the self that is doing the understanding is part of reality
as a whole, if this self understands reality in contradictory or otherwise conflicting ways
then it automatically understands itself, as a whole, in contradictory or otherwise
conflicting ways. (This is also and more obviously true, of course, if the understanding is
Logic of Dreams
23
of the self’s life as a whole, rather than of reality in general as a whole.) That is, its sense
of itself as a whole, and so it as a whole, is automatically caught up in the contradiction
or conflict. This in turn automatically means that this self is actively engaged, as a whole,
in challenging the sense or meaning of its own nature and in the struggle of that
challenge. In other words, this kind of understanding is in itself an active unsettling and
re-settling, a re-working, of the sense and nature of the self that is doing the
understanding. This re-working consists, for example, in either a transformation of the
self or in gaining a fresh relation to itself as its old self.
In fact, as I have argued, even a single awareness of things as a whole
automatically involves awareness of alternative views that it also entirely excludes, and
so engages the person, as a whole, in a contradiction, in an unsettling and re-working of
her/his sense of things. Differently put, registering our existing sense of things as a
particular sense of things, rather than as just a perception of how things simply are, is
already an unsettling of it. Even if we then come to accept our existing sense of things as
the right one again, we now hold it with a deeper perspective on it. There is
transformation of one’s standpoint even if its substantial content remains entirely
unchanged.
If dreams also involve this kind of understanding, they too are not simply passive
ways of seeing, of being a spectator of, these challenges to and transformations of our
sense of ourselves or of things as a whole. They are also active processes of establishing
or enactments of this re-working understanding and its logic; they are acts and processes
of unsettling and re-working the dreamer’s self as a whole or her/his relation to the sense
Logic of Dreams
24
of reality as a whole. That is, they are in themselves transformations of ourselves or of
our relations to the sense of reality as a whole.
If my proposal is right, then, dreams, whatever else they may be, are ways of
asking and dealing with what are sometimes called existential questions. And this means
that dreams are in themselves a practice of philosophy. They establish and express insight
into the sense that our lives as a whole have or existence as a whole has for us. And in
achieving that insight, they are in themselves an activity, a practice, of orienting,
situating, or re-situating ourselves in our relation to our lives or to existence as a whole.
As Alderman (1977) writes, ‘The dream . . . is one horizon through which the
dreamer comes more securelyor insecurelyinto the presence of his world. To
interpret a dream is to act as a Socratic midwife, assisting at the birth of the dream and at
the re-birth of the dreamer’s world’ (p. 118).
4. Partial and Indirect Support in Some Classical Theories of Dream Interpretation
That dreams have this kind of logical structure finds partial and sometimes
indirect support in some of the well-known theories of dream interpretation.
In Freud’s framework, the dream as we experience it, with its mixture of sense
and nonsense, consists in what he calls the manifest dream thoughts. But these are a
compromise between perfectly intelligible latent dream thoughts, and perfectly
intelligible waking thoughts that exclude or censor the latent ones (or that exclude the
entirely intelligible unconscious wishes that the latent thoughts express or with which
they engage). ‘Two separate functions may be distinguished . . . during the construction
of a dream: the production of the dream-thoughts, and their transformation into the
Logic of Dreams
25
content of the dream. The dream-thoughts are entirely rational . . . On the other hand, the.
. . product, the dream, has above all to evade the censorship’ (1953, pp. 649-650). The
censorship expresses what one’s waking thinking or attitude regards as unacceptable. The
irrationality of dreams, then, is the result of combining incompatible ways of making
sense of or evaluating the same things.
The conflicting ways of making sense in Freud’s framework, however, are not
necessarily ways of understanding reality or oneself as a whole. In the cases he discusses,
consciousness generally rejects a particular idea of piece of reality for reasons that
emerge from its particular experiences. This rejection of particular things is contingent. It
could have been otherwise: it is not part of or a result of the ultimate sense of things
that is, the sense of things as a wholeitself. As a result there is no logical necessity (that
is, no necessity following from the very sense of the ideas involved) to its incompatibility
with the latent thoughts or unconscious wishes, and so no logical necessity to the
resulting incoherence.
Freud’s model, then, only partly coincides with my proposal. But it does support
the view that the illogic of dreams is really a combination of two (or perhaps more)
logical sets of ideas, rather than simply having no connection with coherence at all. And
for the rest, the particular focus of the censorship, and Freud’s procedures and model for
working with it, are not incompatible with the framework I am suggesting. There is no
difficulty understanding the two types of conflict, global and particular, between modes
of thought, as simply different dimensions of dreams, neither interfering with the
occurrence of the other.
Logic of Dreams
26
Jung, by contrast, does see dreams as most deeply expressing and working
towards the coherence of the self as a whole. ‘The ego-conscious personality is only a
part of the whole man, and its life does not yet represent his total life’ (1974, p. 78).
Through the analysis of dreams there is a process of ‘assimilation of unconscious
contents’ that ‘finally reaches completion in the restoration of the total personality’ (p.
108).
On the other hand, he does not see dreams as ultimately structured as or
expressing a contradiction in the dreamer’s sense of things. It is true that for Jung the
total personality includes a balance of contradictory opposites, including a balance
between rationality and irrationality. Development of any one side of one’s personality
will necessarily be accompanied at another level by the development of its opposite
(1953, p. 71). But, first, these opposites are included in the same ‘total personality,’
making up its opposite poles. As a result, the contradiction is contained within a bigger
picture, and so is not a contradiction of or in the ultimate sense of things. Secondand,
really, another expression of the same issuethere is a balance between ‘rationality’ and
‘irrationality’ (p. 71), and not an ‘irrationality’ of ‘rationality’ itself. Finally, Jung’s idea
of balance here is not that of a balance between conflicting understandings of the whole
of things, but between different dimensions of what he takes to be the one and only
whole. As a result, while his approach involves the self as a whole in relation to reality as
a whole, it really does not properly raise the issue of the sense of the whole, but takes for
granted the exclusive validity of one particular construal of that sense, which it then
explores.
Logic of Dreams
27
His theory does, however, give a kind of indirect or implicit support to the view
that dreams express an ultimate contradiction in consciousness. There is a central element
of incoherence or contradiction in his theory, though as far as I know not recognised as
such by Jung or Jungians, that flows necessarily from the idea that dreams engage with a
sense of the self as a whole. That the self has to achieve the wholeness of itself means
that it is not yet itself. That is, it is not yet what it is: it does not coincide with itself. And
this is a contradiction. (I should clarify that in my view we can meaningfully speak of
achieving and of not yet having achieved “the whole of ourselves,” so that this is what I
have been arguing is a valid contradiction: but it is still a contradiction.)
This contradiction emerges in his theory in a variety of ways. For example, the
self communicates the achieved sense of its wholeness to itself, in the form of motifs like
the mandala image, and it does so prior to achieving that sense of its wholeness. Jung
describes these motifs as ‘“images of the goal,” as it were, which the psychic process,
being goal-directed, apparently sets up of its own accord, without any external stimulus’
(1974, p. 295). And in his framework the self must communicate with itself in this way,
so that it can know to move towards itself, and know that it is genuinely itself that it is
moving towards. In other words, it knows, and must know, where to go and what it is
before it (the “itself” it is communicating with) knows where to go and what it is.
Jung does point out that the self communicates this sense of itself to a part that is
artificially separated from it, the persona, or the fragment of ourselves that we falsely
identify with as our self. There is therefore no real contradiction: the whole
communicates to a part of itself, which need not coincide with or know everything in the
whole. But it is also Jung’s view that the whole is the real thing, from which the persona
Logic of Dreams
28
arises as only a fake separate entity, one that we take, ‘altogether wrongly, for something
individual’ (1953, p. 276). And this view is necessary to his framework, since the goal is
to work towards the wholeness of the parts: the self is the wholeness or self of the
persona. If this were not so, the persona could not find and would have no need to find its
own completion in the self. This means that the whole is necessarily the true reality of the
persona, which therefore necessarily has no genuinely separate reality. But, if the whole
is the only real thing, the contradiction re-emerges in a different way. The self itself has
produced a part of itself that is discontinuous with and not privy to itself. This is
equivalent to going about hiding something in a place one does not know about. (On the
contradictions in Jung and their re-emergence, see also Binswanger, 1963, p. 246.)
My own proposal might help to articulate and explore the validity of this
contradiction implicit in Jung’s framework. But it would also result in undermining the
current nature of Jungian dream therapy. The goal of that kind of therapy is to be guided
by the coherent sense of the self that awaits and unfolds. ‘The archetype is, so to speak,
an “eternal” presence,’ that ‘only appear[s] more and more distinctly and in increasingly
differentiated form’ (1974, p. 295). On the view that there is a real and central
contradiction in what the dreams express, however, that coherent sense of the self is
necessarily capable of being understood in contradictory ways. That is, that particular
sense of the self is necessarily only one among conflicting senses of the self as a whole,
none established in advance as more legitimate or more real than the others. The goal of
dream analysis would then be to hold in suspense and balance the contradictory senses of
self in order to find out, after the fact, which one turns out to be (or, perhaps better, turns
out to have been) the self’s commitment. The persona, for example, might need to be re-
Logic of Dreams
29
understood as possibly one of the alternative, legitimate senses of the self in its full
reality and in all its wholeness. And all the archetypal motifs might need to be re-
understood as signifying and enacting points of decision, or phases of decision, between
different and potentially equally legitimate understandings of oneself or of reality, rather
than as signposts to or communications from the pre-given, right understanding of
oneself or reality.
Differently expressed, where Jung takes individuation into selfhood to be the
solution to the problem of our relation to ourselves and to existence as a whole, I take it
to be a first, more or less complete, articulation of the problem. To put the kind of
contradiction I have discussed differently, in the process of settling our relation to
ourselves and to existence as a whole we stand outside the whole of which we are part. In
the case of our relation to ourselves, achieving our identity with a previously unknown
self would be the kind of thing that would allow us to recognise, by contrast, the
contradiction or incoherence in our previously not having achieved that identity, not
having been what we have always been. It would allow us to see that part of the nature of
being a self is that it is possible for us not to be what we are, and, for that matter, that in
some ways we also have been or are actually not what we are. This is an element of
incoherence that eludes settled understanding, and that only properly emerges in
establishing one’s selfhood, or, analogously, one’s sense of the whole of things.
Medard Boss, in his phenomenological framework for understanding dreams,
maintains as I do that dreams reflect and engage the deep structures that constitute the
sense of our life or our world as a whole. ‘[M]an when dreaming, no less than when
awake, always exists in his relationships with things and with people,’ relationships that
Logic of Dreams
30
‘go to make up his entire existence’ (1957, p. 122), and that express ‘the total and
original essence of things as such’ (p. 101).
Phenomenology aims to describe the structures of our experience as we live it,
without arbitrarily giving one dimension of it or any particular basis for explanation
greater weight or validity than another. For example, when we feel close to someone who
is physically far away, that person is both physically far and emotionally close, and
neither needs to be the truer or more basic state of affairs, or the one in terms of which
the other is explained. Consequently, if we dream, for instance, that a person who was far
away is suddenly next to us, this is not a distortion of the nature or truth of distance, but
an accurate expression of one dimension of its truth: we suddenly feel close to that person
(Boss, 1957, pp. 88-89).
Boss notes the varied kinds of sense that phenomenological description identifies
as structuring our world, and argues that our dream experiences consist in this variety of
sense structures, rather than in senselessness. And because these are the structures that
give the senses of our world, that is, that constitute its meanings, existential analysis, as it
occurs through dream interpretation, can lead to ‘a new and true relationship with the
essence of all things’ (p. 121).
On the other hand, Boss does not account for the contradictory and non-sequitur
features of dreams. In fact he denies that they have these features, since dreams share the
deepest sense-making structures of waking life. The logic of dreams only appears
mysterious, in his view, because these structures are ‘possibly hidden in daily life’ (p.
89), so that we may not initially recognize their sense when dreams force them on our
attention. But, as I have argued, the waking awareness of ‘the total and original essence
Logic of Dreams
31
of things as such,’ that he argues dreams share, is itself necessarily and legitimately
contradictory and discontinuous.
And while Boss does see dreams as expressing the structure of our sense of reality
as a whole, he only focuses on their expression of particular dimensions of that structure,
rather than on their expression of the sense of the whole of things simply and in its own
right. These two kinds of focus, however, are at least not incompatible. There is no
difficulty in understanding them as just giving insight into different, and in fact closely
related, dimensions of dreams.
Still, in this respect my proposal is closer to Ludwig Binswanger’s understanding
of the existential analysis of dreams. In his view, for example, ‘the dream . . . is nothing
other than a particular mode of human existence in general’ (1963, p. 227), and ‘our
whole existence moves within the meaning matrix’ of the dream (p. 223). Binswanger,
however, is like Boss in seeing no need to account for the contradictory character of
dreams. And while he does see dreams as involving conflict, it is a conflict between the
sense of things as a whole and a lack of that sense (p. 247), and not between alternative
senses of the whole of things. Consequently, his view only allows a limited variety of
ways for the details of dreams to be significant (as Boss also points out, in a different
connection [1957, pp. 82-83]). For Binswanger, there is only one sense of things as a
whole that dreams can express, and they only express it in the form of a contrast with the
lack of that kind of sense.
In conclusion, I propose that we need to acknowledge and account for the very
non-standard kind of logic found in dreams, and that we need to do so not simply to
Logic of Dreams
32
identify and work with what characterises dreams, but to identify and work with their
significance for waking reality.
Logic of Dreams
33
References
Alderman, H. (1977) The dreamer and the world, in: C. E. Scott, ed., On Dreaming: An
Encounter with Medard Boss. Chico, Ca.: Scholars Press.
Barris, J. (2003) Paradox and the Possibility of Knowledge: The Example of
Psychoanalysis. Selinsgrove, Pa.: Susquehanna University Press.
---. (2005) Oscar Wilde’s artificiality and the logic of genuine pluralism, in:
Contemporary Justice Review 8 (2): 193-209.
---. (2006) The problem of comparing different cultural or theoretical frameworks:
Davidson, Rorty, and the nature of truth, in: Method and Theory in the Study of Religion
18 (2): 124-143.
---. (2008) The formal structure of metaphysics and The Importance of Being Earnest, in:
Metaphilosophy 39 (4-5): 546-570.
Binswanger, L. (1963) Dream and existence, in: Being-in-the-World: Selected Papers of
Ludwig Binswanger. Trans. Jacob Needleman. Riverdale, NY: Baen Books.
Boss, M. (1957) The Analysis of Dreams. Trans. Arnold J. Pomerans. London: Rider.
Bremer, M. (2005) An Introduction to Paraconsistent Logics. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.
Cavallero, C. and Foulkes, D. Eds. (1993). Dreaming as Cognition. London: Harvester
Wheatsheaf.
Collingwood, R. G. (1940) An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1984) On the very idea of a conceptual scheme, in: Inquiries into Truth
and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Derrida, J. (1981) Positions. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Logic of Dreams
34
Dunlop, C. E. M. Ed. (1977) Philosophical Essays on Dreaming. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1993) Against Method. 3
rd
ed. London: Verso.
Freud, S. (1953) The Interpretation of Dreams. Trans. James Strachey. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Fromm, E. (1951) The Forgotten Language: An Introduction to the Understanding of
Dreams, Fairy Tales, and Myths. New York: Grove Press.
Gendlin, E. T. (1986) Let Your Body Interpret Your Dreams. Wilmette, Il.: Chiron
Publications.
Haack, S. (1978) Philosophy of Logics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hall, C. S. (1966) The Meaning of Dreams. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Hall, E. W. (1960) Philosophical Systems: A Categorial Analysis. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Johnstone, Jr., H. W. (1978) Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument: An
Outlook in Transition. University Park, Pa.: The Dialogue Press of Man and World.
Jung, C. G. (1953) Two Essays on Analytical Psychology. 2
nd
ed. Trans. R. F. C. Hull.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
---. (1974) Dreams. Trans. R. F. C. Hull. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2
nd
ed. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Lyotard, J.-F. (1988) The Differend: Phrases in Dispute. Trans. G. Van Den Abbeele.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Logic of Dreams
35
MacIntyre, A. C. (1988) Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press.
Malcolm, N. (1959) Dreaming. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Nagel, T. (1979) The absurd, in: Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Priest, G. (2001) An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
---. (2002) Beyond the Limits of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Priest, G., Beall, J. C., and Armour-Garb, B. Eds. (2004) The Law of Non-Contradiction:
New Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rorty, R. (1991) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers Volume 1.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
States, B. O. (1988) The Rhetoric of Dreams. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
---. (1993) Dreaming and Storytelling. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Taylor, C. (1985) Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2: Philosophy and the Human Sciences.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Valberg, J. J. (2007) Dream, Death, and the Self. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1961) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. D. F. Pears and B. F.
McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
---. (1979) Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. Trans. A. C. Miles. Atlantic Highlands,
NJ: Humanities Press.
Logic of Dreams
36
Notes
1
Hall (1966) comments, conversely, that if we dismissed dreams because they are
hallucinations, ‘we would have to dismiss all of the great works of art, of literature, and
of music, everything in fact that has been created out of the mind of man. For dreams,
too, are creative expressions of the human mind. They are the portals through which we
can view the workings of the mind’ (p. 9).
2
I am grateful to Steve de Wijze for drawing my attention to this intriguing book.
3
Fromm (1951) argues that dreams do operate with a logic that would be bizarre in
waking life, but that this logic is appropriate for the context of non-action that goes with
sleep. In that context, there are no consequences of my thoughts for what I could
realistically do to or with the things I think about, so that many kinds of constraints
crucial for waking thinking are irrelevant (p. 28). This view is more unambiguously in
conflict with my own proposal.
Very briefly in response: since the inactivity of sleep is registered within the
waking perspective, and the events of dreams mostly do not occur within that perspective
(except very ambiguously in lucid dreaming, and as remembered but no longer occurring
upon waking), it is not clear to me that the inactivity of sleep has any bearing on the logic
appropriate to the activity or otherwise that occurs within dreams.
4
For descriptions and accounts of the detailed structure of the partly nonsensical (or, as I
have described it here, contradictory and involving non-sequiturs) relation between
different perspectives on reality as a whole, or of the process of shifting from one to
another, see Barris (2003; 2005, especially p. 208; 2008).
Logic of Dreams
37
5
Valberg (2007) rejects this version of dream skepticism, but defends an alternative
version that still results in the view that dreams involve a different sense of the world as a
whole from that of waking life (pp. 105-108).
6
A distinct conceptual or semantic area constitutes a limited whole in this sense. The
concept constitutes or frames the whole of the sense of its content, of that semantic area.
This is evident in that grasping the concept means acquiring something new and unique,
and describing its content in terms of other concepts is to engage in conceptual confusion,
or category mistakes. The shift from understanding something in terms of one conceptual
order to understanding it in terms of another, then, shares the same violations of logical
sense as a shift from one comprehensive framework to another. (Further, both also share
the violations of sense belonging to category mistakes.) As a result, gaining a new
perspective on an element of one’s life, where that perspective involves acquiring a new
concept, involves a passage partly consisting in these violations of sense. I suggest that
these partly nonsensical transitions are often part of what happens in dreams, as in
waking life. See note 4 above for references to accounts of the detailed structure of these
kinds of passages.